You are on page 1of 21

DAVID KENNEDY

THE NINE-YEAR-OLD PHILOSOPHER AND THE HERMENEUTICS OF


SELF-UNDERSTANDING

Published in Studies in Philosophy for Children: Pixie. A.M. Sharp & R. F. Reed,
Eds. , 195-208. Madrid: Ediciones de la Torre, 1996. All rights reserved.

As the heroine of a philosophical novel, Pixie is a master at posing questions


with major ontological and epistemological implications. Among these are
questions about the self and its relations, both internal and external. These
questions are appropriate for philosophers of any age, but particularly for the nine-
year old philosopher, whose self-understanding, while universally human, is also
profoundly influenced by her position in the life cycle.1 Pixie's is the characteristic
self-understanding of late-early or early- middle childhood, a life cycle moment
characterized by dynamic emergence and continual, often rapid and breathtaking
transformation. Pixie is quixotic, explosive, deeply curious, garrulous, crude,
sophisticated, careful, impulsive, egocentric, compassionate, enthusiastic,
extroverted, sassy, loving, confused, bursting with questions. She problematizes
everything. What she shows forth paradigmatically in her endless talk to herself and
to her readers is the self in search of itself. This search goes on all our lives, but
Pixie lives it with freshness and an intensity which is exemplary. This search,
because it is interpretive, dialogical, and dialectical, is a hermeneutic activity par
excellence.
Hermeneutics begins with the situation of a break, a division in an original
unity, whereby something previously understandable, unquestioned even, has
become strange. This break initiates the hermeneutic process, which seeks to re-
establish, through dialogue and a "fusion of horizons" with the object, a new, more
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 2

inclusive, more conscious understanding.2 Philosophy is by definition


hermeneutical because it originates with this rupture in understanding; it turns on
itself in the form of a question. It could also be argued that philosophy is one of the
most characteristic activities of the human self, because genetically, the self
originates as the result of a breech with a prior unity,3 and its development consists
in its attempts to reappropriate that unity on a higher level, through a dialogue which
happens both within the self and with other selves, who also form aspects of the self,
even if they are experienced as "outside." Any narrative about the self and its
development over time can be understood to document this movement of breech,
dialogue, and reappropriation. Before tracing it specifically in Pixie's narrative, I
want to explore her exemplification of the philosophical self, i.e. the self in its very
operative structure as break in understanding, as self-problematization.
Self as doubled
The narrative style of Pixie lends itself nicely to the particular drama of the
self in hermeneutic process with itself. For one thing, it is written in the first person,
and Pixie's "I" is talking to itself as much as to the reader. This fact points
immediately to a chief characteristic of the self--its reflexivity, or doubleness. This
aspect of being doubled is the unique property of the human self: a form of
consciousness which can take the point of view of an other towards itself.
If one definition of the human self is that it is doubled, then it is in a
permanent state of imbalance, of being at one remove from itself. This sense of
displacement sometimes has the feel of a temporary condition--of a tension of
consciousness which inexorably seeks its resolution through ecstacy, sleep, or
death--but it actually seems to be permanent. So our philosophical heroine is Pixie,
but Pixie is not her real name, for how could one name capture this doubled
identity? Because it seeks a unity which it feels is a sort of home, the self, like
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 3

Pixie, is in continual pursuit of itself, in a continual process of figuring itself out.


