You are on page 1of 51

Universitatea Bucureti

Facultatea de Filosofie



Lucrare de Disertaie:


We as Conceptual Entrepreneurs
The Interplay between Rules and Decisions






Coordonator tiinific:
Prof. Univ. Dr. Mircea Dumitru
Absolvent:
Trandafira Andrei




-2005-


Abstract


This work is about our distinctiveness as human beings. The answer is that we are
conceptual entrepreneurs. That is, the realm that makes us different is the conceptual
realm and the way we live within it is as entrepreneurs.
The aim is achieved by building upon insights of two different lines of thought
(the first is mainly American Pragmatism, but the later Wittgenstein was on the same line
in parallel, the second is Austrian Economics).
The first chapter deals with the first line of thought and is mainly an exposition of
ideas of Robert Brandom. The chapter starts from the Kantian insight that we are
normative creatures. Specifically, that judgments and actions are essentially normative.
This positive insight is backed up by the negative point made by Frege, who showed what
we lose if we overlook this normative dimension. Afterwards, it is enquired about how
we can understand the normative. The first strategy is to reduce the normative to explicit
rules and principles. This strategy was refuted by Wittgenstein who showed that we can
enquire about every specific rule how it should be applied. Thus, we will need another
rule and so on, having an infinite regress. The second strategy is to reduce rules to
regularities of behavior. This strategy is flawed because it cannot secure a distinction
between what ought to be done and what is in fact done. Every pattern of behavior can be
made to accord with many rules, and thus we can not pick out a specific rule only by
looking at behavior. The conclusion is that norms must be sought at the pragmatic level.
The second chapter deals with the second line of thought. It tries to show how we
are able to learn from experience. It starts from humans viewed as Homo Economicus.
This means that we are essentially optimizing creatures. But this strategy overlooks the
first step, that of choosing a specific ends-mean framework. Thus, it is shown that the
correct strategy is to view humans as Homo Agens. That is, to see them as possessing an
ability (that of decision-making) which explains also the fact that we can change our
ends-mean framework. This analysis of Human Action ultimately leads to the conclusion
that we are entrepreneurs, making decision in a world endowed with uncertainty.
The third chapter combines these two lines of thought. It starts from the strategy
to explain our ability to use concepts by grasping their essential properties. This strategy
is showed to be flawed by confusing the descriptive and the normative functioning of
language. By showing this it can be showed with clarity what is the relation between a
concept and his applications. Afterwards it is shown how our decisions play an essential
role in employing new concepts and changing old ones. These two points are combined,
and the way we move through the world proves to be as conceptual entrepreneurs; as
beings forced to take decisions in an uncertain world, where any decision could prove to
be mistaken; and as beings capable to impose a structure upon the world by instituting
rules (and specifically for us, concepts).
Acknowledgements:

Besides the works of those from whom I have learned, I would like to thank Mircea Toboaru,
Marian Panait, Vlad Tarko, Andreea Eanu, Andrei Buleandr and Teodor Gugiu for helpful
comments, sugestions and discussions.



Contents:

I. Introduction pg.1
II. Chapter One - Grounding the normative at the pragmatic level pg.3
1. Introduction pg.3
2. Humans as normative creatures pg.6
3. How to understand the normative pg.9
4. Conclusion pg.12

III. Chapter Two The entrepreneurial character of decision-making pg.13
1. Introduction pg.13
2. Homo Economicus pg.14
3. Homo Agens pg.18
4. We as entrepreneurs pg.22
5. Conclusion pg.27

IV. Chapter Three - The conceptual realm as interplay between rules and
decisions pg.28
1. Introduction pg.28
2. The Wittgensteinian and Sellarsian insight pg.31
3. The role of decisions in the conceptual realm pg.37
4. We as conceptual entrepreneurs pg.41
5. Conclusion pg.44

V. Conclusion pg.46



I. Introduction

What is our place in the world, as human beings? What differentiates us from
other creatures? What we have in common with them? On one hand, we deem ourselves
as intelligent creatures, different from every other; we have Reason. With such a general
claim every one would agree. But if we want to put the point more specifically, problems
arise. For example, we all agree that there are some entities that we call concepts. And
we are sure that they play an important role in our lives. Nevertheless we are puzzled by
them. With objects we do not have so many problems; they are concrete, they are in front
of us. But concepts are mysterious entities. Sometimes we put them in our heads, in our
minds. Sometimes we put them in a third world. Although we have a grip on them, at the
same time they have a grip on us. Do we create them or do we discover them?
The aim of this work is to offer a picture of what is specific to us, as human
beings. The picture will not be carried out in a great detail, but it will nevertheless be a
complete picture. This writer hopes that in the end the reader will remain with a clear
image. The picture is based upon insights of many great thinkers. Furthermore, many of
those insights were put together by some others. This work is based on raw materials
obtained from the works of Robert Brandom and Israel Kirzner. It is hoped that this work
keeps the spirit of their works intact (and with it the spirit of the other great thinkers
whose insights were kept clear by Brandom and Kirzner). The claim of this work is not
one of originality, in the sense of saying things that were never said or thought before. Its
claim is that it offers a clear picture of what is specific of human beings, by combining
two different lines of thought, namely that of American Pragmatism and that of Austrian
Economics (Robert Brandom being a great thinker of the first school, and Israel Kirzner
of the second). The two lines of thought are combined because this writer thinks that they
share the same fundamental spirit and insights, but that they develop them in different
ways and from different perspectives. Furthermore, by offering different perspectives
which start from the same fundamental points, if they are put together, then they might
give a more clear picture. This is not to say that by themselves they do not offer clear
pictures. They also offer much more detailed pictures than the one put forward in this
1
work. But at the loss of detail and at the gain of perspective it is hoped that this picture
will be clear to unadvised eyes too.
This work is not an exegetic one or one that tries to make a critical comparison
between different lines of thought. Thus, it will not start from arguments that are
attributed to some thinker. Instead, it will start from insights that some thinkers had. But,
this writer is fully committed to every single insight put forward in this work. So, it is
also his duty to defend them if it is needed and the ones that had them for the first time
can only be of help by providing sound arguments to back up those insights. Furthermore,
it will not be an issue if someone contests that some specific thinker had some specific
insight. This is not a debate about what insights had a specific person or about who had a
specific insight. If this writer attributes an insight to a specific person, then this is made
only because he would like to thank that person in this way, not because he needs some
authority to back him up.
The first chapter presents a line of thought of Robert Brandom in which he builds
upon insights of Kant, Frege, Sellars and Wittgenstein. It is about we as normative
creatures and about where we should seek this normativity. The answer will be that we
should seek it at the pragmatic level.
The second chapter presents a line of thought of Israel Kirzner in which he builds
upon insights of Mises and Hayek. It is about us as decision-makers, specifically about
the entrepreneurial character of human decision-making. The point will be that the way in
which we can gain some knowledge in a mysterious world is by making decisions, even
if they could always prove to be mistaken.
Thus, the raw materials which we will use in the third and last chapter will be that
our ability to follow rules is rooted at the pragmatic level and that our decisions are taken
as entrepreneurs, in a world of uncertainty. In the third chapter we will show how these
two features of us combined give a picture of our specific way of being in the world. We
are concept mongers. This specific ability of ours will be shown to consist in forming a
conceptual web (a system of rules) by taking at every step entrepreneurial decisions about
how to modify it.



2
I. Chapter One Grounding the normative at the pragmatic level

1. Introduction

A friend of ours, which has a very nice house just outside the city, ordered the
most greenish hollandaise grass field to be installed in front of his veranda. After a week
of happy mornings with a cup of tee and the marvelous sight in front of him, one gloomy
morning he could not believe his eyes. In front of him laid what seemed to be a sea of
blood. While he was sleeping, all the grass turned red and, although he squeezed his eyes
hoping that all that is just an appearance, nothing changed. He had to confront the
cruelest of realities. Let us be assured, our friends eyes had nothing wrong, the grass did
really changed. At that moment, for him the range of possible explanations was immense,
for that reason him being completely puzzled, without any firm ground to put his feet on.
Of course, for us as perfectly informed observers the explanation is at hand, but this is not
really important now.
What matters is that, if our friend would have been a little pessimistic, he could
have thought, in the night, of all the different possible colors his dearly grass would have
in the morning. The world of possibilities is, indeed, a large one. Furthermore, is of prime
importance the reaction of our friend: This shouldnt have happened! This is not right!.
But, we may say that in a sense it is right, in a sense reality is always right. So, what had
our friend in mind, what didnt seem right to him? It could be that, for a second, he
thought that the laws of nature didnt work anymore. But, on a second thought, he must
have realized that this is, at best, a very unrealistic possibility. Afterwards, he must have
thought that the world of nature is too complex, for him to grasp completely. That there
must be a chemical reaction or some strange insects or who knows what that explains it
all. Or, that the world of men is a mischievous one and, surely, one of his friends played
some dirty trick on him. These were the kinds of explanations that crossed his mind. But
why the new color didnt seem right to him? What would have been his reaction if, in the
night before, a strange, nearly mad idea had crossed his mind; that of the excitement of a
very surprising thing happening, for example the grass turning red? For sure, in the
morning, the surprise would be as great as in the first case. But the words that would
3
come out of his mouth would be very different: Oh my dear! This is perfect, indeed!.
Now, it seems that all that feeling of frustrating wrongness vanished in this new situation.
Now everything is correct according to our friend, even if a bit unexpected.
At this moment it should be noted that, making abstraction of our friend, the
reality is identical in the two cases above. The weather is the same; the grass has the same
reddish color. Everything is the same excepting the words our friend uttered and, maybe,
his state of mind. Of course, someone who is very fond of reductionism could say that in
our friends brain are happening very different things in the two cases, that the neuronal
processes present us enough of a difference. What could we say to him, besides that he is
trying to obscure the very point we are trying to make, that he looks in a wrong way? We
can add that it is nothing wrong in tracing the different neuronal processes, but if he has
this liberty, he should also let us have the liberty of tracing which differences we like.
That there is nothing wrong with this, will not be showed here thoroughly
1
. It will suffice
to say that we are on equal footing with the reductionist. That with the same legitimacy
with which he points toward what he considers being the relevant differences, we can
also do exactly the same thing. And that if he considers that this is not so, then this is a
point for him yet to make, not for us to defend.
So, what is different in the two cases? Let us suppose that our friend is fond of
drawing and that in the night before he made two drawings: one of a happy morning for
him and one of an unhappy one. Furthermore, let us suppose that in each case he made
the same drawings, two landscapes with him on the veranda, in one the grass being green,
in the other being red. The only difference is that in the first case the one with green grass
stands for the happy morning, and in the second the one with red grass stands for it. So,
by looking only to one of these pictures, or to both of them, we could not say which one
stands for the happy morning. Furthermore, it will not suffice to know that one of them
corresponds to reality. We really need to know what our friends idea of a happy morning
was if we want to know which drawing describes it correctly.
Being a rigorous person, our friend likes to plan in advance many things. He is
also a little childish so, before going to sleep, he likes to imagine how the next day should
be, for him to be happy. By doing this, he makes something like a plan, although it does

