You are on page 1of 17

390

391
IN PRAISE OF VAGUENESS
Diffuse Perception and Uncertain Thought
(2010)
A PERSONAL CONFESSION
Among the books that have had the most dccisiw imp<KI on my think-
ing since my student years in the late 1950s and early 1960s arc two
books hy Anton Ehrenzweig ( 1908- 1966), practically forgotten by
today's academia:' The Psychoanalysis of Artistic Vision a11d Heari11g:
An Introduction to a Theory of Unconscious Perceprion
2
(1953) and Tile
Hidden Order of Art ( 1970).
1
I was educated in the postwar positivist
and rationalist manner to sec and 1hink clearly and to seek precision
and cettainty. However, in Lhc mid 1970s, I found Ehrenzweig's psy-
choanalytical studies that explained the insislenl demand for preci-
sion in academic education and professional practices "as a defensive
secondary process in a psycho-a nalyt ic sense.''" Ehrcnzwcig argued
provocativdy and con vi nci ngly that creativity arises from vague, jux-
taposed, and di ffusel y inl erncring images, and unconscious perceptions
and processes, not liom focused percepts, precision, and logical cl ariry.
In his scholarly mission, .Ehrcnzweig quoles 1he decl aralion of rhe pio-
neering American psychologist and phil osopher Willi am James (1842-
1910) as the motto of his ftrst book: "I t is, in short, Lhe reinstatement
of Lhe vague t"o it"s proper pl ace in mcmallifc which I am so anxious to
press on the auen1ion."
5
This perspective shook the very foundations of my education and
newly acquired professional b e l i e f ~ Ehrenzweig's two books and his
essay entitled "From Conscious Planning to Unconscious Scanning"
6
gave my early interests in the mental foundalions of artistic phenomena
and the psychoanalytic approach Lo artistic creativity a new direcLion.
Evenrually this perspective opened up LO me the phenomenological
understanding of existential and artistic phenomena.
224
THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THE UNCONSCIOUS
In the 1>rcface to his f1rst book, Ehrenzwcig makes the thought-pro-
voking argument: An's substructure is shaped by deeply uncon-
scious proces:;cs and may display a complex organization that is
superi or to the logi cal struct ure of conscious thought."
7
For all the
strength and suggestiveness of rhis statement, I do not recall hav-
ing heard the concept of the unconsciousness even once during the
years of my education. Ehrenzweig suggests further that, "In order
to become aware of inarticulate forms [nrlistic expressions rhat seep -
into rhe work past conscious intentionality and control] we have
to adopt a mental attitude not dissimilar to that which the psycho-
analyst must adopt when deali ng with unconscious material, namely
some kind of diffuse attention.'"
8
The laycrcd nnd "polyphonic
structure of 1>rofound artworks, appreciat ed through "multi-dimen-
sional attemion," has also been pointed out by anists, such as Paul 392
Klee. Ehrenzweig cmphasizcs the signifi cance of this layeredness
and merging of motifs, and observes that it calls for a specifiC mode
of attention. "All artistic structure is cssemially 'polyphonic' : it
rvolves not in a single line of thought, but in several superimposed
mands at once. lienee creativity requires a diffuse, scattered kind of
attention that contradicts our normal logical habits of thinking.'"'
0
This requirement for diffuse attention co1H.:crns both the condition
of creative llcrccprion and thought. Ehrenzweig also uses rhe noti ons
of "allover strucrure and or-or structure" to describe layered and
vague anistic images.'
1
The overwhelming role of the unconscious realm over our con-
scious awareness is revealed by a theoretical calculation of rhe informa-
tion nansrnission capacities of our conscious and unconscious neural
systems in the brain. The abili ty of a nerve flhcr to transmit in formati on
is approximately 20 bits per second or, according tO some esti maks, a
maximum of 100 birs per second. As there arc some 10
15
nerve f1hers in
the brain, the total information conveying CaJ>acity of rhe brain is about
10'
7
bits pt>r second. Yet, we arc only capable of conveying a maximum
of an estimated 100 bits per second of conscious information coment.
Thus the total information transmission capacity of the brain is 10"
times its conscious capacity.'
2
THE DYNAMICS OF VISION
Dynamic vagueness and absence of focus arc also rhe conditions of
our normal system of visual perception, ;Jilhough we do not usually
acknowledge these qualiti es. Most of us who have normal eyesight
tend to believe that we see the world around us in relative focus at
225
390
Anton Ehrenzwei g, The Psychoanalysis of Artistic
Vision and Hearing: An Introduction to a n>eory
of Unconscious Perception. Sheldon Press, t967.
Cover.
391
Anton Ehrenzweig. The Hidden Order of Art.
Paladin. 1973. Cover.
392
Paul Klee. Room Perspective with lnhabi!illlts,
1921. wate1color and oil on paper mounted on
cardboard, 48.5 x 31.7 em. Klee Foundation.
Kunstmuseum. Bern.
all times. The fact is thai we see a blur. and only a tiny fraction of
the visual field at any time- about one-thousandth of the entire field
of vision- is seen distinctly. The f1eld outside of t his minute focused
center of vision turns increasingly vague and hazy towards the periph-
ery of the visual field. Focal vision covers ahout four degrees of 1he
approximate 1otal angle of 180 degrees. llowever, we are unaware of
this fundamen tal lack of accuracy because we constanlly scan the f1eld
of vision with movements of our eyes-that for the most part remain
unconscious and unnoti ced- to bri ng one part of the blurred periphery
at a time into the narrow beam of vision that is brought to a focal
pinpoint at thejo1;ea.
Experiments have revealed the surprising fact that the unconscious
eye movements are not merely aids to dear vision, bul :111 absolute pre-
requisite or vision altoget:her. When the subj ecl's guze is experimemally
forced to remain eomplel'ely f1xed on a stationary obj ect, the image of
the object disintegrales and keeps disa ppearing, and reappearing again
in distorted shapes and fragment s. ''S1aric vision docs not exist; there
is no seeing without exploring," argues Hungarian-born writer and
scholar Arthur Koestler ( 1905- 1983).'