Success in this process, which is the project of the self in its hermeneutic aspect,
would amount to finding out--or giving itself (which is it?)--its real name.4
The self is a mystery to itself. Who is the real mystery creature in Pixie but
Pixie herself? In G.H. Mead's and Sartre's terms,5 the "I," the "pour-soi," the
eternally present upsurge of consciousness, intentionality, is continually in search of
the "me," the "en-soi," the self as a finalized, determined, secure entity, i.e. as object.
The self is a continual aspirant to becoming a perfect other, a whole which can
behold itself as if it were outside itself, which psycho-logically is a sort of tragi-
comic joke. Although it can watch itself in the mirror, it will never be able to see
inside and outside at the same time; it will never be able to comprehend its own
doubleness as one. The self is also ultimately unknowable to itself because,
although the upsurge of the "I" feels like it comes from beyond or outside of time,6
the "me" is in time. To fix the "me" in one aspect would actually be to kill it, to turn
it to stone. The self is, simply because it is a continual upsurge of the newness of
personal identity, incapable of fixing and systematizing its inherently ambiguous
internal (and external) relationships, except in inauthentic forms and images.
Self as story
As a phenomenon of doubleness, the self is a conversation--an internal
conversation, which is what thinking is. So human selfhood is by definition
characterized as thought. Even Brian, who has fallen silent, never stops talking, and
that conversation manifests as who he is. So each self is characterized by the
conversation it is having with itself about itself. The fact that the self is a
conversation also means that the self is language, for any conversation implies
language. The conversation is infinite, as the self is engaged in an infinite process
of becoming, an endless emergence.
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 4

What does the self tell itself in this infinite conversation? Pixie shows us that
the self is telling itself--and us, the self's other interlocutor--a story about itself. The
self may be characterized as a narrator in endless search of a story that makes sense.
This search is in fact what characterizes the philosophical turn of the self, and it is
what makes Pixie philosophical. The non-philosophical self presumes to identify
completely with the story it has been given by others, to be already determined, and
therefore unproblematic. We discover this aspect of the self in Pixie's sister,
Miranda, who is non-reflective and quite content, thank you! To Pixie, the
philosopher, this presumption of a non-problematic self-understanding is a great
scandal. But Pixie must also recognize that Miranda is part of her own selfhood, as
are all those with whom she shares world. I will return to Pixie's understanding of
herself as part of a larger self composed of others later in this paper.
The story Pixie seeks to construct is a myth of self. The self's story can only
be expressed mythically, because it is a creature both found and made, a fantastic
closure always in the making. Perhaps this has to do with its felt self-understanding
as timeless and disembodied, a non-temporal presence to itself. It is experienced as
an ever present emergence into the now of the moment from some place beyond
itself, perhaps that nothing which Pixie evokes as she questions space and time. It
weaves stories of the past and the future in order to create and to name itself in time,
to establish a sense of continuity, to locate and identify itself within the world.
Confronted with its own sense of being thrown into the world from nowhere, the
self is a self-maker, the teller of its own story, woven from the world in which it
finds itself, laced through with the drama of its own drives--loving, destructive, self-
destructive, egocentric, compassionate, fragmented, unified, digressive, deeply and
mysteriously goal-directed. Only the story, the narrative, provides the necessary
context for the self making sense to itself. In the story the self remembers a history,
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 5

and works continually to harmonize its present circumstances and behavior with that
history, and with the sorts of possible futures that history and the present imply.7
Every self-story at least implies a beginning, and so is a search for its own
origins. Those origins are non-intuitive to the self, which perceives itself to have
"always" been there, yet which obviously has not, and is not perceived that way by
others, and is well aware of that too. Because self-awareness transcends any theory
of its own origins, even if that theory can be empirically verified, any account of its
origins must be mythic, for myth is the language of the non-temporal and
transcendent. But unlike the collective myths which tell the story for traditional
societies, the myth of the modern individual is continually in revision. As Pixie's
final story plays with the great Western myths of origin, and as her classmates, in
telling her story, play with it and change it once again--in the same way there is no
final, original story.
The self can never know itself through its stories, because its stories are not it,
but just about it; the self can never get outside its own ground to tell about itself. On
the other hand, the self can only know itself through its stories, because it is
essentially unsayable and unknowable in any positive sense, and can only know
itself as object at one remove, in its products, through its representation in its own
narrative process, in its dreams, in its memories, in its continuous chatter to itself, in
what others tell it about itself. Thus the self is an analogical construct, which seeks
itself through mirroring and comparison, through themes and styles of self-
construction provided by its biological, cultural, psychodynamic, and interpersonal
context. So Pixie's preoccupation with relationships is analogous to her
preoccupation with herself. The self, like Mr. Mulligan's "mind," is its
relationships, both within itself and within the world of others. It is a series of
comparisons with others, distinctions and connections between aspects of oneself,
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 6