1
This point is developed by R.Brandom in his essay Modality, Normativity and Intentionality
4
not require much action from him to make the plan work. Nevertheless, he makes a plan
because it involves two very distinct images of the future. In one of them, the happy one,
the reality sticks to the plan; it conforms to it. In the other, the unhappy one, reality
diverges from the plan; it does not conform to it.
To press the analogy further, any rule is a plan, because it involves two different
possible ways in which the events could develop. One in which the rule is followed
correctly, another in which the rule is followed incorrectly. In a similar way, intentions
could be successful by being followed by actions, or they could be not; concepts could be
applied correctly, or they could be not, opinions could state the facts correctly, or they
could not, and so on. We can ask many questions about what has been said here. Like,
what exactly is a rule, is there any difference between the laws of nature and those of
men, and if there is what is it, how could be a rule followed correctly, how could we
know that we followed a rule correctly and many others. But the important point here is
what the source of all these questions is. In the story above the emphasis was put,
although implicitly, on a distinctive feature of human beings, namely their normativity.
The point of this chapter will be to settle some important points about normativity, which
will be used as raw materials in the later chapters. The points that will be restated in this
chapter were offered by Robert Brandom in the first chapter of Making it explicit,
where he builds upon insights of great philosophers like Kant, Frege, Sellars or
Wittgenstein.

2. Humans as normative creatures

We, humans, have always regarded ourselves as special. And, maybe, we had
every right in doing so. After all, beginning with the discovery of fire, we have invented
inasmuch as we discovered many things. We have changed the world according to our
desires and ideals; we have tamed the beasts, but also the inanimate forces of nature. All
these, we have done with the power of our mind, our special ability, which permitted us
to rule the world and the other species. Of course, all these and many other differences
are said by us and from our point of view. Nevertheless, our distinctiveness is clear to the
vast majority of us: we are intelligent creatures, reasonable beings, we can make our own
5
rules and we can follow them. We are free to choose our path, but we are responsible for
it, at the same time. So, what makes us special? The short answer is that we are normative
creatures. But what does this amount to? Although different stories on this subject could
be told, the one that will be restated here (in a very short and incomplete version) is that
of Robert Brandom. According to Brandom, Kant had a great insight on the point of
normativity:
[One] of Kants fundamental insights, into the normative character of the
significance of what is conceptually contentful is that judgments and actions are above
all things that we are responsible for. Kant understands concepts as having the form of
rules, which is to say that they specify how something ought (according to the rule) to be
done. The understanding, the conceptual faculty, is the faculty of grasping rules, of
appreciating the distinction between correct and incorrect application they determine.
Judgings and doings are acts that have contents that one can take or make true and for
which the demand for reasons is in order. What is distinctive about them is the way they
are governed by rules. Being in an intentional state or performing an intentional action
has a normative significance. It counts as undertaking (acquiring) an obligation or
commitment; the content of the commitment is determined by the rules that are the
concepts in terms of which the act or state is articulated. Thus Kant picks us out as
distinctively normative or rule-governed creatures.
2
A rule does not specify what the facts will be. It only specifies what the facts
ought to be, what would count as being in accord with that rule. If we would see a
signpost on which is written: Don not step on the grass!, then we would not know what
will in fact happen. Some people will step on the grass, some will not. But the rule that is
expressed by the words written on the sign will show us something. The rule will show us
who complied with it, and who did not. If we are to understand that rule, then we have to
discern what counts as correctly following that rule from what counts as incorrectly
following it. Similarly, for someone to count as possessing a concept, for example the
concept square, he must know how to apply that concept correctly. For example, if he
says about something that it is a rectangle with all sides equal, then he should agree to say
that it is a square. Or, if he says about something that it is a square, then he should agree

2
Articulating Reasons pg. 163
6
to say that it is a geometrical figure. Also, we are responsible for our intentional states
and actions. Once certain concepts are in play and certain rules are being followed, they
have a grip on us. The fact that we followed a rule correctly does not depend on us
anymore. It is not up to our liberty anymore to decide if what we have done consists in a
correct or incorrect following of a rule.
The Kantian insight tries to settle a positive point. It tries to settle the important
role that normativity, in the form of rules, plays in the lives of human beings. This point
can be backed up by a negative one, by showing how things would be if we rule out the
normative ingredient. This point is carried out by Frege. In the words of Brandom:
Kants lesson is taken over as a central theme by Frege, whose campaign against
psychologism relies on respecting and enforcing the distinction between the normative
significance of applying concepts and the causal consequences of doing so. For Frege, it
is possible to investigate in a naturalistic way acts of judging or thinking (even thinking
conceived in a dualistic way), but such an investigation inevitably overlooks the
normative dimension that is essential to understanding the propositional contents that
are judged or thought
3
The consequence of overlooking the normative dimension is that everything that
is thought or judged is on equal footing. We can not have right or wrong inferences; we
can only have inferences that are actually made. By looking only to what actually
happens and to the causal links between facts we are in a position from which the line
between correct and incorrect can not be drawn. This is so, because in the natural order
everything happens according to some (natural) law, and so everything turns out to be
correct. If we are to make sense of the correct/incorrect distinction we need something
else, besides what happens, besides what is. We must make a place for what ought to be.
If I held true that It is raining now, then it does not help to look at what happens in my
brain to know if what I say is really true. Instead, I have to know what ought to be the
case for my statement to be true.
Frege made clear the distinction between causation and justification. To ask what
caused a certain event is to ask what made it actually happen. Causation runs through the
realm of actuality; with the help of it we can know why something did happen, is

3
Making It Explicit pg.11
7
happening or will happen. J ustification is about what ought to happen. In searching for a
justification, we enquire about what ought to happen. We may successfully causally
explain why an event took place, but this does not say if it should have happened. After
all, good things as well as bad things happen. But in the causal realm (which was in place
for a long time before our coming in the world) there is no place for good and bad, for
what ought to be and what ought to be not. J ustification does just that, it makes room for
the distinction between what ought to be and what ought to be not. Something that ought
to be, nevertheless, may not actually obtain. Conversely, something that ought to be not
may actually obtain. The point is that causation and justification are different stories
(complementary, for sure) and failure of grasping this difference may lead to a hopeless
search in one realm for something that can be found only in the other.
At this point, it may be useful to ask how this confusion could happen. This kind
of enquire was done by the later Wittgenstein, who looked for the difference between the
causal must and the logical (normative) must. Both of them are kinds of must
because both of them involve some necessary correlations, which do not leave room for
misfire. The causal must does not leave room for misfire between the laws that govern
the functioning of the machine and how it does, in fact, function
4
. The logical must
also does not leave room for misfire, but between different things. As Brandom puts it:
The relation between the content of an intention and the performances that would
fulfill that intention does not leave any room for misfire, corresponding to the melting or
bending of the parts of a mechanism, for it is already a normative relation. The state is to
settle what ought to be done, what must be done if it is to be realized. What actually does
or would happen is another matter. The images of superrigidity of being guided by rails
that one cannot fall away from are what one gets if one assimilates normative
compulsion to causal compulsion, ignoring the Kantian distinction. That is, if the
normative must were a kind of causal must, it would have to be a puzzling , superrigid
sort but the point is not to start with this sort of naturalistic prejudice
5



4
Of course, every machine could break. But if we would be omniscient we would know that it was not the
case of this kind of misfire, but some other laws were in place, that made the machine break.
5
Making It Explicit pg .14
8
A rule cannot fail to settle what must be done if it is to be followed. Between
these two there is no room for misfire. But the relation between the content of a rule and
what actually happens is not predetermined in any way. One may succeed, as well as he
may fail, in following some rule. So, we have two kinds of must, because we have two
kinds of compulsion, between different things; but if we look in the logical must for the
same type of compulsion that we have in the causal must, we will look in vain and we
will be puzzled for sure.

3. How to understand the normative

The previous section was meant to establish that the normative ingredient is a
very important one in us, of our intentional states. Now, the question that comes in place
is: How can we understand the normative? Brandom attributes to Kant the view that:
norms just are rules of conduct. Normative assessments of performances are
understood as always having the form of assessments of the extent to which those
performances accord to some rule. Reference to proprieties of performance is taken as
indirect reference to rules, which determine what is proper by explicitly saying what is
proper. On this account, acts are liable as normative assessments insofar as they are
governed by propositionally explicit prescriptions, prohibitions and permissions. These
may be conceived as rules, or alternatively as principles, laws, commands, contracts, or
conventions. Each of these determines what one may or must do by saying what one may
or must do. For a performance to be correct is, on this model, for the rules to permit or
require it, for it to be in accord with principle, for the law to allow or demand it, for it to
be commanded or contracted
6
According to this view, whenever we asses the propriety of some conduct, we
make appeal to some explicit rules or principles which determine the correctness of that
conduct. The rules must be given somehow in advance, and we are to judge the propriety
of that conduct by looking at what is permitted by that rule. If we want to make an
assessment of correctness, then we have to make reference (at least implicitly) to a rule
that determines what is appropriately to do by saying what is appropriately to do. This

6
Making It Explicit, pg.19
9
view is called by Brandom regulism and consists in conceiving the proprieties of practice
as being only expressions of more basic principles. The normativity is at home in
discursive principles that explicitly say what is correct, and only afterwards is it exhibited
in practice.
The critic of regulism was Wittgenstein. His argument drew on the observation
that a rule can be, itself, applied correctly or incorrectly. A rule specifies how something
ought to be done (e.g. how someone ought to cross the street); it must be applied to
particular cases (e.g. in which people are crossing the street) to see if in those cases it was
followed. If we ask if a rule has been applied correctly to a particular case, how shall we
settle the question? According to the regulist view we have to make appeal to some other
rule for deciding the correctness of our performance (i.e. that of applying the first rule).
So, for deciding if a rule was applied correctly, we must appeal to some other rule, and so
on ad infinitum. This regress argument shows that the process of interpretation
7
must end
somehow, because it ends as a matter of fact. To stop the regress we need to question our
view that every assessment of correctness must be made by looking at some explicit rule.
This view does not propose an autonomous conception of norms. The final step, which
can stop the regress, is missing. Normativity cannot be rules all the way down because
we cannot even start in this case. If we think that our first step consists in applying a rule,
then we will soon found out the trace of our earlier step, which consists in applying a rule
that allows us to know if we applied the first one correctly. Indeed, a rule specifies how
to do one thing correctly, but on the condition that the first step is already secured, that
we already can do something else correctly (applying the rule). So, what is the first step?
According to Brandom:
The conclusion of the regress argument is that there is a need for a pragmatist
conception of norms a notion of primitive correctness of performance implicit in
practice that precede and are presupposed by their explicit formulation in rules and
principlesThe regress argument does not by itself provide such a conception of
proprieties of practice; it just shows that without one we cannot understand how rules
can codify the correctness that they doWhat Wittgenstein shows is that the
intellectualist model will not do as an account of the nature of the normative as such. For