1
We could think that our visually acquired image of the world is
nol ~ single picmre" at all, but a continuous plastic construct thai
keeps inlegr<lting singular percepts through memory. In fac1, visual per-
cepts are integra1ed and memorized as embodied haptic enlilies rather
than singulur reti nal pictures, "haptic snapshots," as it were. Finally,
the presence. permanence, and continuity of our experiential world is
established and maintained as an emhodied and haptic understanding
of "the flesh of the world" (a nolion of Mnurice Merl eau-Ponty) that
we share with our bodily existence. In fact, the sense of Self and 1he
world could be regarded as one of our sensory :systt:ms, and, indeed, rhe
Steineri an phil osophy theorizes twelve senses. one of which is the ego
sense, the sense of Self.'
5
This sense is crucial f'or our experience of the
world and ourselves as a l'empora l continuum and relative conslancy.
Recent neurological studies have revealed another surprising
dynamic characteristic of vi sion. Experiment s that measured the rela-
tive times that it takes to perceive color, form, and motion. show that
these three attributes of visual perception are not perceived at the same
lime. Color is perceived before form which is perceived before motion;
the difference in time bet\een the perception or color and motion is
60- 80 mill iseconds. This suggests that the different perceptual systems
are functionally special ized. '
6
The manner in which certain artists sepa-
rate color and form has 1hus a molivation in the faculties of our per-
ceptual mechanism.
226
Koestler s uggests u c<lutious analogy between visual scanning <Jnd
memal scanning, ''between the blurred, peripheral vision outside the
foc;1l beam, and the hazy, half- formed notions which accompany think-
ing on the fringes of consciousness.'''
7
"If one auempts to hold fast to a
mental image or conecpt-ro hold it immobile and isolated, in the focus
of awareness, it will disintegrate, like the stalk, visual image on the
fovea ... thinking is never a sharp, neat, linear process," Koestler argues
and distinguishes focal awareness from peripheral awareness.'
8
Even
pronouncing a familiar word repeatedly makes it gradually dissolve and
lose its meaning.
William James made a similar remark on t-he fundamental dyna-
mism and hi storicity of thought: ''Every def1nit e image in the mind is
steeped and dyed in the free water rhat nows around it. With it goes
the sense of its relations, nea r and remote, Lhc dying echo of whence it
came to us, the dawning sense of whither it is to lead. The significance,
the value of the image, is nil in th is halo or penumbra that surrounds
and escorts i r . ' ~
GESTALT-FREE PERCEPTION AND UNCONSCIOUS VISION
Gestalt lheory established the view of the arriculaling, or gestalt ten-
dency, of surface perception that selecrs and organizes images and their
clements in accordance with distinct formal properties, such as simplic-
ity, similarity. compactness, coherence, and closure. At the same time,
tl1c theory completely neglects the inarticulate form elements which
are not part of the gestalt. In constrast, Sigmund Freud has previ-
ously observed that form experiences arising from lower levels of U1e
mind-such as dream visions- tend to appear inarric:ul ate and chaotic
for the conscious mind, and arc thus diff1cull' or impossible to grasp
consciously. However, this undef1ned, forml ess. nnd involuntmily inter-
acting mcdlc:y of images, associati ons, <1nd recollections seems to be
exactly the necessary mental ground for crcati ve insight, as well as for
the richness and pl astici 1y of a rlis Lic expression-the "shock of li fe" and
the "sensation of bren lhing" LhaL Constantin Brancusi requires from a
profound WOrk Of <lrt,lO
Ehrenzweig dearly disLingu ishcs surface vision from unconscious
vision: "While surface vision is disjunctive, low level [unconscious pri-
mary level] vision is conjunctive and seriaL "
21
The superior efficiency
of unconscious vision in scanning the tolal f1eld has been con fumed by
experiments in subliminal vision, such as our capacity to grasp split-
second tachistoscopic exposures of consciously invisible, subliminal
images. ll1is capaciry is shrewdly deployed in methods of subliminal
advertising and other forms of mental conditioning.
227
393
A typical Rorschach figure.
394
Willem de Koomng. Atric, t949, oil, enamel, and
newspaper transfer on canvas. 157.2 x 205.7 em.
The Muriel Kallis Stemberg Newman Collection.
395
395
Jackson Pollock, Untitled, c. 1951, black and septa
ink with green gouache on mulberry paper, 62.5 x
95. 5 em. Museum of Modern Art, New York.
Ehrenzweig convincingly esl<lhlishes the priority of unconscious
perception and thinking in the cre<J ii ve process. He even suggests that,
"any act of creativeness in the human mind involves the temporary
paralysis of the (menta]] surface fu nctions and a longer or shorter
reactivat'ion of rnore archaic and less differentiated functions."
22
Thus,
instead of merely adding detail to the multiplicity of artistic form, the
inarticulare ingredients of d1e artistic language may well be its very
origin and essence. Ehrenzwcig ;.rgues for 1 he central importance or
'gestalt-free vision" [modes of vision that take place outside the gesralr
principles], ;md assumes that the capability of the superimposed per-
ception of simultaneous and juxtaposed images impli es that normal
focused perception has to be suppressed. In accordance with Henri
Bergson's views, he argues that, "all creative thinking begins wirh a
state of Ouid vision comparable to intuition from which ... later rational
ideas emerge. Ehrenzwcig concludes that, "all artisti c perception pos-
sesses a gestalt-free element," and this "gestalt-free diffuse vision ... is
the artistic way of seeing the world. "
24
In his studies in the psychology of mathematical thought, the
french mathematician Jacques Iladamard ( 1865-1963) proposes that
even in mathemarics the ultimate decision must be left to the uncon-
sciousness, as a clear visualization of the problem is usually impossible.