and between oneself and others, which results in a never ending narrative,
constantly being revised, which is also an approximation of the "real" self, the self
which is utterly sure of its own existence, but can never ultimately attain itself with
any kind of final certainty.
Like "space," like "mammal," "It's just a word. . . People talk about it as if it
were something, but it's really nothing." Like the light when you turn off the switch,
where does the "self" go when you go to sleep? Or when I point to myself and say
"me," what do I mean? Just as Pixie mistakes the word mammal for a member of
the class of mammals, so the self in search of itself is liable to category mistakes and
part-whole confusions. What category does the self, which senses itself as outside
time but can never approach itself except in time, belong to? Can we draw a Venn
diagram of the "I"-"Me" relationship? The process of self-knowledge is in itself a
crisis classification, in that the whole and the parts are never in a final, closed
relation. In our search for self, we are continually taking parts for wholes--at times,
given the hologrammatic nature of the implicate order, rightly. Indeed, the whole is
unavailable, for if the self is only its relationships, then there is no whole. What final
category, in the multiple, ambiguous, infinite digression of the self's narrative,
provides a locus for the concept? Like Pixie's cat playing with its tail, self is
shapeshifter, trickster, constantly losing the distinction between its own shape and
the shape of the world it is a part of, or other selves--constantly drawing false
distinctions, whether within itself or between itself and the world, denying the
extent to which the world provides it with the only definition it has.
Self and body
Pixie as disembodied self, res cogitans on the nine-year-old philosopher's
continual holiday, has a fine time with her relationship with her body. Her foot goes
to sleep and she mistakes it for Miranda's; she lifts up her sleeping mother's eyelids,
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 7

and asks "Are you in there?"; she becomes temporarily convinced that she has two
left feet. Is the self the body? Is the self in the body? Does the self have the body,
i.e. is the body in the self? Is the self-body relationship a unity that transcends both
terms? Is it a part-whole relationship or an identity relationship? Does the self
change as the body changes--as it gets bigger, and no longer able to sit on its
mother's lap, for example? The self is unimaginable apart from a body, but body
can not only be imagined, but experienced, apart from self, as in a sleeping limb, or
the sleeping body of another, or the bodies of animals. The mind-body separation is
in fact the basis of the sense of self, and emerges at around 18 months, when
children first recognize themselves in the mirror, and are able to regard themselves
from the point of view of an other. So the self cannot seem to escape having, being,
or being had by a body, and yet its experience of itself is as something separated and
transcending its body.
Self and its relationships with others
But it is not just the relationship with her body which is ambiguous. Pixie
also finds herself to be spread through all her relationships. It is the ontological
paradox of the self that it experiences part-whole confusion with other selves. This
is true even in a highly atomized, individualistic society like the modern Euro-
American. Isabel and Pixie, walking down the hall, pausing at the top of the stairs
and hugging, are paired and synchronized in a way which shows them to inhabit, in
some way, the same psychological space. Isabel is an essential element of Pixie's
self definition, in the often uncanny mirror of the alter ego. She says of her, "She's
just like me in all the things I like about myself. And she's different from me in all
the things I don't like about myself." Inherently isolated, inherently social, finding
itself simultaneously completely separated from, and an aspect of, the world in
which it is placed, only another self can clarify the self for itself, even if the very
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 8