7
For Wittgenstein a rule for applying a rule is called an interpretation
10
when applied to the norms governing the application of rules and principles, it generates
a regress, which can be halted only by acknowledging the existence of some more
primitive form of norm. The regress is Wittgensteins master argument for the
appropriateness of the pragmatist, rather than the regulist-intellectualist, order of
explanation.
8
This is not to say that we cannot go on in enquiring about the correctness of the
application of every rule. The point is rather that every time we apply some rule, we
settled already in some other way what amounts to following correctly that rule; and that
this first step must be sought at the pragmatic level, where we can do something correctly
without first assessing that correctness by an appeal to some explicit rule. So, we need a
notion of norms that are implicit in practice, that are already in place, before our explicit
assessment by and of them. So, where should we seek the norms?
One strategy of response is that to talk about implicit norms is just to talk about
regularities that practices should be understood just as regularities of behavior
9
. This
strategy tries to pick the rules by searching regularities of behavior. The regress argument
is avoided, since the norms need not be expressible by those in whose conduct they are
implicit. It is sufficient that we observe regularity in behavior and, thus, to see what rule
that conduct is conforming to. This strategy risks to reduce the following of a rule to a
mere to be in accord with a rule, and this would come up to a reduction of the
normative to the causal. To avoid such a risk, this kind of strategy must be able to fund a
distinction between what is in fact done and what ought to be done. It must make room
for permanent possibility of mistakes, for what is done or taken to be correct nonetheless
to turn out to be incorrect or inappropriate, according to some rule or practice.
10
For
this, it is needed a way of picking out a preferred pattern of regularities, which will
permit us to identify correct performances with regular ones.
The problem appears when we try to pick out the relevant regularity. Or, as
Brandom puts it: The problem is that any particular set of performances exhibits many
regularities. These will agree on the performances that have been produced and differ in
their treatment of some possible performances that have not (yet) been produced. A

8
Making it explicit pg 21-22
9
Making it explicit pg 27
10
Making it explicit pg 27
11
performance can be denominated irregular only with respect to a specified regularity,
not tout court.
11
Put in other words, we now face the problem of selecting the relevant regularity
from many others. Only by doing this we can denominate some performance as
irregular. But then, the problem arises again at the level of the selection of the relevant
regularity. Why some regularity is relevant, and not others? How can we decide which
regularity ought to be the relevant one? So, all this strategy does is to push the
normativity further away, but not to give an account for it.
What is the next move that we should make if we want to ground the normative?
If anything is to be made out of the Kantian insight that there is a fundamental
normative dimension to the application of concepts (and hence to the significance of
discursive or propositionally contentful intentional states and performances), an account
is needed of what it is for norms to be implicit in practices. Such practices must be
construed both as not having to involve explicit rules and as distinct from mere
regularities
12
The points are: first that our normativity reaches beyond our discursivity, and
second that we can not look for norms by looking only at mere regularities. Our norms
must be implicit in practice, in the first place, and they are in a strong sense ours, in that
they can not be grasped by looking from a completely external perspective, trying to
guess them somehow.

4. Conclusion

The purpose of this chapter was to provide the first raw materials needed for the
construction pursued in the third chapter. It was meant to establish that we are normative
creatures; that the Kantian insight is one without we cannot make sense of our specificity
and that our normativity must be sought at the pragmatic level. For now, it will suffice
the negative thesis that normativity is not to be reduced to discursivity (norms are not
rules all the way down) and that normativity is not to be reduced to mere regularities.

11
Making it explicit pg.28
12
Making it explicit pg.29
12
III. Chapter two The entrepreneurial character of decision-making

1. Introduction

Ever since their coming into the world, humans strived to survive. Indeed, this is
not specific only to human beings, but to every living being. Nevertheless, why we did so
well in this respect is a question which regards only us.
Perhaps in the Stone Age
13
humans did not have much knowledge, although they
could have made good use out of it. When some tribe found some new and unknown
fruit, they knew they could not afford to pass that opportunity away. They had to know if
that fruit was eatable, and so, eligible to become a new asset in their fight against
starvation. But they had no idea if that was so, that fruit being of unknown color and
form. They had only one chance: to risk, to try and see what will happen. One of them
was chosen and he ate the fruit. After that, the tribe acquired new knowledge, even if
sometimes this knowledge came at the cost of one human life.
Fortunately, the process of acquiring knowledge gives us important advantages. It
is a cumulative process and knowledge can be communicated. It is cumulative, because
we need not try two times the same poisonous fruit and we need not be in doubt twice
whether to eat a healthy fruit. Knowledge can be communicated, because one life is
enough for the other members of the tribe to know what to keep their hands off.
Of course, there are some inherent difficulties that come bundled with the process
of knowledge. Acquiring knowledge is not an easy task; it is a very hard and arduous
process. After all, it is not so easy going into the complete unknown and trying to shed
some light there. The world is immense and by acquiring knowledge we fathom only an
infamous part of it. So, the incompleteness of knowledge is something that we should get
used to it. The other problem is that knowledge is inherently uncertain, although to the
unadvised it may not look so. After all, not only in the Stone Age people died by eating
poisonous food, even today people die by eating poisonous mushrooms that look
identical with the eatable ones. Although for the advised the differences overwhelm the

13
This is not to talk about a different culture which is inferior to ours. We refer to that period as we refer to
the child in comparison with the grown adult. It is meant as an earlier stage of a historical process, not as a
different process.
13
apparent similarities between the so different (in terms of the consequences of eating
them) mushrooms, this certainty (of knowing for sure how to differentiate them) comes at
the cost of being fooled at least once by what we thought to be sure ground and proved to
be otherwise (not everyone must be fooled because, fortunately, knowledge can be
communicated).
This chapter will enquire about our doing so well in a world full of mystery and
surprise, about our abilities that permitted us such accomplishments. The line that will be
followed will be one of economic thought
14
. Precisely, what will be restated here, are
things said by I. Kirzner, who in turn developed and built on insights had by L. von Mises
and F. Hayek.

2. Homo Economicus

Survival is an important end, perhaps the most important one. Besides it we have
many other ends. But, we live in a world with limited resources. We can not accomplish
all our ends. Every moment we have to decide for what ends we should employ the
available means; and this is something every one of us must do. In the words of Kirzner:
The basis of the economic analysis of individual decision-making is found in its
economic aspect. Since the classic discussion by Lord Robbins (An Essay on the Nature
and Significance of Economic Science, 1932), the economic aspect of individual activity
has been understood in terms of the allocation of scarce means among competing ends.
Each individual is seen as confronted with an economic problem the problem of
selecting those courses of action, with respect to given means, that will secure the
fulfillment of as many goals (in order of their significance) as possible. This problem is
sometimes expressed as that of securing efficiency, or as maximizing goal
satisfaction.
15


14
Why this is chosen should not come as a surprise. After all, the economist is the one which is oriented, at
least implicitly, towards practices of maximization. He is the one which observes human practices in which
we are all involved, more or less. And so, by starting from concrete situations, rather than by mere
hypothesizing, he is in a better position to realize what abilities are those which permit us to be so
successful.
15
Competition and entrepreneurship, pg.32
14
The situation seems clear: we can choose with ease examples which show that we
are confronted with the economic problem. If we are in a supermarket, we have to
decide how to spend our money. If we are careful enough, then we could calculate what
the optimal course of action is (which will best satisfy our goals). All would come up to a
computational problem, of distributing the scarce means (the sum of money allocated for
shopping) between competing ends (the products we want to buy). Suppose that we want
to buy apples and oranges and that we have the same preference for both of them. Then,
the best course of action is to buy equal quantities of both. This course of action can be
decided by mechanical computation, by calculating how much money to spend on apples
and how much on oranges. If apples are twice more expensive than oranges, then we
should divide our budget by three, and use two parts for buying apples and one for
buying oranges. In this way we will optimally achieve our ends, of buying apples and
oranges, for which we have an equal preference. In the same situation, if we would spend
all our money on apples, we would not optimally achieve our given ends. To be sure, this
kind of calculus is not always that simple, but with given means and ends there is some
course of action which is best.
We can observe this kind of behavior whenever a person has some ends which he
tries to achieve. This can be misleading and could lead us to think that maximization is an
essential characteristic of our actions. But, we must overlook an important step to get this
picture. In Kirzners words:
Being broader than the notion of economizing, the concept of human action does
not restrict analysis of the decision to the allocation problem posed by the juxtaposition
of scarce means and multiple ends. The decision, in the framework of the human-action
approach, is not arrived at merely by mechanical computation of the solution to the
maximization problem implicit in the configuration of the given ends and means. It
reflects not merely the manipulation of given means to correspond faithfully with the
hierarchy of given ends, but also the very perception of the ends-mean framework
within which allocation and economizing is to take place
16
Now, the point can be put clearly. The allocation problem is indeed one of
choosing the optimal course of action. But, the choosing must be made between courses

16
Competition and entrepreneurship pg.33
15
of action that are predefined by the ends-mean framework. Once we suppose that the
ends-mean framework is already in place, we can calculate what employment of means
would best achieve the ends. But, to put emphasis on the method of maximization is not
to look at the whole picture. The optimal course of action within a given ends-mean
framework is optimal in respect only to that given framework, and leaving unanswered
the question of the adequacy of the framework itself does not shed much light on our
problem. The problem is that:
A multitude of economizing individuals each choosing with respect to given ends
and means cannot, without the introduction of further exogenous elements, generate a
market process (which involves systematically changing series of means available to
market participants)
17
By focusing on maximization, we necessarily leave out of the picture the first
step, that of how a specific ends-mean framework comes into place. It is true that we can
pick out any action and that we can evaluate it by its economic aspect. For any particular
action, given the ends-mean framework, we can decide if it is optimal. But, by doing this,
we can not answer how our ends-mean framework changes. We are compelled to let the
coming into place of the framework beyond our understanding. The point can be put in a
different vocabulary (that of the first chapter). At any moment, a person has a set of given
rules to which he is committed to. That he tries to follow those rules follows analytically,
because to be committed to a rule means just to try your best in following that rule.
Likewise, to be committed to an ends-mean framework means just to do your best in
reaching the ends by the means.
But, what is expressed by the quest for optimality in respect to a given ends-mean
framework can be traced back to the earlier step. Why are we committed to some rules
and not to others, why are we committed to some ends-mean framework and not to
others? Why, for example, when we think of someone that committed suicide we do not
think in the first place of how successful he followed his rule, of how optimally did he
achieve his ends? Why this kind of ends-mean framework is not chosen by the vast
majority of us? The answer is that we raise the problem of optimality only after we