Hadamard, li ke his mathcmal ician predecessor Henri Poincare ( 1854
1912), stales categorically thai it is mandato1y to "cloud one's con-
sciousness in order to make the right

Hadamard makes an
inl eresting l'urther suggestion: "Greek geomcl ry lost its creative impetus
in Hellenistic times because of loo precise visualization. It produced
generations or clever computers and geometers, but no true geometri-
cians. Development in geometric t heory stopped altogethc:r."
26
By extension, I have made the worried suggestion that the absolute
mcuic precision of computerized design horh in architectural education
and practice has a negative impact on the innately shapeless and meas-
ureless flow of images and ideas in human imagination.
27
The method of "clouding" one's attention seems to have other
applications too. Richard Buckminster Fuller ( 1895- 1983), the American
engineering genius, once explained his extraordinary capacity to read a
book as a process of scanning, in which he saw the pages as meaning-
less grey surfaces witl1out details, unti l his unconsciousness spot ted a
piece of information that was new to him. Only at that moment did his
eyes focus on the text, but the text swiftly rerurncd to an unarticui<Jted
visual blur again as he had read I he passage that contained novel infor-
mation for his consciousness.
28
In Ehrenzweig's pioneering studies in the role of unconscious pcrccp-
228
tion in creativity, he shows how the two manners of perception
also apply to artistic he<Jring <Jnd music, the surface gestalt of visual
ilrts is represented by the musical melody which draws conscious attention
to itself and also represents the mcm01ized pattern of the musical piece.
Yet, music contains numerous inarticulate inflections of the melody, such
as vibrato, po1Tame11to, and rubaro. which are not articulate enough to be
expressed by musical notation, although they contribute signi ftcanlly to
the emotional impact of musical experience <lnd are part of its essential
stmcrure. They are left to l.he spontaneous execution of the pcrformcr.
29
THE LIVED WORLD AND UNFOCUSED VISION
Beyo nd specirtc realm ol'artbtic perception and creativity, an essen-
ti al prerequisite l'or the everyday experience of the enveloping spatial-
ity. interiority, and hapticity of the world is the del iberate suppress ion
of sharp, focused vision. We perceive and grasp overall and
structures only at the expense of precision and detail. Yet this important
observation has hardly emerged in the lht:orelicat discourse of archi-
tecture. Architectu ral theorizing and teaching continue to be interested
in focused vision, a strong gestalt, conscious intentionality, and the
perspectival understanding of space.
The historical development of representational techniques of space
arc closely tied with the history of architecntre itself. Represema1ional
techniques reveal d1c concurrent understanding of rhe essence of space;
conversely, modes of spatial representation guide the understanding of
spatial phenomena. The human system of sensory perception is a result
of evolutionary processes, determined and limited by our fundamental
primordi;JI exislenlial condition:;, whereas our intellect and imagination
are of engaging in conccr>tualizcd spatial characteristics beyond
the scope of direct scnsoty perception. Scientific constructs of mull i-
dirncnsional space that arc impossible to be visualized exempl i(y this
extraordinary menta l capacity.
Today's computer-generated renderings of architectun: appear
as if they would rake pl ace in a valueless and homogenous space, an
abstracted, maJhemali cn l, nnd world, rather than in exis-
tential and lived human reality. Jived human condition is always
an "impure" or '' di rty" mixture of a score of ineconcilable ingredients.
The lived world is beyond formal description because it is a multipli cit y
of perception and dream, observation and desire, unconscious processes
and conscious intentionalities, as well as aspects of past, present and
future. As the design process itself in mdays practice is
distanced from this "impure human reality, the existential life force of
architecrure tends 10 he weakened or enLi rdy lost.
229
396
396
Jost Amman. Portrait of Jamniczer in His Studio
with a Perspecttve Machine, ca. 1565. Bri1ish
Museum, London.
397
Georges Braque, Stili Life with Harp and Violin,
191 1, oil on canvas. 116 x 81 em. Kunst sammlung
Nordrhe-in-West lalen. Dusseldorf.
EMBODI ED EXPERIENCE OF SPACE
Sinct: its invention in [he Renaissance, the perspectival understanding
of space has emphasized and strengthened the architecture of vision.
By its very dt"r1ni1'i on, perspectival space turns us into outsiders and
observers; Lhe picture frame and vantage point push us outside the
realm of the obj ect or rocused perception. SimuiLaneous and hap-
tic space encloses and enrolds us in its embrace, making us insiders
and participants. In the relinal understanding of space we observe it,
whereas haptic space a shared and lived existential condi-
tion. The world and the pcrceivt:r are not separated and polarized as
they art: borh ingredients of the shared "flesh of the world."
The quest to liberate the eye from iLs perspectival Ft xation has
gradually brought nbout conceptions of mul ti -perspectival, simultane-
ous, and haptic space. This is the perceptual and psychological essence
of Impressionist, Cubist, and Abstract Expressionist painterly spaces, an
essence that pulls us inlo lhe painting and make us cxpcrknce space
as insiders in a fully cmboclil:d Visual space thus is trans-
fomlt:d into an embodied and cxislt:ntinl space. a qualitative space thai
is essentially n dialogue and exchange bel ween the space of the world
and the internal space of the perceiver's mental world. The experience
of intetiority and belonging is a merging of the outside and inside
worlds, the cvoccJ li on of a Weltinnenra.um-the inlerior experience
or the world (a bcautil'u l notion of Rainer Maria Rilkc).
10
"Th(' world
is wholly inside, and I am wholly outside myself," as Merleau-Pomy
states.
31
This is the unique, personal existential space that we occupy
in our lived experience. In an expnience of place, particularly that of
one's home, the external world and space become internalized: they
arc sensed as intrapersonal conditions, ratht:r lh<m ns external material
objects and perct:pls.