necessity of that clarification compromises the self's experience of pure identity and
self-unity. But as Brian's meeting with the giraffe implies, the self is only completed
in its individuality in meeting with an other. The I-Thou completes the circuit of
relation in which the self understands itself, and is free, in the way in which Brian is
freed to speak through his meeting with an other.
Miranda is also an essential element in Pixie's self definition, but she
represents, as siblings archetypically do, the menace of the other to the self, the one
who is so much like oneself that she threatens the self with a sense of contingency
which leads to a loss of identity. In her relations with Miranda, Pixie faces the self's
opacity to, and objectification by, the other with whom one does not choose to be in
relation, who does not necessarily share one's project. So the relationship with
Miranda, whose name means "looking," and evokes the word "mirror," is the
relationship of the stare. In the Sartrean cosmos of self and other, the stare is what
turns self into an object, what transfixes self in itness, in the "en-soi." It is the mark
of domination, of victimization, and of the master slave relationship. It is the dark
underside of the self and its relations. Miranda is the alter ego who, in
contradistinction to Isabel, is "just like me in all the things I don't like about myself,
and different from me in all the things I like about myself." That this is the case
makes of Pixie and Miranda no less a unity than are Pixie and Isabel. This is
expressed in Pixie's physical confusion with Miranda, with whom she shares a bed,
and a virus, possibly a headache, a leg when hers goes to sleep, ideas when
Miranda's uses hers to prove her wrong, and with whom she is even more mixed up
in family resemblances: Pixie has her father's mouth and her mother's eyes, Miranda
has her father's eyes and her mother's mouth. This is indeed the world of mirrors, of
repetition, and the threat to self at the prospect it is simply a generic self, a duplicate,
in fierce competition with other duplicates for the same place in the sun.
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 9

Beyond its involvement in these individual alter relationships, the self is also
inextricably tangled up in the community of which it forms, necessarily, a part. It
internalizes aspects of all the selves in which it is in social, cognitive, or spiritual
process. The community, in particular the community of inquiry, which is
community in more concentrated, more focused form, may be understood as one
large self, which through the interaction of the selves within it, is emerging and
clarifying itself, becoming more and more "like" itself, in its tortuous approach
toward that horizon of understanding which, as Robert Corrington has so well
described it, "lures us beyond ourselves into larger stretches of experience and
world encounter."8 Each member of the community of inquiry is a sort of hologram
of the larger self of the community, in that it is both a separate piece and an
internalization of the whole. Within the community, each member occupies a unique
perspective, which by definition is just the perspective which is lacking in all the
other selves. Through the operation of the community of inquiry, each member
internalizes all the other perspectives. Each other perspective represents a part of me
which is present and functioning when the community of inquiry is functioning.
When the community is successful, it also protects, nurtures, and brings to
expression my own identity, because my perspective is necessary to the whole.
Because of its part-whole structure, the community of inquiry is potentially a
therapeutic community in relationship to the self, as is illustrated in the case of
Brian. Brian represents that aspect of the self which has the potential of giving up
talking. The text does not give information on why--whether Brian's silence
represents the wounded self, the self which has broken with nature, or the self in
protest and refusal against the absurd.9 What we do sense strongly from the text is
that Brian finally resumes talking because the community of inquiry has given him a
voice--it has affirmed his perspective as unique and necessary in the process of self-
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 10

correction and emergence which characterizes the community, and in that same
process, healed him.
The part-whole relationship within the community of inquiry may be
characterized as a hermeneutic circle both epistemologically and in terms of the
ontology of the self. In the hermeneutic "circle of interpretation," there is a
dialectical interaction between the whole and the parts, a circular relationship, in
which each gives the other meaning. This involves, as Richard Palmer has pointed
out, a logical contradiction, for the whole receives its definition from the parts, and
yet the parts can only be understood in reference to the whole. The contradiction is
resolved on the level of meaning, in which the meaning of the whole is a "sense"
derived from the meaning of individual parts, yet not identifiable as the mere sum of
those parts. It is meaning which understanding grasps in the essential reciprocal
interaction between the whole and the parts.10 So the self understands its own
meaning through its interaction with the larger sense which emerges in the evolution
of the community of inquiry. As Pixie's story is transformed in being taken up by
the group, so the self's story, as it interacts with the community of selves, is
transformed in that interaction. In allowing itself to be affected and changed by that
interaction, the individual self undergoes a process of universalization, which is also
the coming into a kind of objectivity, although that objectivity is, like the self,
emergent and therefore never attained once and for all. And we must admit that, just
as the self remains fundamentally a mystery to itself, in that it is never fully
articulated or expressed, nor is there some ultimate point from outside itself from
which to view it; so the community, because it also is an emergent narrative, a story
it is telling itself which is never finished and which is continually self-correcting in
ways which are fundamentally unpredictable to each member of the community--so
the community is also a mystery to itself.11 Both the self and the community are
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 11