17
Competition and Entrepreneurship pg.33
16
accepted that a specific ends-mean framework is in place and that the problem
concerning the adequacy of the framework itself is dealt at an earlier step.
If we would be omniscient, then things would be very simple. Our plans would be
absolutely correct and all that we would have to do were to wait for them to unfold
completely. Being omniscient, we would choose the best course of action for the
achievement of all our ends. Furthermore, there would not be any end that would prove
incorrect, in the sense that we would come to see that we should have not even tried to
achieve it.
Unfortunately we are not omniscient. Our knowledge is incomplete and uncertain.
We should always keep these characteristics before our eyes, because they are always
with us. But there are ways to obscure them, to lose sight of them. One of them is to put
emphasis on the economic problem, on the maximization aspect of our actions (in a
given ends-mean framework). With the framework being already given, we are
confronted with a puzzle type problem. We just have to search for the correct (optimal)
solution, which is already predefined by the framework. Of course some of us are better
at solving puzzles; some of us will find the optimal courses of action and others will not.
It may seem that this search for the optimal courses of action is the most important one,
that by solving this kind of problem we solve all there is to solve. Being in this paradigm,
we might think that the knowledge problem is reduced to calculating what the optimal
course of action is.
Let us get some perspective. We live in a world full of mystery and uncertainty.
Somehow we have to overcome this problem. We have to move in a familiar setting, so
we have to make it familiar. By establishing an ends-mean framework we accomplish
exactly this. We provide ourselves a setting for our action to take place. The ends-means
framework provides us the possibility for rational action, in the sense of action directed
towards the maximization of our ends (provided by that very framework). But we can
concern ourselves with maximization (in a given ends-mean framework) only as long as
we perceive that framework as adequate. We can try to maximize as long as we leave the
problem of uncertainty behind, because as long as an ends-mean framework would be
endowed with full-blooded uncertainty there would be no such thing as the optimal
course of action. So, establishing an ends-mean framework is a necessary precondition
17
for the very possibility of maximization. Thus, we must seek to understand maximization
by finding its place in the scheme which starts with the establishment of the framework
itself. By separating these two aspects and by looking for essential characteristics only in
the first one, we give up perspective and we get only uncorrelated pieces.

3. Homo Agens

Mises had this specific insight, of bridging the two steps: that of the very
perception of the ends-mean framework and that of maximizing in respect with a given
framework. He says:
We call contentment or satisfaction that state of a human being which does not
and cannot result in any action. Acting man is eager to substitute a more satisfactory
state of affairs for a less satisfactory. His mind imagines conditions which suit him better,
and his action aims at bringing about this desired state. The incentive that impels a man
to act is always some uneasiness. A man perfectly content with the state of his affairs
would have no incentive to change things. He would have neither wishes nor desires; he
would be perfectly happy. He would not act; he would simply live free from care.
But to make a man act, uneasiness and the image of a more satisfactory state
alone are not sufficient. A third condition is required: the expectation that purposeful
behavior has the power to remove or at least to alleviate the felt uneasiness. In the
absence of this condition no action is feasible. Man must yield to the inevitable. He must
submit to destiny.
These are the general conditions of human action. Man is the being that lives
under these conditions. He is not only homo sapiens, but no less homo agens.
18
The Misesian insight was about what sets off human action in the first place. He
started by noticing when a human being would not act. If we would be perfectly content
with how things are, then we would not want to change anything. We would not act.
Action becomes feasible only when we are not perfectly content. We act so much only
because we are not perfectly content. So, the necessary precondition for us to act is some
uneasiness. Would this uneasiness be absent, then we would not want to change anything.

18
Human Action pg 14-15
18
This uneasiness need not be specified in any way
19
, for it to play its specific role,
namely driving us to act. At this first step it is sufficient that we are not perfectly content,
for us to want to make a change. Our desire to change things starts from a negative
insight. We are in some condition and we know that it is not good enough, that it is not
perfect. And we know this in the sense of feeling uneasy about it. If this feeling would be
totally absent, then we would be completely happy. Indeed, this amounts exactly to the
complete absence of action, to the complete absence of uneasiness. That some uneasiness
is what drives us to act need not be justified positively. This is not a point about our
mental states and about our neuronal connexions. It is not a point that could be decided
by analyzing our brain. This uneasiness is a condition of possibility for action. Actions
change the world. So, in order to act we need to want to change the world. And wanting
to change the world is possible only if we are not perfectly content; and not being
perfectly content means that we are somehow uneasy about our current state. For if this
would not be so, then we would not want to change anything; we would not act. As long
as we act, we do it because we have this uneasiness.
The understanding of this point might be obscured if we see it only from our point
of view, that of acting humans. By seeing things only from our perspective, we run the
risk of not being able to see the specific role of action in our lives. By not getting enough
perspective we may become too puzzled by what is omnipresent in us, by action. But, by
keeping in mind the fact that there are other ways for human beings to live we can also
understand our way better. That Nirvana is a state in which action disappears from the
picture and that its purpose is exactly the removal of uneasiness could show us
something. Precisely, it could show that very different strategies can be employed for
achieving the same goal. That these two cultures are so different and at the same time are
human cultures can be traced back to one common primary goal (the removal of
uneasiness) and two very different strategies (withdrawal from the world by non-acting
and involving in the world by acting). So, uneasiness is indeed the condition of

19
That this uneasiness exists is arrived at by a transcendental deduction. The fact that we act shows that
there must be some uneasiness. But by this method we only reach this conclusion. If someone desires to be
more specific about this uneasiness, then it is up to him. If he think that it can be proved that a specific
uneasiness motivates every human being, then he is the one who has to make this point.
19
possibility for action, but action is just our (e.g. occidental) specific way with dealing
with the specific human problem (our uneasiness).
This unspecified uneasiness is the first condition of human action. The second one
is that of conceiving a more satisfactory state. This is a positive step. It consists in giving
a specific determination to that uneasiness. It consists in reducing the uneasiness to the
inexistence of the conceived state. This reduction is a methodological one. We need not
believe that once we accomplish the conceived state we will be perfectly content. It is
sufficient to believe that the accomplishment of that state is a small step towards the
removal of that uneasiness. Nevertheless, we must believe that that step is a good one;
that it will diminish our uneasiness once it is accomplished, or at least that it is possible to
diminish it in this way. This is the third condition: the expectation that purposeful
behavior has the power to remove or at least to alleviate the felt uneasiness
20
. Without
this our plans will remain idle. They would never be put to practice. We need to believe
that our plans could be carried out and that by being carried out they could make a
difference.
How this three condition link up together? How do they set off human action? To
answer these we should start with the second condition. This is the step where the ends-
mean framework comes into play. The ends-mean framework is sustained by the (at least
implicit) belief that it will help alleviate our uneasiness. The ends-mean framework is the
specific formal structure that our conceived states have. It bridges the gap between the
unspecified uneasiness and our concrete actions. We can act only in concrete and
determinate ways. So, if we are to have any hope of alleviating a complete indeterminate
uneasiness by acting in completely determinate ways, we have to bridge the gap
somehow. We need a way of discerning, of choosing between many possible actions.
And that unspecified uneasiness can not offer by itself criteria for choosing between
actions. In this case we would be at the mercy of pure luck. On the other hand, we learn
from experience that some actions are more apt at alleviating the uneasiness than others.
So, by acting without criteria we will not be better off either.
How does the establishment of an ends-mean framework help us? The ends-mean
framework is a formal structure which permits us to embed in it our past experience and

20
Human Action pg 14-15
20
also to take new guesses about what will alleviate our uneasiness. At the same time, it can
be evaluated with respect to our ultimate standard, the perceived level of uneasiness
itself. By establishing an ends-mean framework we temporarily suspend the
indeterminate character of our ultimate goal (the removal of uneasiness). This is so,
because our specific ends are seen as proxies for the ultimate goal. In this way, the
indetermination is pushed between the proxy and the ultimate goal and we can act in a
determinate environment. At this point, all we have to do is to get the best possible
combination of available means to achieve the given ends. And this amounts to solving
(by mechanical calculus) a maximization problem.
Only now, having in background this new image, we can see what the place of
maximization is. Maximizing amounts to reaching the proxy in the best possible way.
This is indeed something that some of was do better than others. But, which course of
action is better and which is the best can be decided precisely because the ends-mean
framework provides a positive criterion for this (specifically the accomplishment of the
end). But we should not forget some points. Firstly, by establishing a proxy we take only
a guess. J ust by choosing a proxy we are not necessarily making a step towards
alleviating our uneasiness. This can not be foreseen with certainty. Every time we choose
a proxy we hope that we chose wisely. Furthermore, if we are rational, then our past
experience must support this hope. But, even so, we can not be sure of our choice of ends
until we accomplish them (that they are not feasible we can see before accomplishment
too). After reaching the proxy that we set we are again face to face with our ultimate
goal. The step that we made might have taken us closer or farther from our ultimate goal.
This is something we can only decide by perceiving our level of uneasiness. Now we
must start the process again and we must establish a new ends-framework, and with that a
new proxy. Designing the new framework, we can embed in it the past experience of
designing the old frameworks and of the points where they led us. And for sure, besides
adjusting what did not function as expected, we will introduce some completely new
elements in our framework.
In conclusion, every one of the three conditions is necessary. The first condition is
the one which provides the very possibility for human action. Furthermore, it serves us as
the ultimate standard for evaluating our actions. In absence of such a standard our actions
21
would be just uncorrelated pieces of behavior. This standard makes possible an entirely
human activity, that of Human Action
21
. Only against the background of this activity,
particular actions make sense. The second condition permits the existence of a structure
in which we can embed our past experience and our new guesses. This structure is the
stable ground we need to be more than drifters on the winds of chance. Nevertheless, this
structure is only formal. Now the third and final condition comes into play. It amounts to
our distinctive feature and power, that of deciding to face the world, to involve actively
into it. This decision precedes every act of ours. Without it we could not bring anything
into existence. That we are not conscious of its omnipresence means only that we got too
used with it. Our world, the World of Action starts only when we decide to start filling it
with actions. That this is possible only against a background of an ultimate goal which
will (probably) be always before us and that we tamed our power by imposing a specific
structure on it is something that we can only acknowledge for the time being.