The heightened presence and reality of profound artworks derive
from the way they engage our perceptual and psychological mecha-
nisms and articulate the boundary beiween the viewer's experience of
sdr and the world. Works or arl hnve two simultaneous cxistcnces:
their existence as a material objecl or as a performance (music, theater,
dance), on t he one hand, and as an imaginative world of image and
ideal, on the other. The experiential reality of ari is always an imagina-
tive reality.
12
Gaston Bachelard, another touchstone author ror me, was an
authoritative philosopher n r science until his mid-career, when ht: {a me
to the conclusion that only a poetic approach, not scientific inquiry and
rn!."lhodology, can touch upon Lhe essence of lived human reality. Lived
reality always fuses observation, memory, and fantasy into the lived
230
existential experience. As Lhc consequence of this ;,impurity" or experi-
ence, it is beyond objective, scientific descripl ion, and approachable
only through poetic evocation. This is 1he innate structural vagueness
of human consciousness.
In architecture, a clear cli!Terentt:: exists between an architecture
rhat invires us to a multi-sensory and full embodied experience, on the
one hand, and that of cold and distant visuality, on the other. The works
or Frank Ll oyd Wright, Alvar Aalto, Louis Kahn, and more recently, of
Renzo Piano. Glenn Murcutt, Steven Holl. Peter Zumthor, Tod Williams
and Billie Tsicn, and Patricia and John Patkau, among those of numer-
ous other profound archi tecrs of today, are examples of a multi-sensmy
architecrure that draws us into ils sp<H.:e and reinforces our experience
of ourselves and rhe sense or the real.
Works of this root us in the complexities and mysteries of
perception and 1he real world, instead of confming us in an alien-
ating, construclcd artil'tciality. Again, artistic phenomena take place
simultaneously in two worlds: the realm of mauer and that of mental
imagery. In meaningful architectural works, even the imaginaty world
of architccrure is rooted in the realil y, malt'riality, and processes of
construction. This narralive and logic of construction and utility also
distinguishes archilecture from other art tonns that also utilize space.
Without the tension between its simultaneous material reality and its
imaginary mental suggcsLion, an architectural work remains shallow
and semimcntal.
THE DIMMING OF VISION AND SOFTENING OF BOUNDARIES
In heightened emotional states-ca ressing our loved ones, recalling a
strong memory, listening to deeply feli often close our eyes,
hoping to eliminate lhe and distancing sense of vision
alrogether. The spati al, rorrual, nncl color integration in a painring is
also often appreciated l1y dimming the sharpness of vision; the dynamic
composilinn;l l loL;l lily can only be appreciated by means of suppressing
detail.
Maximum color interaction in painting, in fact, calls for a weak
formal gestalt that obscures t he boundary of form, thus permitting an
unrestricted imeraction of the color f1elds. The i nleraction ben-veen ftg-
ure and ground in visual perceplion stands in inverse proportion ro the
strength of the ges/a/1 of the f1gure. The strong gestalt generates and
maimains a srrict perceptu<ll boundary, whereas liberated "gestall- free"
perception weakens the structuring impact of boundaries, rhus permit-
Ling form and color imcraction across boundary lines and between
ground and f1gure.
231
The vagueness and softness of boundary has yet another meaning
in creat ive thought, and that concerns Lhc experience of self. In Salman
Rushdie's 1990 essay written in memory of I Icrben Read, he observes
the softening of the boundary between the world and Lhc self that takes
place in the artistic experience: "Literature is made at the boundary
between self and the world, and during the creative acr this borderline
softens, rums penetrable and allows the world to flow into rhe arrist
and the artist flow into the world."
33
At the moment of creative fusion,
even the artist and architect's se-nse or self becomes momentarily fused
with the world and with the object of the creative efforr. In psychoana-
lytic li terat ure this experience of sameness with Lhe world is frequently
called an "ocea nic" fusion.
Creative activity and deep thinking s urely call for an unfocused,
undifferentiated, and subconscious mode of vision which is fused
with integrating tactile experi ences and embodied identification. The
creative vision mrns towards the ins ide, or in fact, it is directed om-
wards and inwards at the same lime. Deep thought takes place in a
t ransformed reality, a condition in whi ch Lhe existential priorities and
alarms are momentarily forgotten. The obj ect of the creat ive acr is not
only identified and observed by the eye and touch, it is inlrojected
(the psychoanalytic notion for the internalization of an object through
the interior of Lhe mouth at the earliest phases of infancy), and identi-
fied with one's own body and existential condition. In deep thought,
focused vision is blocked, and thoughts travel with an absent-minded
gaze accompanied by a momentary loss of surface control of tl1e exis-
tential situation. This is why deep thinking ca nnor rake place in the
unguarded outdoors, but usually occurs only in the protective embrace
of architecture, in the ~ c r d l e of the house," to usc a notion of Gaston
Bachclard.
3
'
1
Bachelard points out that architecture allows one to dream
in safety: "The chief benefit of the house [is that] the house shellers
daydreaming, the house protects the dreamer, the house allows one to
dream in peace. "
1
s
THE POOL OF VAGUENESS, PERIPHERAL VISION
Photographed architectural images are centrali zed and precise pictures
of focused perceptions. Yet. the quality ol' a lived architecrural real -
ity seems to depend fundamentally on the nature of peripheral vision,
and a deliberate suppression of sharpness thar enfolds the subject in
the space. PhoLOgraphed imagery, particul arly ones taken with wide
angle and deep focus, are alien to the fundamental faculties of vision.
Consequently, t11crc is an evident discrepancy between architecture as
experienced through photographs and a real lived experience, to the
232
degree that imposing images of arch itecture in photographs often prove
to be decisively less impressive when experienced live.