being taken "where the argument leads," in an evolutionary, self-correcting path, a


drive towards a horizonal unity which is both always present in potentia, and
infinitely receeding.
Self and freedom
Pixie as paradigm of the structure of self-understanding also leads us to
reflect on issues of freedom, rules, and individual agency. The self's lived
experience of itself is as ageless, beyond the possibility of death (which only
happens to others), disembodied, self-naming, and self-creating. The origins of the
self are lost to itself in infinite regress, and the present of the self is an unfolding
narrative, an infinite process of becoming which appears to offer complete freedom
of the next move. As res cogitans, "pure mind," it experiences itself as potentially
omniscient, at least in regards to its objects--Pixie lying in bed and thinking about
what's happening "all over town" is a play on this felt sense. Above all, the
intentional structure of the self is a motion of transcendence, or, as Heidegger put it,
an ekstasis, a standing "out into the openness of being."12 For all these reasons the
self is emblematic of the possibility of absolute freedom--as Pixie says, "Free free
free! Everything's possible!" Yet the self's lived experience is also characterized by
a sense of radical contingency and limitation, both by others and by oneself, and by
the experience so well described by St. Paul: "What I would, that I do not; and what
I would not, that I do."13 So Pixie has a "tantrum" when told she can't stay up late,
i.e. she loses control of herself. Then, at supper, she loses control of the three
concepts--analogy, simile, and metaphor--which she thinks she has understood quite
well.
In fact the self is ruled by its compositeness, its relative fragmentation, and by
the same patterns of cause and effect which are found in the res extensa. The self is
not "free free free": it lives in a space of eternal conflict between its own urge for
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 12

self-expression, gratification, and even transgression of limits, and its


responsibilities to others. Typically the self enters every new situation under its
characterstic sign of personal transcendence and unlimited freedom, only to discover
that each situation builds towards increased and more complex levels of mutual
responsibility, and inherent demands for self-restraint. Ultimately, freedom turns out
to be, not release from situation, or the experience of the absence of boundaries, but
meeting, connection. As Buber expresses it, "the free human being encounters fate
as the counter-image of his freedom. It is not his limit but his completion; freedom
and fate embrace each other to form meaning." And he contrasts this freedom to
what he calls "caprice." "Free is the man that wills without caprice. . . He must
sacrifice his little will, which is unfree and ruled by things and drives, to his great
will that moves away from being determined to find destiny."14
Self in hermeneutic process
What Buber describes as the movement of the self from the "little" to the
"great" will is at least analogous to the movement of hermeneutic self-understanding
described by Gadamer and by Ricoeur. Understanding, Gadamer says, involves a
moment of "loss of self," as a result of which "the individual self, including his
activity and his understanding of himself, is taken up into a higher determination."15
As I have already pointed out, this moment of loss of self resulting in new self-
understanding is only possible because of an initial breach in understanding, a sense
of discrepancy, of alienation. The self becomes problematic to itself--it becomes a
strange text, difficult to decipher, once (before the onset of reflection) familiar, but
no longer so. This problematization, or crisis of self-understanding, although it is
always latent in the structure of the self, is triggered by historical (i.e. collective)
and/or developmental (i.e. individual) events. It only emerges into philsophy when
the pre-understandings--whether personal, cultural, or some combination of the two-
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 13