4. We as Entrepreneurs

In this section we will apply what has been said in the previous section to the real
situations. We will see how humans move within the framework of Human Action. This
will help us understand with clarity how we manage to do so well in the world. To
recount with the help of Kirzners words:
Human action, in the sense developed by Mises, involves courses of action taken
by the human being to remove uneasiness and to make himself better off. The
decision, in the framework of the human-action approachreflects not merely the
manipulation of given means to correspond faithfully with the hierarchy of given ends,
but also the very perception of the ends-mean framework within which allocation and
economizing is to take placeMisess homo agens is endowed not only with the
propensity to pursue goals efficiently, once ends and means are clearly identified, but
also with the drive and alertness needed to identify which ends to strive for and which
means are available. Now I choose to label that element of alertness to possibly newly

21
Human Action as an activity is more that the sum of all actions. It consists also in the pragmatic context
that makes every action appropriate or not.
22
worthwhile goals and to possibly newly available resources the entrepreneurial element
in human decision-making. It is this entrepreneurial element that is responsible for our
understanding of human action as active, creative, and human rather than as passive,
automatic, and mechanical.
22
In a world of perfect knowledge the circumstances of a decision are known with
certainty. Here, the decision will always come up to selecting the optimal course of action
in respect to those circumstances. That course will be followed mechanical, at every step
in the process being perfectly clear what should be done. In such a world, where there is
no place for error, decisions will be indeed mechanical. But we live in a different world,
of incomplete knowledge and of uncertainty. It is incomplete because there are many
things we do not know yet and it is uncertain because every bit of knowledge can turn out
not to be so.
Let us take an example. Suppose that we have two markets A and B. In market A
the price for a certain product is 10 monetary units. In market B the price for the same
product is 5 monetary units. Initially the users (sellers and buyers) of the markets do not
know of the existence of the other market. In this case, if someone would have
knowledge of the existence of both markets he could grasp the opportunity for pure
profit. He could buy the product from market B with 5 monetary units and sell it in
market A for 8 monetary units. Thus, he will make a profit of 3 monetary units. It is
important to notice that this opportunity is already there, before our entrepreneur in fact
grasps it. The opportunity appears (in the sense of becoming visible for someone) when
something that is already in place is perceived by some alert individual. The opportunity
is already there because buyers from market A will readily offer to buy the product for 8
monetary units and sellers from market B will readily offer to sell the product for 6
monetary units. But neither one of them knows of the other. The one who discovers this
bit of knowledge grasps an opportunity for pure profit that was already there, but that
nobody has perceived yet.
For our entrepreneur to actually act for grasping the opportunity the three
Misesian conditions must be met. Firstly, he must be interested in finding opportunities.
Secondly, he must be capable of noticing opportunities. Thirdly, he must actually go on

22
Competition and Entrepreneurship pg.33-35
23
to grasp the perceived opportunities. Of course there is a difference between acting for
grasping a perceived opportunity and succeeding in grasping it. In the first place, the
perceived opportunity may not be a real opportunity (i.e. the real price from market B is
also 10, but our man was misinformed). In the second place, he must be able to develop
an adequate ends-mean framework which will lead him to grasp the opportunity (i.e. he
must find also the means to buy the product from market B, the means to reach market A
and so on). In the third place, although the perceived opportunity was real when it was
perceived, it must be so also when our entrepreneurs actions get him to the point where
he can actually grasp the opportunity (i.e. when he reaches the market A he finds out that
other people where faster than he and that the price is now already 6). All this steps must
be carried out successfully for him to successfully grasp the opportunity. And the final
success depends in part on his abilities and in part on luck. For example it may be of no
use the fact that he manages to find the optimal course of action in respect to his ends-
mean framework or that, given his context, he chose the best framework. Even so, there
may be others who are in an objectively better position to grasp that opportunity (i.e.
another entrepreneur has already purchased the product from market B, when the first
entrepreneur perceives the opportunity). Thus, in many cases the entrepreneurs abilities
can make the difference between success and failure. Nevertheless, the external factors
(luck, if we look from the point of view of the entrepreneur in case) can also make the
difference. This is so precisely because we live in a world of incomplete knowledge and
uncertainty. And our knowledge has an inherent guessing component in it. By extending
our knowledge and by developing our abilities we can become better guessers, but we
can never leave the possibility of surprise behind.
At this point, we should say a few words about two different knowledge
problems
23
. Both stem from the incompleteness of knowledge. The first problem appears
when we devise an over-optimistically plan (i.e. due to incomplete information we may
believe that we could sell a product at a very high price). In this case we presuppose that
some things are true when in fact they are not, that some things will obtain when in fact
they will not. This type of problem tends to be self-revealing. At some point, the plan will
be revealed as untenable. We will not reach the expected outcome, we will be

23
I.Kirzner Knowledge problems and their solutions
24
disappointed. In this way we will acquire new information which will help us in
redesigning our plans. When some plan will not get carried away successfully we will
know for sure that we have a problem and we can start finding solutions
24
.
The second problem appears when we devise an unduly pessimistic plan (i.e. due
to incomplete information we believe that we could sell only at very low prices). In this
case we do not presuppose that some things will obtain, when in fact they could have
obtained. This type of problem is not self-revealing. Our plans will get carried out
successfully. The problem is that they could have been carried out even more
successfully (in the sense that by devising a better plan we would have obtained more
profit). This kind of problem will not be necessarily revealed and corrected. What we
may fail to know today (when we are devising the plan), we may nevertheless continue to
fail to know tomorrow.
So, it is sufficient that we devise a plan for the first type of problem (if there is the
case that such a problem exists in that case) to reveal itself sooner or later. By devising a
plan we have done our part concerning the revealing of this type of problem. Now, it is
up to reality to refuse to comply to our over-optimistically plans and thus to reveal to us
that we have a problem. The second problem is not so easy to reveal. We may say that
reality is very happy that we demand to little of it and will not show anything to us in this
case. Put into other words, the bad plans will reveal themselves as bad by not being
successful, but every successful plan is not necessarily the best plan. We must actively
search for better plans. Overcoming the first problem helps us embed in our future plans
knowledge obtained from past experience (i.e. knowledge obtained by confronting the
expected results with the actual results and by adjusting our expectations to what
happened). Overcoming the second problem is a different process. Here we can not
compare the expected and actual results because they are identical. The only possible way
to overcome this problem is to introduce genuine new elements in our plans, to take blind
guesses about what the reality is and about what plans will be more successful. Once we

24
Of course if a plan does not get carried away successfully, then it does not necessarily mean that the plan
was bad. It may also be the case that the problem is on our part, on our failure to carry it. But the point is
that whenever a plan is devised over-optimistically, it will tend to lead to disappointments on our part (of
course luck can play a part, but a plan that is carried away successfully, will be employed systematically in
the future also; and if its success is due only to luck this will be clear when luck will not play a role
anymore).
25
successfully overcome this problem, we can also embed new knowledge in our future
plans. But this knowledge is obtained not by analyzing past experience and by removing
the parts that made us expect too much
25
, but by introducing genuine new elements in our
plans, and by testing the new plans.
Someone need not be an entrepreneur to overcome the first problem (although he
must be an entrepreneur in order to devise the plan in the first place). He must only be
willing to remove parts from a plan that is already in place, until he successfully removes
the parts that led him to overly-optimistic expectations. But the overcoming of the second
problem calls for entrepreneurial decision-making, namely the decision to introduce
genuine new parts in the plan, parts that were not there before. And this type of decision
always involves a blind guessing on the part of the decision-maker. Introducing genuine
new elements always involves a blind guessing, which can be verified only afterwards,
by putting the new plan to work.
As long as we devise plans and as long as we modify our plans by introducing
genuine new elements into them we are entrepreneurs. Being entrepreneurs is our best
strategy of coping with a world full of uncertainty and of enlarging our knowledge about
it. Being entrepreneurs we have to take decisions, even if anyone of them could turn out
to be incorrect. But, with every new decision, with every new plan we take a new chance,
we make a new guess. As long as we are apt to carry the process further we can hope to
succeed in our guesses and to never repeat the mistakes.


25
In a case of a plan that did not carried out successfully we have of course the possibility of keeping the
ends unchanged, and introducing new means in the plan, thus making it work. But this will amount to
overcoming the second type of problem, not the first type. Nevertheless, we can separate the two problems
if we proceed analytically. The first problem can be overcome by adjusting the ends so that the new plan
will be carried out successfully. The adjustment of ends amounts to removing parts from them until the
expectations become low enough for them not to be invalidated anymore. Afterwards, by introducing new
means and by (re)introducing the old ends we can indeed devise a successful plan. But this amounts to
changing a successful plan (the one that was reshaped by the adjustment of ends) with a new one, hoping
that it will be more successful. That in changing the plan we do not introduce only genuine new parts, but
we also reintroduce some other parts does not change the type of problem that we try to overcome. It is still
the second type of problem that we are trying to overcome at this point. And this is so because we
introduced genuine new elements into the plan. And genuine means not absolutely new in respect to every
plan that was ever devised, but with respect only to the first plan that faced the first type of problem.
Introducing a genuine new part does not mean that that part is new as a part, irrelevant of the plans in
which it figured, but only that is new in respect with a specific ends-mean framework (that by introducing
that part in a specific framework we can not predict the outcome because the framework obtained is
genuinely new and this is due to the introduction of that specific part).
26
5. Conclusion

This chapter was about how we manage to live in a world full of mystery, about
how we are able to learn to do better in this world. The answer was that we are
entrepreneurs; that we have to make many steps into the unknown to shed some light
there; that we are motivated in our journey by some undefined uneasiness; that we chose
as a safety device a specific formal structure the ends-mean framework; that with the
help of it we can trace back our steps into unknown that is our decisions; that with the
help of our safety device (the ends-mean framework) and of our guiding device (the felt
uneasiness) we can systematically learn to make wise steps; but that, nevertheless we can
not be certain of anyone of our steps, which are still steps into the unknown.






