A forest context. a Japanese garden, a richly molded architectural
space, as well as an ornamented or decorated interior, provide ample 398
stimuli for peripheral vision. These settings weave us into the fabric
of the space, and center us in it in a haptic manner. As we move our
position in the space, even slightly, the unconsciously and peripherally
perceived details and distortions invigorate the experience of interiority
like an unconscious haptic massage. Rega rdless of the object- like exter-
nality, the very strictly bounded nature of our focused gaze, and the
cont inuous fl ow of individual fragmentary images, we sense the conti-
nuity and completeness of space around us as we sense an embrace. We 399
even sense the s pace behind our backs; we live in worlds thal surround
us, not in frontal rel'inal images, or mere perspectival pictures facing us.
The im1ate of perceprion is refl ected in the fact that our
has the surprising capacity Lo distinguish and identify light and color.
16
The preconscious perceptual realm which is experienced outside
the sphere of focused vision is existenti ally as important as the focused
image. In fact, there is medical evidence that peri pheral vision has a
higher priority in our perceptual and mental system. Ehrenzweig offers
the medical case of hemianopia as a proof of the priority of peripheral
vision in the psychological hierarchy of our mechanism of sight. In
this r<trt: illness, one half of the visual field becomes blind while the
other retains vision. In some cases, rhe field of v ision reorganizes itself
into a new completely new circular f1eld of vision with a new focus
of sharp vision in the center and an unfocused periphery zone. As the
new focus is formed, the reorgan ization necessarily implies that parts
of the former peripheral field of inaccurate vision acqui re visual acuity.
and more signi ficantly, the area of former focused vi sion gives up its
capacity for sharp vi sion as it trans forms into a part of the new unfo-
cused peripheral fi eld. Ehrenl.weig notes, "These case histories prove, if
proof is needed, t: hul. an overwhelming psychological need exists that
requires us to have the larger pa rl of 1he vis ual field in a vague medley
of images. J'
LOSS OF SPECIFICITY AND SENSE OF CONTINUITY
These observations of the existential signifiCance of unfocused periph-
eral vision suggest that one of the reasons why the architectural and
urban settings of our time often project a weak sense of spatiality, inte-
riority, and place, in comparison with the stronger emotional engage-
ment of historical and natural seuings, could be in their impoverished
stimulation of peripheral perception. In our modern world, we live in
233
398
Katsura ViUa and Garden, the Pine Lute pavilion.
399
Forest in Eastern Finland. Photo Seppo Hilpo.
a more focused world than was the case in earlier times. The fact Utat
the human sensory world has dramatically changed t hrough time has
been convincingly argued in literature. This rather newly ucquired pre-
cision-in an evolutionary perspective-could well have been supponed
by the central role of reading and pictures in our culture, as both call
lor a foc used and ftxed eye. The visual experience of the world clearly
has ga ined strength at the expense of auditory, haptic, and olfm:t01y
experiences, a message emphasized in Walter J. Ong's significant book
Orality and Literacy.
38
The current ly unchallenged hegemony or the eye m;ly be a fairly
recent conditiou, regardless of its philosophical grounding in Greek
thought and optics. In lucien rcbvres view: "The sixteenth centllly clid
nol sec fnst': iL heard and smell ed, it sniffed the air <Jnd caught o u n d ~
IL was only later that it seriously and actively became engaged in
geometry, focusing attention of the world of forms with Kepler ( 1571-
1630), and Desargues of Lyon ( 1593-1662). lr was then that vision was
unleashed in the world of science as it was in the world of physical
sensations, and the world of hcauty as well."
19
Unconscious peripheral perception transforms sharp and fragmen-
rnry retinal imngcs into vague spatial, embodied, and haptic experiences
lh<tl constitute our full existential and plastic experience and sense
of continuum. We live in a plastic and continuou:; world due 10 our
dynamic system of perception, awareness, and mt:mory that continues
to const ruct an entit y out of discontinuous fragments. PeripheraJ vision
integrate:; us with space, while focused vision makes us mere ocular
observers. In physical training, our physical skills are deliberately maxi-
mized for the purposes of the specifrc spCli'L, but the mental processes
of creative perception and thought are h;1rdly touched upon directly in
education. It is time to give vagueness iLS proper role in human con-
:;dousness as well as in artistic and architectural thought and education.
THE VIRTUE OF UNCERTAINTY
The issue of vagueness and indefmitencss is related with the notion of
uncertai nty. We are usually taught to seck certainty in our rh inkin!j and
work, but a self-assurance of the tccling of certainty tends to stop the
flow of sensitive creative exploration, and consequemly, tum counrer
-productive.
Joseph Brodsky poinrs out the value or insecurity and uncertai nty
for the creative endeavour. "I n the business of writing what one accu-
mulates is not expertise but uncertainties, "
40
the poet confesses, and
a true archi tect likewise ends up accumulating unccnainties. Brodsky
connects uncertainty with a sense of humility: "Poetry is a tremendous
234

school of insecurity and uncertainty ... !P]oetry- writing it as well as
reading it- wi ll teach you humility, and rather quickly at lhat. Especially
if you are holh writing and reading it."
41
This observation surely applies
to archit ecture as well, and is pmticul arly humbling if you arc both
maldng architectun and theorizing about it! But !he poet suggests thaT
these mental states Lhat are usually considered det rimental, can actually
be turned into a creative advantage: If this (uncertai nty or insccuriry]
does not destroy you, insecurity and unceJtai nty in the end become
your intimate friends and you almost attrihu1.e to them an intelligence
all their own," Brodsky advjses.