-into which one's narrative fit seamlessly and unproblematically, break down. So
Gadamer says, "The hermeneutical problem only emerges clearly when there is no
powerful tradition present to absorb one's own attitude into itself and when one is
aware of confronting an alien tradition to which he has never belonged or one he no
longer unquestioningly accepts."16 Ricoeur calls the condition prior to the break
"belonging," which he characterizes as "a prior relation of inclusion which
encompasses the allegedly autonomous subject and the allegedly adverse object. . . .
Hermeneutics . . . begins when, not content to belong to transmitted tradition, we
interrupt the relation of belonging in order to signify it." This interruption he
characterizes as "distanciation," which initiates a dialogue with the object, resulting
in what he describes, using Gadamer's concept, as a "fusion of horizons." The end
result (which is only a temporary result in an endless process) is a dialectical
movement resulting in "appropriation," whereby the knower "makes what was alien
become one's own."17
Belonging is a an original condition of self-unity, either before the doubling
of consciousness--i.e. before 18 to 24 months og age--or when the doubling of
consciousness is non-problematic, because of the presence of a "powerful tradition
which absorbs one's attitude into itself." Philosophy, psychoanalysis, and art
represent a rupture in that unity, a self-problematization of the subject: the self turns
on itself, becomes its own text, and enters into dialogue with that text. Pixie's
dialogue with herself is paradigmatically a philosophical rather than a
psychoanalytic or artistic one--she questions, reasons, identifies contradictions,
makes generalizations, identifies part-whole relationships, etc. in a way which is
identifiable as "philosphical." It is in dialogue with this "text" which is herself, that
the dialectic unfolds.
The hermeneutical dialogue, Gadamer suggests, has the structure of a game,
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 14

the to and fro, fateful character of play. In it, the player puts her identity at risk, in
that "the game tends to master the players. . . .The real subject of the game . . is not
the player, but instead the game itself. The game is what holds the player in its
spell, draws him into play, and keeps him there." Thus Gadamer can say, "all
playing is a being-played," in the sense that "the player experiences the game as a
reality that surpasses him."18 Play has ontological significance, in that when things
are represented in play, there is a "transformation into the true." Through the playful
representation of art, philosophy and psychoanalysis,19 and over against the "world
of aims" and "biological conceptions of purpose," "what is emerges. In it is
produced and brought to light what otherwise is constantly hidden and withdrawn."
Gadamer thus calls play the "clue to ontological explanation." He summons in
illustration tragic or comic drama, which, when it is successful, is a kind of self-
representation of being which "leaves behind it everything that is accidental and
unessential, e.g. the private particular being of the actor. He disappears entirely into
the recognition of what he is representing. But even that which is represented, a
well-known event of mythological tradition, is raised by its representation to its own
validity and truth."20
Gadamer's ontology of play has implications for an understanding of how the
community of inquiry functions and develops which cannot be taken up here. From
the point of view of the hermeneutics of self-understanding, what is important is that
the self gets absorbed into this larger play of the dialogue with itself and the world.
This ammounts to a loss of self, a becoming vulnerable to something which is not
under the individual self's control. It is this Hegelian "moment of negativity" which
results in appropriation, or a new self-understanding on a higher dimension. So
Kierkegaard has the young man in Repetition say, "Did I not get myself again,
precisely in such a way that I must doubly feel its significance?"21 On one level, we
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 15

may understand Pixie's final crisis, leading to the plays of the final chapters, as such
a process. Her disastrous category mistake at the zoo, followed by her sickness,
followed by the transformation beyond recognition of her story into four stories by
her classmates, suggests this dialectical movement of self-loss followed by what
Ricoeur, describing appropriation, calls "the self-interpretation of a subject who
thenceforth understands himself better, understands himself differently, or simply
begins to understand himself."22 Above all, Pixie "loses" herself in the
transformation of her story by her classmates into the play of art, but through that
self-loss begins to understand herself better.
The Pixie plays
The four stories which emerge from Pixie's story can be seen as the playful
self-representation of Pixie's and her classmates' inquiry, and the community of
inquiry's appropriation of the foundational metaphors of the Western philosophical
tradition. The plays function as a "transformation into the true" of the ideas with
which Pixie and her community have been in dialogue throughout the novel. From
the point of view of the hermeneutics of self-understanding, Ricoeur refers to this
process as "refiguration by narrative." The self, he says, "does not know itself
immediately, but only indirectly, through the detour of cultural signs of all sorts,
which articulate the self in symbolic mediations."23 So Pixie and the other members
of the community of inquiry tell the original philosophical stories over again--or are
the stories telling them?--in an effort to find themselves there: to find their origins,
which involves evoking the origins of everything; to define the mind-body relation;
to address the problem of parts and wholes, not only intrapersonally ("If I replace all
my parts again," says the Tin Woodman, "will I still be me?") but interpersonally,
i.e. the part-whole relationship between the individual and the community of
individuals ("No one was happy. the best pair of eyes would say, `We're really no
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 16