27
III. Chapter Three The conceptual realm as interplay between rules and
decisions

1. Introduction

What have all the games in common? Do they share a common essence in virtue
of which we name all of them games? Do they all have something in common? Till the
later Wittgenstein it was possible to give an affirmative answer to these questions and
then to go on in search of that common essence. But, Wittgenstein showed in a powerful
manner that this is not the case. There is no such thing as the common essence of all the
games, as the platonic idea of Game. There are only games and games.
If we want to describe a game so to grasp its quintessence how shall we proceed?
Let us imagine an essentialist who is trying to enlighten us and show us the way. He is
new in our community; he never played or heard of any games. He says that it will
suffice to observe a few games and then he will tell us what the essence that all games
share is. So we will take him to a particular game, a football match. After watching the
first half he could say that football is a game because it is played between two sides and
the point is to defeat the other side. But, immediately we can take him to watch a game
which does not conform to this definition. Of a game which is played by more than two
sides or of a game which point is not to be won. Of course, our essentialist friend would
insist that to discover the essence that all games share is a difficult process, one of trial
and error, that the first definition was just the first step. After every new example he
would refine his definition so to obtain a concept that could be correctly applied to every
case we present to him. Of course, we can not expect from him perfection, he can be
wrong; after all he is only human. He could say about something that it is a game only to
realize afterwards that he was mistaken. After watching him with his complicated, almost
scientific endeavor, we may be a bit confused because for ordinary people it seems very
easy to recognize if something is a game. Or, about an unclear case, they do not think too
much before deciding if that dubious activity is worthy to be called a game. Being late
for dinner because we kept bugging him with new cases which called over and over for a
refined definition, he may take a stand, although with a raised voice. He will say that the
28
process is now complete, that he gathered enough information, that the essence of the
game is now grasped. And that it is completely in vain to present him new cases because
things are as clear as the deepest azure summer sky. If the new case does not conform to
his definition, it is too bad for that case. It will never be worthy to be called a game, for
games are just the ones which conform to ours friend definition. Although we could ask
him why we needed to go from venue to venue in search of the essence that now he
proclaims with a raised voice, when he could have done that from the beginning, we need
not take this line of attack, because the odds are in our favor now.
In the journey we took together, we also have done some thinking. Being true
friends, for some time we imagined ourselves in a world where our friend is right. In this
way, we could see what would follow if we would think that there really is a common
essence of all games. In the first place, we would like to ask our friend some questions.
On the ontological side, we would like to ask if something can participate to only one
essence or to many and in the second case to how many. On the epistemological side, we
would like to ask how can we find to which essences does it participate or how can we
know that we found all of them. Thinking about these questions the first thing that comes
to mind is that by postulating all this essences we did not solve anything. At what does it
help to say that all games share a common essence? Why should we not restrict ourselves
to what we perceive, to particular games that have similarities and differences between
them? Why should we not start from here?
What Wittgenstein saw was that if we look to many games we will see that they
have family resemblances. There is not any property that belongs to all of them and in
virtue of which they are games. The second part is important. Because it can happen that
all the games played in a certain community consist in doing something with a ball. The
important point is that even in this case we can imagine the invention of a new activity
which does not consist in doing something with a ball and which, nevertheless, the
community decides to call it a game. At this moment, it should be said, though, that
although Wittgenstein is an enemy of nave essentialism, he is not a friend of the
relativists either
26
. Put into better words: the insight that Wittgenstein had was not a

26
Wittgenstein has an argument against the possibility of private language. If we switch from a single
person (which can not have a private language) to a single community, what has changed? If the argument
29
relativistic one. It was just an insight of someone who went farther than anyone before
into the depths of the dark waters of language. An insight of the flexibility of language, as
a tool which can be at the same time perfectly rigid and also which can be used to
account for the immense diversity that can be grasped through it.
At this point, let us remind an interesting moment in the journey we took with our
friend. In the final part of our journey, after watching many different games, we took him
by surprise and stumbled upon yet another football match. The last bit of enthusiasm our
friend had vanished when he saw that we took him to the same game! He asked us
angrily if were trying to make fun of him or what else could be the point of taking him to
a game which he already watched and thoroughly analyzed, extracting every bit of
essence out of him? With a candid voice we whispered to him: But look! They have
different shirts! And also the grass is greener! We need not go deeper into the story,
because our point is made. Our friend, with all his serious look of a man who came to
discover some essences, got a little carried by the wind; he behaved like an ordinary man.
Because for ordinary men, not only to see all those different activities as being all games
is, in general, a simple task, but also the capacity to pass over the many irrelevant
differences is something fully within their reach.
It seems that we are continuously praising the ordinary man, with his ability of
discerning relevant from irrelevant differences and resemblances. It must be asked why
this is so? Why the application of a concept (in this case that of game) is usually an
ability fully within the reach of an ordinary man? To answer this question it is clear that
we can not make use of any complicated activities usually associated with philosophical
practice.
The answer to this question will complete the picture of what is distinctive of us,
humans. The raw materials developed in the first two chapters will be used in giving this

against private language is sound in the case of a single person, why would it not be sound in the case of a
single community? If a person is helpless without external standards, why this would not be the same in the
case of a community? After all, a community is just a sum of persons which interact. If the switch from one
person to a community is enough for securing the possibility of language, then this is so because for each
person become available external standards. A private language is impossible not because it is the language
of a person, but because it is one of a single entity which can not have access to a different perspective. It
would be very strange indeed if Wittgenstein would have agreed with the relativistic picture of seeing a
community as a single person which, without external standards, nevertheless has a language (and a private
language indeed).
30
answer. We will show that the use of concepts is an ability that is indeed within the reach
of every human. This is so precisely because the use of concepts is nothing else than the
result of our abilities of following rules and of choosing what rules to follow.

2. The Wittgensteinian and Sellarsian insight

The insight that was already mentioned is that of the great flexibility of language
and at the same time of its rigidity. Let us recount the moment when we took our friend
to another football game and we justified our decision by pointing to outrageously
irrelevant differences. The point is that with the help of complicated theoretical
constructions we can make every difference look as a relevant one. But now we face a
dilemma. On one hand, if we would not have the possibility of selecting new differences
as being relevant, then we would be at a loss in explaining how our language evolves. On
the other hand, if we could not find a way for selecting some differences as relevant
rather than others, then we could not even start the whole process; we would be stuck
before the first step, being puzzled by the infinity of choices that we have in front of us.
So, the insight starts from the fact that we actually succeed in steering through the horns
of this dilemma. In what follows, we will show how we manage to accomplish this task.
Furthermore, we will show that by steering through this dilemma we also manage to sail
into our mysterious world.
Firstly, let us recall a classical distinction: that of token/type. The classroom
presentation of this distinction is along these lines: if we look at the word apple we can
count the letters in two different ways. We can count five tokens and four types. In this
word, the type p is instantiated two times; we have two tokens of p. So, the type is
what can be instantiated in every token that falls under it. Conversely, the tokens are the
instantiations of types. If in a sentence we have the word the for three times, then we
have three tokens of that type. This distinction can be applied to every sort of entity we
wish. What is the utility of this distinction, we may wish to ask? Apart of being
something which can be observed by someone who is interested in the functioning of
language, does it do something in particular? As with any answer, we can choose the
level of complexity which suffices us. In the present context, a simple one should do. The
31
role of this distinction is exactly to make possible the coexistence of rigidity and
diversity, because we have both of them at both levels, of types and tokens. On one hand,
every type is a type among many and the very possibility of recognizing something as a
type presupposes that it is perfectly distinct from all the others. A discussion of the
criteria that permits us to individuate these types is not relevant at this moment. Of
primary importance is that at the level of types every type can be differentiated from
every other. On the other hand, every token is a token among many identical others
which fall together under the same type. Again, the criteria for discerning the tokens that
fall under the same type are irrelevant. Here, of primary importance is that the tokens of
the same type are perfectly identical, all off them being imbued with the distinctiveness
of their type.
A classical strategy for trying to make account for the power of language could be
to see the categories of type and token as ontological distinct; to give ontological primacy
to the first one, to put the types in heaven and the tokens on earth. We are merely humans
and the World of Ideas is too far and too great for us to have an easy and direct access to
it. We should consider ourselves lucky if we can copy it, if we can instantiate through
earthly tokens the heavenly types. It doesnt matter that for bridging the gap between
heaven and earth we need a magic wand, or better, that we should keep quiet on this
matter altogether.
Maybe it will be of some help to get back to the disagreement with our friend
concerning the relevance of the differences between the two football matches. Let us
remember that he was trying to discover the essence of the game. How did he know for
sure that the two football games are the same in that context? Maybe Sellars will be of
help:
The psychologistic blunder with respect to means is related to another
fundamental error, that, namely, of confusing between (1) language as a descriptive
category for which symbols are empirical classes to which certain events belong (and
hence are symbol-events) by virtue of performing an empirical function, with (2)
language as an epistemological category for which the relation of type to token is not
that of empirical class to member
32
For the moment it will help clarify the epistemological distinction between
symbol-types and symbol-tokens, if we think of the former as norms or standards, and of
the latter as events which satisfy them. We can therefore, for the moment at least,
contrast the above two senses of language as the descriptive and the normative
respectively. Making use of this distinction, we argue that meaning or, better
designation is a term belonging to language about languages in the second sense. Its
primary employment is therefore in connection with linguistic expressions as norms.
27
Maybe an example should be given to clarify the distinction. Let us take the term
red. The descriptive sense of language picks out all red objects as members of the
empirical class red. Every member of the class red belongs in this class in virtue of
performing an empirical function (e.g. of emitting a certain length-wave radiation). In the
descriptive sense, the identification step already took place. For classifying an event as a
member of a certain class the identification of the relevant set of properties must be
already done. Afterwards a class groups together all the events which share some set of
properties. Using the language in the descriptive sense amounts to describing some event
as a member of a class (for which the symbol stands for). The epistemological sense of
language puts emphasis on a different point. Red used in the epistemological sense
stands for the type red. The relation between type and token is different from the
relation between class and member. A type is a rule. By correctly applying a type (that is
by successfully following that rule) we obtain a token of that type. Thus, a token is what
is obtained by successfully following a rule. A type does not group together its tokens in
the sense a class group together its members. To obtain every token we must correctly
apply the type. In the type-token relation the emphasis is put on the normative aspect. We
must be able to follow the rule if we are to have any tokens of that rule. This ultimately
amounts to our practical ability of grasping the difference between correct and incorrect
applications of a rule. Thus, grasping the meaning of red (that is using red in the
epistemological sense) amounts to the practical ability of correctly applying the rule
expressed in the epistemological use of red
Our friend was looking for that essential property(es) which every game has and
in virtue of which every particular game is a member of the class of games. He used