2
Uncertai nty and insecurity are espe-
cially receplivc states of mind that sensit ize it for crcutive perception
and insight As Brodsky clarifu:s, " ... When uncertainty is evoked, then
you sense bcaurys proximity. Uncertainty is simply a more ul crt state
than cerli tude, and Lhus it crt:ales a beLLcr lyrica l climate. "
43
l fully share the poet's views. In both wriling and drawing, the
tm and image need to be emancipated from a pre-conceived senst:
of purpose, goal, and path. When one is young and narrow-minded,
one wants lhe word and the line to concretize and prove a precon-
ceived ide;l, to give the idea nn instant and precise formulation and 400
shape. Through a growing capacity to tol erate uncertainty, vagueness,
lack of defmition, <Jnd precise rendering, as well as momentary illogic
and open-endedness, one grudually le<Jrns the skill of cooperating with
ones work and <JIIowing the work to make its suggestions and take iLs
own unexpected turns and moves. Instead of dictating a though1, the
creative process becomes an act of listening, collabomlion, di alogue,
and patient waiting. The object of one's work is insi de lhe space of the
mind while the mind is simul taneously projected out into the work;
the inside and oul.side space constinne a Moebius strip with one si ngle
surface. The work then becomes a jourm:y that may expose visions and
ideas that one has never before conceived, or whose existence has been
unknown prior to having been guided there by the work or one's own
hand and imagination, as well as one's combined attitude of hesitation
and curiosity, fused 1ogether by genuine un.certainty.
There is an inherent opposilion between Lhe defmit e and the indcti-
nile in art. An artistic phenomenon wants to escape dctinition until it
has reachl'd its self-sufficient existence. Tme creative fusion always
achieves more !han can he projected by any theory, and profound
design always <H.:hieves more than the brief or anyone parLicipat ing
in the process could amicipatc. This is why Milan Kundera suggests a
"wisdom of 1he novel'' and beli eves that all greut writ"ers listen to thi s
supra-individual wisdom. In his view great novels are always wiser
than d1eir writers.
m
400
Juhana Blomstedt. Far Away (1065). from lhe
Moebius Series. 2003, oil on canvas 90 x 60 em.
I began my essay with a personal conlcssion, and I am going to end
it with another. The modes of 'diffuse and "empty" or "unfo-
cused stare" have gradually also become my method of working, both
in design work and writing, and these modes have helped to emancipate
my perception and thought from the constraints of constricting focus
and Only after having learned to confrom my tasks as
open- ended explorations without any preconceived ideas of the entity,
or its essence and boundaries, have 1 felt capable of working in a man-
ner that can lead to new grounds of vision and thought.
Ever since the foolishly self-assured days of my youth (that cer-
tainly disguised genuine uncertai nty, narrowness of understanding, and
shortsightedness), my sense of uncertainty has grown constantly ro the
degree that it has become nearly intolerable. Every issue, every ques-
t ion, each th.ought is so det:ply embedded in Lhe mysteries of human
existence that often a satisfactory or clear response or rendi!ion seem
inconceivable. In a mental sense, I can say that instead or becom-
ing a professional, possessing immediate and assured responses, one
becomes increasingly more an amateur by age and experience. Bur
one also learns to tolerate uncerl<ti nty and vagueness, and even take
advantage of Lhesc mental stales tha[ are normally seen as psychic
weaknesses and threats to ones sense of security and self .

Whar is most human is not rarionalism but tlu? uncontrolled and
incomrollable continuous surge of creati11c radical imagination in and
through the flu.r of rcpresc11tarion, affects and desires.'
6
- Cornelius Castoriadis

236
2 Bachel ard, 'f'hc Poetics of SpiH'I', 6.
3 Louis Kahn, "form and Design," ( t960), Louis I. Kahu:
Writiugs, l.rtlures, t>dited by AJess:mdra
Larour (N<'w York: Rizzoli, 1991) 116.
4 Yi-Fu Tuan. /.am/sea pes of F<'ar (Minneapolis: University
of Minncsol:l Press, 1979), G.
'> Cited in Mohsen Mostafavi and David leatherbarrow,
Weatlu:riug, (Cambridge, Massachusells and london.
England: The Mrr Press. Cambridgl", 1993), 76.
6 Michel Foucault Discipliuc nud l'uuish: The Bini of till!
Prisou (New York: Vintage, 1979), 200.
7 .Juhani "The Architecture of Terror," Tile
Artllifecture of lmngr: E.ristculinl Spnt'e iu Ciuemn
[Helsinki: Rakennustieto Oy, 200t), t41-176.
8 Peter Wollen, 'i\rkkitchtuuri ja clokuva: paikat ja eptlpaikat'
(Architt"Cturc and cinema: )Jiates and Museum
of i"innish Architecture Mt"mlcrs Newsletter 4, 1996, I 5.
9 Paul Val t'y. unidentified source.
10 Paul Valery, "Eupalinos, or tht: architect," Dialo!fuCs,
transl aterl by William McCausland Stewart (New York:
Pantheon !looks, 1956). 86.
I I Richard Sennett, "The Glass Age. Harpers Mngaziue,
June 2004, 1 '1.
12 John Ruskin as quoted in Gary J. Coates, Erik Asmussen,
Archil'cct. [Srockholrn : Byggtllrl aget, 1997), 230.
11 Alvar Aal to, "The Human Factor," Al11ar /1alro in his Own
Wortls, edited hy Giirnn Schidt. (llelsinki: Otava, 1997),
280. (translation modired by the author).
14 Alvar /\alto, "Spt"t"ch at the llelsinki University of
Technology Centenni al Celebration," Schildt ed., A/tillY
Aalto In His Own Words, 265.
I 5 Peter Eisenmann, "En samtal med Carsten Juel-
Skala 12, 1987.
16 Cited in Anthony Vidler, 1lrc Ardritccwral U11t:llllll)'
(Cambridge, Massachusetts and London. England: The
MIT Press, 1999), 75-76.
I 7 Vidler, 'fir e Architcctllml l111C11111ry, 224.
18 frnntz Kafka, Lt:trcr to Fathl'r (Prague: Vita lis. 1999), 25.