good, because we can't run'"); to solve the mystery of personal identity beyond
physical transformation, and the origin and nature of difference between persons; to
address the mystery of self's lived experience as transcending the body, even while
aware of itself as body. Each story represents the self's effort to "start from the
beginning," and to tell the "big story" which will satisfy all the appearances.
The fact that each person has taken Pixie's story and transformed it into
something which is both the same as the other stories and also quite different, is not
only characteristic of the horizonal multiplicity of the community of inquiry, but
helps us understand the role of narrative in self-construction. Each person is telling a
story about him or herself which is both common--sharing a tradition, or a set of
pre-understandings--and unique. Each self tells itself, indeed "produces" itself,
writes its script, directs, and plays the leading role. It must do so, in order to "give
shape to things and put them in order." So, in the fourth story, Brian plays himself,
and the Pixie he plays is the Pixie of his own representation, the only Pixie he
knows. Each self tells the story, not only of her own self, but of all selves, from a
perspective which is unsharable by other selves; yet there is a common horizon, if
infinitely receding and never determined once and for all, in which the perspectives
converge. That horizon, as Corrington's discussion of the hermeneutics of Royce,
Peirce, and Gadamer shows, is visible to all members of the the community of
inquiry, if never completely attained.
The final story--a story identified with Plato, but much older than he24--which
tells yet again the grand Western story of the forms or edoi, of knowledge as
remembrance, and of the relationship between beauty and truth, can be read as a
grand analogue for the lived experience of the self: the sense of ontological
uniqueness we cannot help but experience ourselves as; the sense of being
incarnated, i.e. come from beyond yourselves, combined with the sense of being
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 17

"thrown" into a world in which "nothing ever comes out quite right," thereby
implying the existence of a world, or at least a conceptual realm, in which
everything is just right; the sudden opening within the self, the sense of significance
associated with the experience of beauty and of great art; the irreconcilable longing
for homecoming, for "being back home where we belong again, and we're happy."
The abrupt interruption by Robert of this grand evocation of the vision which
dominated Western self-understanding for thousands of years returns us with a jolt
to the postmodern world, where no story--neither the idealist's, the realist's, the
empiricist's or the pragmatist's--can claim that it is more than a story. This is
Wittgenstein's world of language games which do not translate into each other, and
Pixie's "third mystery," the aporia created by the epistemological relativism which is
the current condition of Western philosophy. The novel ends with the implicit
suggestion that it is this "third mystery" that she is now ready, through the self-
enlargement she has experienced, to take on.
Conclusion
Pixie, our philosophical heroine, has represented the self for us:
disembodied, timeless, ageless, voice, doubled, shapeshifter, "smaller than small and
bigger than big," inherently digressive, a compulsive storyteller, a story in search of
itself requiring constant revision, a continual crisis, a never-ending conversation
with itself, involved in an infinite regress in search of its ground, spread through its
internal and external relationships, multiple, in constant transition, pure identity yet
completely determined by its environment, radically free and radically contingent,
ambiguously related to its body, unpredictable, charismatic, flashing, unstable, a
mystery to itself, a walking fallacy of composition, an aspirant to becoming a perfect
other, an idea in search of becoming a thing, a thing longing to become its own
ideas. . . . Pixie shows forth these characteristics of the self as only the quixotic,
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 18

enthusiastic nine-year old philosopher can. Like many 9-year old philosophers, she
has so many questions she hasn't the time to pause and go about answering them.
This is as it should be, for "the structure of the question is implicit in all
experience,"25 and the experience of the self is, in hermeneutic experience, the
ultimate question.