27
W.Sellars Realism and the New Way of Words
33
language in the descriptive manner. He presupposed that games form a class and that
every particular game is a member of that class. One possibility would be that every
game shares a set of common properties and that that set defines the class of games. In
his search he was trying to discover the properties of this set. The simplest strategy of this
kind is to see the having of every property of the set as being a necessary condition for
belonging to the class of games. In this way, by looking at new instances of games we
can eliminate accidental properties (because we see that some properties are instantiated
only in some cases, not in all of them). At some point we would succeed in eliminating
every accidental property and thus, we would obtain the essential set of properties which
every game has; and in virtue of which it is a game.
An improved strategy is to talk about family resemblances. It amounts at saying
that the members of a class do not have to share exactly the same set of properties for
them to belong to that class; that the rule for belonging to a class need not be a
conjunctive one, that it may be a disjunctive one; that for a class to be well formed it is
sufficient a transitive relation between its members (i.e. a member of a class must share
the following set of properties abVbcVcdVde). Wittgenstein had a descriptive point when
he talked about family resemblances. He observed that many of our concepts function in
this loose way; that for something to be a member of a certain class it need not share a
common (conjunctive) set of properties with all the other members. It should be noted
though, that this is not a normative point; it does not amount to saying that all our
concepts should function in this way. It is just an observation of how our concepts in fact
function; that applications of the same concept, although they do not share a set of
common properties, nevertheless are applications of the same concept.
At this point we should answer two questions. First, why the use of concepts is
not governed by the same type of rules every time (some concepts are based on a
common set of properties, others are based on family resemblances etc.)? Second, what
kind of essentialism is rejected by observing that many concepts are based on family
resemblances?
In answering the first question we should remember that concepts are themselves
just rules. By employing a concept we follow a rule, for we can apply every concept
correctly or incorrectly. So, when we talk about rules that govern the use of concepts we
34
talk about rules that govern the use of some type of rules. If concepts were some kind of
empirical objects, then it would make sense to search for the class to which they
belonged. But they are not objects. Furthermore, we have seen already (in chapter one)
that the essential normative ingredient of rules must be sought at the pragmatic level. So,
when we ask what we should do according to some explicit rule we should seek the
answer at the pragmatic level. The common normative ingredient found in every rule is
not some ultimate explicit meta-rule. This kind of regress, as we have already seen, can
not be stopped. What is common to all concepts, as rules, is the normative ingredient. Of
course, as a special type of rules, concepts must have something in common that
differentiates them from other types of rules. Thus, the quest for finding the special
ingredient that makes them concepts, not just rules, is legitimate. But, searching for it in
the genetic of concepts might not be the best strategy. It would amount at trying to find a
specific normative ingredient in a descriptive land. Let us suppose that all our concepts
would be based on a common set of properties that would be found out in every
application of that respective concept. What would be relevant on the normative level in
this case? Precisely, that concepts could be applied (correctly or incorrectly); that we
would have criteria for applying them (looking for the particular instances that present
the common set of properties). But, at this point, nothing could stop us in finding
different criteria that would do the same job. Maybe we could think that the first criterion
is too rigid; that we could make good use of a weaker type of similarity. By letting a
concept be based on family resemblances we enrich our conceptual reservoir. We obtain
new concepts that nevertheless are concepts because they are formed with the help of
precise criteria; and they are precise precisely because we can grasp the difference
between correct and incorrect applications. Also, it should be said that we can not choose
a priori between criteria; that they are good as long as they can be applied; and that this
ultimately amounts to possessing the practical ability to do so.
What was the mistake of our essentialist friend? The sound insight he had was
that concepts really work. The mistake was to explain this success by the use of the
specific criterion. Thus, he had to embark on an impossible quest: that of explaining the
successful employment of concepts by the use of a specific criterion that did work. It
amounted to confusing something sufficient for being also necessary. What Wittgenstein
35
noticed was that it is not necessary to use an essentialist criterion for a concept to be
employed successfully. And he saw this by observing that in practice many of our
concepts are not based on essentialist criteria. Concepts do their job so well not because
we found the single criterion which makes this possible, but because we succeeded in
finding criteria that work; and for a criterion to work we must posses the practical ability
of applying it correctly. Wittgenstein managed to see through the irrelevant details. He
saw that for a concept to function it is needed a criterion that makes possible this
functioning; and that a specific criterion is ultimately just our succeeding in putting the
normative at work. In contrast, our essentialist friend mistook a specific criterion for what
makes any criteria to work: our practical ability of discerning between correct and
incorrect applications of it.
Now, we can answer how our friend knew that the two football games were two
tokens of the same type. Let us remember what he was trying to do. He was searching for
the essence of game. He thought that this essence consists in some essential properties
that are to be found in every game. Of course, he knew that there are many kinds of
games, for example football games. They have an essence of their own which is formed
by the core essence of game plus a few other specific properties of the football game. In
his quest he tried to find the essence of game by eliminating the accidental properties
specific to special kinds of games (which were essential for those special kinds of
games). We might call his strategy a bottom-up strategy because he started from specific
games and tried to isolate the essence of game. But his strategy was not bottom-up all
the way down. He started from specific types of games
28
. At some level he had to make
what we think that is the really important step. He made use of the practical ability of
applying concepts. Before starting to examine every kind of game, he already applied the
respective concept. He secured his ground by recognizing in a particular situation the
instantiation of a certain type. When we took him to the first football venue he used his
ability of applying concepts, specifically that of football game. Thus, afterwards he
could select the relevant properties that make something be a football game. But he could

28
For this point I have to thank to Mr. Marian Panait, who in a short discussion made it in a somehow
different context.
36
have never made that step if he did not have the practical ability of recognizing
29

something as a token of some type. The reason we took him to another football game was
exactly this. We tried to show him that he looks for something that is not the really
important point; that the important point is that we can apply concepts and that we do this
without the help of essences of the kind he was after. Furthermore, that his insight was
good but that he searched for it in the wrong way. Indeed every concept has an essence,
but this amounts to our practical ability of discerning correct from incorrect applications
of it. Also, even if we manage to explicitate this practical ability in terms of an essential
set of properties (which will define the class of games), we would analyze only a
corpse. And this will never explain how the living organism works.

3. The role of decisions in the conceptual realm

In this section we will explain what has been left unexplained in the previous
section; we will see how the living organism works; we will see how concepts function.
In doing this we will build upon the insight that applying concepts amounts to the
practical ability of discerning between correct and incorrect application of a rule.
Furthermore, we will see how decisions fit in the conceptual picture.
Let us take an example. Imagine a child who never got out of his home yet. All
the chairs in his home have four legs; no other object in his home has four legs. His
parents teach him the concept chair extensionally by telling him which objects are
chairs and also by showing him what is their utility. Furthermore, trying to protect him
from sitting on unsuitable objects they tell him that only chairs can be sat upon. Let us
suppose that for our child chair means from now on an object which has exactly four
legs and which can be sat upon. In his home environment this concept does its job
perfectly. By applying the concept chair he succeeds in identifying an object which can

29
This use of recognize although natural might be very misleading. This ability is not that of recognizing
something that already is in front of us and independent of us; it is not about passively recognizing
something; on the contrary it is about actively applying a concept, actively following a rule. This use of
recognize refers to something that could not be without our making it so. To recognize a token as
belonging to a certain type, we must first be able to apply that type.
37
be sat upon every time he wants
30
. Suppose now that he gets into another environment. In
this new environment there are only three-legged chairs. When he wants to sit our child
starts looking for a chair. For this, he starts to apply his concept of chair. Now, he does
not have much success. In the beginning, he does not find anything wrong with his
concept. After all, in his home environment it did its job perfectly. But, after a while he
becomes a little tired. Furthermore, he notices that other people sit on the strange three-
legged objects. At this point our child will have some decisions to make. His concept of
chair that fared so well at home is not of any use in the new situation. So, what are his
choices? He could decide to keep his concept of chair unchanged. In this case he could
also decide to form a new concept schair which will have as its applications the strange
three-legged objects. Or he could decide that forming a new concept for coping with the
strange objects is not appropriate at all. He could also decide that the similarities between
the four legged-objects and the three-legged ones are much more important than the
differences between them. Thus, he could decide to modify his concept of chair so that
the three-legged objects will become also chairs. Or he could decide that the similarities
are indeed much more important, but that the old concept was flawed in a serious way;
and that he should form an altogether new concept that will have as its applications the
four-legged and three-legged objects. Or he could decide that the number of legs is
indeed an irrelevant feature and that the new concept should not specify anything about
it. And so on. The number of decisions our child faces is great. And neither one of them
has already the label correct put on it. What matters is that his decisions will shape his
world
31
.

30
Someone might say that if our child would have been smart enough, then he would have realized that the
two features (that of having four legs and that of being sittable) are independent and thus, that there is no
point in employing a concept that puts them together. First, we would like to say that we are not interested
in what would happen only if someone is smart enough. Second and most important, he is wrong in
thinking that our child could know that the two features are independent on a priori grounds. To take
another example, imagine a primitive man who saw for the first time a fire, after lighting struck a tree. He
also had the chance of using that fire. But how could he know that fire can be obtained by other means too?
Our Universe could have been different so that fire could appear only by lighting. Our primitive man could
just hope that fire could be replicated and with some luck he stumbled upon means for doing exactly this.
In conclusion, to think that being smart enough could do the job of experience is wrong because it amounts
to think that we can know a priori what can be known only a posteriori.
31
Let us suppose that we meet some alien creatures. They can not see (they have other senses), but they
can classify objects with the help of a device. Now, suppose that we tell them about red apples, which we
can only identify visually, and they tell us about some strange things which have a certain index according
to their device. So, we tell them about some type of objects, and they tell us about a different one. Imagine
38
A concept is a rule. We live in a mysterious world. Every day we face a number
of situations. If we would think that every situation is completely new, then we would
have no use for concepts. What use we would have for rules that are adequate for only
one case
32
? But, we do not think this way. Instead, we think that between different
situations we might find relevant similarities; that what was appropriate in one case will
be appropriate in a sufficient similar case. If similarities are also important, then we could
make good use of rules that grasp those similarities. By forming a new concept we decide
that some similarities are relevant. By successfully applying a concept we obtain cases
that are similar in respect to that concept. Thus, by forming a concept we can treat new
cases as old ones. This is useful because we can repeat the good steps and avoid the bad
ones we made until now.
Let us suppose that we have three situations a1, a2 and a3 and that we decide that
they are similar in a relevant way. Thus, we introduce a new concept A. From all our past
situations, the new concept A applies only to a1, a2, a3. Of course, we need the practical
ability of forming such a concept, which will discriminate the three situations from every
other existing situation. But, let us suppose that we accomplish this task. The point of
introducing the concept A would be to make use of the knowledge obtained in the three
cases in future situations (we want to be able recognize in the future chairs because we
know that we can sit on them). So, the point of introducing concept A is for applying it in
the future cases a4, a5 etc
33
. The future cases a4 and a5 will share the same similarities

now that we bring a few red apples to our friends, and they bring us a few objects with the respective index.
With great surprise we see that they brought red apples, and they realize that we brought objects with the
same index as theirs. In this case, we may wonder if our rules for picking up the respective objects are still
different rules or maybe there are only different forms of the same rule. But wondering would not solve
anything. We have to decide that things stay in some way or another and afterwards new experience might
or might not back up our decision (for example if the aliens put together by using their device yellow
bananas too, we would be inclined to think that they use the same rules as us; but if they put in the same
group ten yellow bananas and three green apples, we would for sure start to wonder about the kind of rules
they are using).