19 Fern and LeJ.(cr, Functions of l'lrinli11g (London: Thames
and lludson, 1973), 132.
20 Rcyncr Banham, "A Home Is Not a House," ( I %!>)
Arclritc:ctml' Culture 1948- 19611, edited by Ockman
(New York: IUzzoli, 1993), 371-'3'/8.
21 Herbert Art aud Society (Ntw York: Schockcn
!looks, 1974).
TOWARDS A BIOMIMETIC ARCHITECTURE
Joseph Brodsky. "An Immodest Proposal,'' On 1111d
Reaso11 (New York: Farrdr, Strnus and Giroux, 1997), UJI.
2 Virruvius, Tlr<: Tt:ll Books 011 Arclritrcture. translated by
Morris Hicky Morgan (New York: Dover Publications,
New York, 1960), 36-39.
3 Doctor Nol d Egenter at Universi ty of Lausam1e i n
particular has studied the hui l ding behavi our of 3Jles in
northern Japan.
307
4 Dcrnanl Ruclofsky, Arl"ltitecturc Witlwut llrcllitects [ New
York: The Museum of Modern Art, l'l61).
5 The Reverend J.G. Wood, Hom<:s Witlroul Hauds (London:
longmans, Green and Co., 1865).
6 Karl von Frisch, Auimnl Arclrift:clflr<' [New York and
london: ll arcourL Drace .Jovanovich, 1')79).
'I Hansell, Mit hael H.: Animal Archicecttr rt> and Building
Behaviour. l.ongman, london (1971)
HanscU, Mil'had tL: Animal Construction Company.
Humcrian Museum and Art Gallery, Glasgow (1999)
6 Gaston BachdanJ. Tire Pocrics of Space (Roston: Beacon
1969).
9 Part! Ambroise. 1.1' li1rc des a11imtw.r er de
tlr 1'/wmm<:. Oeuvres <:ompli:trs, Vall//. (Paris: Editions J.
F. Malgaignc, t840), 74.
10 $l't' for instance: Klaus Bach ct aL under the direction of
J.G. l-lelnskc anrl r:rri Ouo, N<:ts i11 Na ture nud Tetlruics
(Stuttgart : lnstitutt for Lightweight Structures. 1975);
Bach, et al. under the dircctim1 of Eda Schaur,
Pncus in Nature n111i "l'echnics [Stulll{llrl: Institute for
Lightweight Stnlctures,J976): Frci Otto et al. Liglrlll't>iglrt
Structures i11 Arclrit<'Ciure tllld Nnturr (Jl 32). [Stunl(art:
Institute for lightweight Structurcs. l 963).
II Svcrrc fehn, personal communication with the author 1985.
I 2 Gaston R;Jcbel ard, Tile Pnrtks of Space [!lost on: Deacon
Press, 1969).
I 1 Julian Jaynes. T11c Origi11 of i11 tire
Brcakdormr of tire Bicameral Mind (Boston: Houghton
Mirmn Company, 1982).
14 As quoted i n .Jarrirrc M. Benyus, BiomirlliCiy. (New York:
Quill Willi am Murrow, t 997), 132.
t5 "Does even more limn a spid<:r tan: How to make something
useful of spider silk," Tire Ecouomisr, January 31. 2009, 81.
16 Edward 0. Wilson, Hioplrilia (Cambridge, Massachusetts
and London, Enghmd: Harvard University Press. 1984), 37.
17 Aalto, ''At and ' lh:bnology," inaugural lctnn1' as
memher oftl1e Fi nnish Academy, 0<1ohl' r 3, 1955. Alvur /\alto
111 /lis Own Words, ffiited and annotated by G6rnn Schildt
(I lclsinki: Otava Publishing Company, Ud., 1997). 174.
IN PRAISE OF VAGUENESS
Arrlon Ehrenzwdg was born and educated in Vienna.
lie was traint>d as a la'II'Jer hut also deeply interested in
modern an and music and as a pianist and
singer. After "Anschluss" with Germany. Ehrenzwcig
in England in 1938, abandoned his formal educa-
tion ;md made a tarcer as a lecturer in Art Education at
Goldsmith College, llrriversi ty of London.
2 Anton Ehrcnzweig, '17re Psydroa11alysis of Artistic Visiou
nnd Heariug: An lmroduciiou ro a 'JIIcory of U11conscious
(1953). [London: Sheldorr Press, 1975).
3 Anton Ehrcnzwcig, '11re Hidde11 Orrlu of Art [1970).
(i"rogmore, Sr AI hans: Pal adi n, 197'l).
Along with Rudolf Arnheim's An a111/ Visual Perceptiou.
and Herschel Chipp's 'nreories of Morlmr Art,
...
Ehrenzweigs second book is considered one of the three
classics of art psychology.
4 Ehrcnzweig, The Hidden Order of Arl, 59.
5 As quoted in Ehrenzweig, The Hidden Order f!( Arl, IlL
6 Anton Ehrenzweig, "Conscious Planning and
Scanning," Education in Vision. F.dited by
Gyor!{y Kepes (New York: George I:Jrazil ler, 1965), 27-49.
7 t: ltrenzweig, The Hidden Order of Art . VIII .
8 Ehrenzweig, The Hidden Ortler of Art, XL
9 See Paul Klee, Tltc Thinking Eye (london: Hutchinson,
1964).
10 l:hrenzweig. Tlte Hidden Order of Art, 14.
II Ehrenzweig, "Conscious Planning and Unconscious
Scanning," Education in Vision. Edited by Gyorgy Kepes
(New York: George Braziller, 1 'l65), 2.8, 30.
12 Matti Bergstrom, AiJJojenfysiologinsta jn psyykcslli [On
the Physiology of the llnl in and the Psyche], (Helsinki:
WSOY, 1979), 77- 78.
13 Arthur Koestler, [he Act of Crention (London: Hutchinson
Cl Co LTD, 1964), 158.