ENDNOTES

1. I am assuming, although this is not the place to argue it in any detail, that at
each phase of the life cycle, the self is most vividly revealed in certain of its
aspects. Those aspects are present in persons throughout the life span, but
they are represented paradigmatically in the particular phase of the life cycle
in which they are most strongly expressed.
2. The major terms for the discussion of hermeneutics in this paper are drawn
principally from Paul Ricouer, Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981); and Hans George Gadamer,
Truth and Method (New York: Crossroad, 1975), and Philosophical
Hermeneutics (Berkely, CA: University of California Press, 1976).
3. The psychoanalytic literature is filled with accounts of this process. A few of
the classic philosophical narratives on the emergence of self-consciousness
are found in George Herbert Mead, Mind, Self, and Society (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1934); Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "The Child's
Relations With Others," in The Primacy of Perception (Evanston, IL:
Northwestern University Press, 1964), which includes a discussion of Lacan's
analysis of the role of the "specular image” in the formation of self; and John
MacMurray, Persons in Relation (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press,
1961).
4. It could also result, it could be argued, in the end of itself--a merging of the
en-soi and the pour-soi which abrogates the doubleness which is the
determinative characteristic of the human self.
5. G.H. Mead, Mind, Self, & Society; and Jean Paul Sartre, Being and
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 19

Nothingness, trans. Hazel E. Barnes (New York: Philosophical Library,


1956).
6. Karl Rahner makes a coherent case for this sense of transcendence of the
person, who exists "before the multiplicity of his immediately-given objects."
A Rahner Reader, Gerald A. McCool, ed. (New York: Seabury, 1975), p.
264.
7. For an incisive portrait of the self as narrative, see Alasdair MacIntyre, After
Virtue, Second Edition (University of Notre Dame Press, 1984), Chapter 15.
See also Paul Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, vol. 3, trans. K. Blamey and D.
Pellauer (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988). This discussion also
draws from Heideggerian and Husserlian analyses of temporalization, which
are well-represented in Schutz and Luckmann,
8. Robert S. Corrington, The Community of Interpreters (Macon GA: Mercer
University Press, 1987), p. 32.
9. See Ann Sharp, "Silence and Speech in Pixie," in this volume.
10. Richard Palmer, Hermeneutics, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
1969, pp. 87, 118.
11. We have one topographical analysis of this mystery in Johari's Window,
which is an application of the Four Possibilities to the terms Self, Other,
Known, and Not Known. The possibility "Not known to self, not known to
other" expresses the condition of mystery.
12. Martin Heidegger, "Letter On Humanism," in Basic Writings, Ed. David Krell
(New York: Harper, 1977), p. 231.
13. Romans 7:14
14. Martin Buber, I and Thou, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Scribners,
1970), pp. 102, 107-108.
15. "On The Problem of Self-Understanding," in Philosophical Hermeneutics, p.
54.
16. Ibid, p. 46.
NINE YEAR OLD PHILOSOPHER AND HERMENEUTICS 20

17. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, pp. 105, 117, and passim.
18. Truth and Method, pp. 95-96, 98.
19. All of these practices may be characterized as spiritual, and can be grouped
with the practices of various spiritual traditions, all of which involve the
hermeneutic relationship to the self.
20. Truth and Method, pp. 96, 97, 101, 103.
21. Quoted in Patricia A. Johnson, "The Task of the Philosopher: Kierkegaard--
Heidegger--Gadamer," Philosophy Today 28,1 (Spring 1984): 3-18, which is
an excellent exploration of the "movement of retrieval" which results from the
moment of self-loss in dialogue.
22. Hermeneutics and the Human Sciences, p. 158.
23. Paul Ricoeur, "Narrative Identity," Philosophy Today 35,1 (Spring 1991):80.
24. Mircea Eliade calls Plato "the outstanding philosopher of `primitive
mentality', that is the thinker who succeeded in giving philosophic currency
and validity to the modes of life and behavior of archaic humanity." The
Myth of the Eternal Return (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1955).
25. Truth and Method, p. 326. And see this section of Gadamer's text, entitled
"The Hermeneutical Priority of the Question."
THE NINE-YEAR-OLD PHILOSOPHER
AND THE HERMENEUTICS OF SELF-UNDERSTANDING

David Kennedy
Northern Michigan University
September, 1992

You might also like