14 Merleau-Ponty describes the notion or ''the nesh of the
world" by stating, "My body is made of lhe same nesh as
the world ... this nesh of my body is shared by the world
1---1' and "The Resh of the world or my own is 1---1 a
texture that returns to itself and conrom1s to itself." The
notion initially derives from Merleau-Ponty's dialectical
of the intenwining or the world and the self. He
also speaks of the 'ontology or the nesh' as the ulti mate
conclusion of his phenomenology or perct'ption. This
ontology impl ies that is both wil'hin and without,
subjective and objective, S1Jiritual ;111d material.
Maurice IVIerleau-Ponty, "The lntt'rtwining-The Chiasm,"
in Tlte Visible and the lnvisibk, ed. Claude Lefort
(F.vanston: Northwestern University Press, 1992). 248, 146
IS Albert Socsman, Our Twelve Wcllspriltgs of rlre
Soul (Stroud, Glos: Hawthorne, t998).
16 Semir Zeki, lmrer Vision: An rplornrio11 of Arl and rite
Brai11 (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1999), 66.
17 Koestler, The Act of 158.
18 Koestler, The Act of Creatio11, 180.
19 William James, Principles ofPsycllology ( 1890). (Camhridge,
Massru.:husetts: Hatvard University Press, 1903).
20 As quoted in Eric Shanes, Constanti n Bnwcusi (New
York: Abbevi ll e Press, 1989), 67.
2t Ebrenzweig, Tlte 1/iddett Order of Arl, 46.
22 Ebrenzweig. Tlte Psychoanalysis of Artislir Vision, 18.
23 Ehrenzweig. Tlte Psychoanalysis of Arlislic Vision. 35.
24 Ehrenzweig. Tlte Psychoanalysis of Artistic Vision. 36.
25 As quoted in Ehrcnzweig, Tire Hidtlt'n Ordrr of Art, 59
26 As quoted in Eluenzwcig, Tire Ordrr of Arr, 58.
27 Juhani l'allasmaa, The Tit inking 1/and: F..ristcntial ar1d
Emllodicd Wisdom i11 Arcl!ilet'lure (Lontlon: John Wiley
ft Sons. 2009), 95-100.
20 Conversation with the author in New Delhi, India,
October 1969.
29 l!hrenzwcig, Tile Hidden Order of Art, 43.
JO "Lukijallc," [To the Keader) Rainer Mnrin Rilkc, Hi/jainen
raitccn sisin: kirjeitii mwsi/ra 1900-1926 [The Silem
lnnennost core or art; letters 1900- 1926] J;dited by Liisa
Enwald (Helsinki: TAl-tens, 199'1). 8.
31 Mauri ce Merleau-Ponty, Pltmomcnology of
Perception, Translated by Colin Smith (London: Routledge
and Kcgan Paul, 1962), 407.
32 For lhc reali ty of att, sec eg. Jean-Paul
Sarlrc, ?'Ire Psychnlngy of Imagination (Secausus, New
Jersey: The Citadel Press, 1948); Jean-Paul Sa nrc, Tile
Imaginary. (London New York, Routledge, 2004),
and; Kichard Tlte Wake of Jmagi1tatioll (london:
Routledge, 19AA).
33 Salman Rushdie. "Eiko mikaan ole pyhaii?" [Isn't
Anything Sacred?] Pamasso I (1996): 8.
34 Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space (Bos1on: Beacon
Press, 1%9). 7.
35 Barhelard, Tile Poetics of Space, 6.
J6 .fames Turrell, "Plato's Cave and ligh1 Within", lilcplwnt
(I lid nom:rjly: permanence a.ml cltallf}e ill (//'i'hil'cctorc,
Etlitcd by l'vlikko Heikkinen (Jyviiskylii: Alvar A alto
rounclation, 2003), 144.
7 Ehrenzweig, The Hidden Order of Art, 284.
J8 Walter J. Ong, Orality am/ Literacy- Tltc:
ofrlrc World (london and New York: Routledge, 1991).
39 As quoted in Man in Jay, Dowucast Eyes - Tile:
De1rigration of Vision in Twentietlr Century Frc:nclr
Tllougltt (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University or
Cali fornia Press, 1994), 34.
40 Joseph Brodsky, "Less Than One", Less Titan One (New
York : 1-'flrrar, Straus (t Gi roux 1998), 17.
41 Juseph ll roclsky, On Grief and Rea sort (New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux., 1 997), 473-4.
42 Brodsky, On Grief and Reason, 473.
43 Brodsky, Tltnn One, 340.
44 Milan Kundera. Romaanin taide [The Art or the Novell.
(H<>lsinki: Werner Soderstrom Ltd., 1986). 165.
45 Ehrenzwcig, conscious Planning and Unconscious
Scanning," Educarion in Vision. by Gyorgy Kepes
(New York: George Braziller, 1965), 32. 34.
46 As quoted in Arnold H. Modell, lmanination a111i rite
Menninafill Brain (Cambridge, Massarhusetis and London,
r.ngland: The MlT Press, 2006, lil'le page.
ON ATMOSPHERE
Jain McGilchrisr, Tlte Masrer and His Emissary: The
Divideti/Jrain and tltc Making of /Ire Wc:s1em World (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 2009), 184.
2 Pewr Zunnhor, Atmospheres - Arclrileclllml i:lwirosmrents
- Surrouuding Objects (Bascl: Birkhauser, 2006), 13.
J .John Dewey, Art As Experic11ce (1934) as IIUOi ed in Mark
Johnson, Tile Meaning of tlte Body: Aeslllelil's <!( Human
llndersta/11/iug (Chicago: The University uf Chil'ilgn Pr<"ss,
2007), 75.
4 John Dewey, Art As E.rperience (New Ynrk: The Berkley
Publishing Group, t980), 74.
308
-

You might also like