32
We can imagine many scenarios very different from the one we usually use. For example, we can
imagine that someone decides to form 1000 new concepts every day. Furthermore he decides that only this
matters. So, even if he would recognize situations in which the application of an old concept would be
appropriate, he would choose to form a new concept instead. We could not even say to him that he is not
rational. He could be very rational in achieving his end; he could devise an adequate schedule which would
permit him to form exactly 1000 new concepts every day. This kind of example shows that our decisions
could lead us on very different paths.
33
Wittgenstein says: But I dont mean that what I do now (in grasping a sense) determines the future use
causally and as a matter of experience, but that in a queer way, the use itself is already present. The use is
39
that made us introduce concept A. Put differently, by introducing the concept A we select
some relevant features that make a1, a2 and a3 applications of that concept. Furthermore,
the concept A specifies what we ought to do in similar future cases like a4 and a5. Now,
let us suppose that we face a new situation. This is the moment for taking some decisions.
We have to decide for example if we met the case a4
34
or if we have to deal with a
different case b. If we decide that indeed we face the case a4, then we know what we
ought to do; and if we think that the application of the concept A is appropriate
35
in this
situation and then, if we manage to apply it correctly, then we will apply concept A. But
this is a decision for us to make; and we have many other options like the child in our
example had. Even if we have a strong disposition to apply the concept A in the new
situation, this is not enough. We also have to think that our disposition is reliable
36
. Our
dispositions have their place among the factors we have to take into consideration before
making a decision.
At this moment, it should be said once more what we mean by decision. In the
normal use decision refers only to situations where the alternatives are more or less in
equilibrium. Only in these cases the decision comes fully in the spot light; only in these
cases we become fully aware that we must make a decision; that we are at a crossroad
and we have to decide which way we should go. In such cases we might start to whisper:
I have to decide what to do!. But we should not be fooled to think that decisions come
to play only in such difficult cases. A decision comes to play every time we could have
done otherwise. That we know our way and we do not stop at every crossroad does not
mean that there are not any crossroads there.

already present in the sense that all possible cases of application are in the same relation with the respective
concept. And this is the same for the past cases as well as for possible future cases like a4, a5. The problem
that we will face, though, is to decide when it is appropriate to use that concept; when it is the case that a4.
This could amount to deciding if it is appropriate to use concept A or if it is appropriate to see a certain
case as a4.
34
When we introduced concept A, the case a4 did not stood for a real case, but for a future possible one. It
meant only that it is the next case of application of concept A. Whether or when will happen to be the case
that a4 was not specified.
35
Let us take the case of an object. For something to be recognized as an object, first we need to apply the
concept object. If we apply it correctly, then we can go on and apply further concepts that will specify the
type of object. But an object can be specified in multiple ways at the same time. An object might be
specified as a chair, or as made of wood etc. if the concept A is chair, then we could meet case a4 in a
situation when we are looking for a wooden object not for a chair. In this case, although we will recognize
the case as being a4, we will not actually apply the concept A.
36
If someone takes a drug which distorts the visual perception then he would be justified in resisting to
commit himself to the existence of the strange beings he sees, although he sees them very clearly.
40
Thus, in the conceptual realm we see at work the interplay between rules and
decisions. At a first sight we could have any rule we want; we could form every concept
we like. But, if we look carefully we will see that this is not so. A rule comes to life only
if we succeed in applying it; and this is not only up to us. It is up to us, because it requires
that we have the practical ability of grasping the difference between correct and incorrect
application of it, and thus being able to apply it. But we should keep in mind that without
this ability we do not have a rule yet. We might have the plan to make a rule, but this is
only the first step
37
. It is not only up to us because once we make a rule we can not
choose anymore what is correct and what is not correct according to that rule. By making
a rule we make ourselves responsible for how we apply it. Also we have to decide what
rules to follow. Here it is totally up to us what we decide. We could follow many rules,
but is up to us to decide what rules we want to follow. Afterwards, we become
responsible for our decisions, because they are of our making.

4. We as conceptual entrepreneurs

Now, the time to complete the picture has come. We saw in the first chapter that
we are normative creatures and that our normativity is rooted at the pragmatic level. We
saw in the second chapter that we live in a mysterious world and thus we are always more
or less entrepreneurs. Until now, in this chapter we saw how rules as well as decisions are
to be found at every point in the conceptual realm. In this section we will se the complete
picture. We will see how the two features combine to make us the creatures that we are,
namely conceptual entrepreneurs.
Normativity is not exhausted by explicit rules and principles. It is not exhausted
even at the level of norms that are implicit in practice either. This is clear if we try to
bridge the explanatory gap between what ought to be and what is. More specific, how can
we explain that we manage to do what we think we ought to do? How my thinking that I
ought to raise my hand materializes in the fact that I actually raise it? After all, this is

37
A full-blooded rule must already contain its proper use in it. As an analytically device we can separate
form from content, and if we like we may even use rule to stand only for the formal part. But this is
another usage of the word. When we talk about rules that really work, that can be used, we have together
form and content. And the content is acquired only by successfully putting the rule at work.
41
what normativity is all about. By talking of normativity we point to the accomplishment
of this miracle. How is it possible that something that is only envisaged by us (in one way
or another) actually happens in some occasions? The only answer we could give starts
with us as being normative creatures. That is, precisely that somehow the gap can be
bridged; that it is bridged sometimes. What we can understand is our specific form of
normativity. We can start from the most specific, from normativity explicit in rules and
principles. That we can trace this further down and indeed that we must is no big surprise.
After all, the discursive practice is just a practice among others. So, when we realize that
the discursive practice shares some kind of meaningfulness with the other practices, we
realize that normativity must be traced back to the pragmatic level. That is, to the level of
practice. After this step we can not trace back normativity anymore. And this does not
mean that it starts from here. It means only that we have to stop here. Normativity is
something that we start with, not the other way around. Furthermore, talking about forms
of life in the sense of Wittgenstein amounts to our acknowledging that normativity is not
specific only to us.
Now we can go back to a pre-conceptual era. In other words, to a time when we
had some practices, but we did not have the discursive one. At that time we were still
normative creatures. After we would get burned for the first time, we would never touch
fire again. And this would happen because we would still be entrepreneurs. We would
still have to face a mysterious world; and we would still be able to learn from experience,
from our earlier steps. We would not repeat the wrong steps and we would repeat the
correct ones. But in that pre-conceptual era our entrepreneurial ability would be very
limited. We would use our past experience in facing the new situations. But we would not
have the means of selecting some specific experience as being similar with the new one.
We could not escape our dispositions, because we would not have other ways for making
use of our past experience. Our dispositions will be exactly the voice of our past
experience. And after we would get burnt almost every time when we did not follow our
dispositions, we would realize that following them is the best option for the moment.
What accomplishes the conceptual when is introduced in a world of sheer
experience? A concept, which is a rule, introduces a line of order into the world of
experience. It selects a number of cases and puts them under him. Thus, we can group
42
similar experiences in a systematic way. A concept stands for the relevant similarities
which are picked by applying that concept. It is important that a single entity can fall
under many concepts. Something may be at the same time an object, a chair, a piece of
wood etc. The conceptual structure forms a web with the help of which we can grasp a
particular experience in many ways. It becomes interrelated with many others, by means
of different similarities, introduced by different concepts. Now, when we face a new
experience we do not do it against the background of a vast ocean of indiscriminate past
experience. The new point we are facing can be caught up in our conceptual web. By
incorporating it in this web it will have a clear place. We will be able to trace back our
past experience through different paths, choosing how exactly to throw the web on our
new experience. After successfully catching it in the web, by putting it under a concept,
we can make use of relevant past experience. All this past experience will be already
embedded in our conceptual web, at different points. And every concept, by being caught
up in the web, will be connected with others by different paths. Now, when we have to
take a new decision we can take alternative paths which lead in different directions. And
we can always put an experience under more and more concepts and we can revise the
old ones. How good is anyones web and how well we manage to place new experiences
in it depends on our practical ability of doing this. And every individual develops his
ability by practicing it more and more, by learning from successes as well as from
failures. Where we will incorporate a new experience into the conceptual web is up to us
to decide. It is also up to our deciding how we modify the web. But once we deem for the
moment the web as adequate and we decide to put the new experience in some place, we
can only follow predefined paths
38
, although we may choose which ones. That we can
follow only predefined paths should not be taken as a sign of our lack of freedom. We
should not forget the situation we were in the pre-conceptual era. That we decide to
follow the conceptual paths (which are of our making) is because we constantly see this
as the best option available. We are always free to dissolve any concept before making
use of it and we could do this with every concept. That we do not do this shows that we
decide that giving up some liberty (in the sense of not dissolving any concept for

38
Put in the words of Wittgenstein, this is the way in which the grammatical structure defines our world.
43
example) will pay off in the long run because we will be free to move farther, faster and
safer in our mysterious world.
Furthermore, by entering the conceptual realm we acquire a laboratory. Before,
we were directly facing the world. Our steps were always for real. We faced every new
situation backed up by previous experience but we could not do any trying. Then, after
every decision the real step must have been made. But now we can throw the conceptual
web many times before deciding that we threw it well. Only after this we will go on to
act. Also, by using counter-factuals we can walk on our conceptual paths as many times
as we like, thus knowing them better. Thus, when the real steps must be made we will
walk on much more familiar paths and we will know better where they lead.
In conclusion, we are conceptual entrepreneurs because we face every decision in
the conceptual realm as entrepreneurs. That is, without knowing anything for sure;
without knowing for sure what will be the effects of our decisions and actions; without
knowing in advance that we will make wise steps. The conceptual realm is very much
decided by us. With the help of it we can have clear paths on which to walk, not just
wilderness. In deciding to make a step we can also plan a sequence of further steps. We
do not have to make any step backed up only by an unstructured past experience and
afterwards start the whole process again. We will still face the world as entrepreneurs, but
we have very good tools for doing this.

5. Conclusion

The aim of this chapter was to show the way in which we use concepts. We
started from the insight that concept use is an ability which is fully within the grasp of
every human. We used the raw materials from the previous chapters, namely that we are
normative creatures and that our normativity is rooted at the pragmatic level, and that we
are entrepreneurial decision-makers who operate in a mysterious world. These two points
shed some light on how we use concepts. We saw that the use of concepts amounts to
having a practical ability and that concepts are in the first place rules. By forgetting these
two things we might try in vain to discover in every concept an essential set of properties.
We saw that this amounts to seeing the concepts as dead entities, which would not
44
change. But a concept is a living entity, because we endow it we life. A concept is indeed
rigid (in the sense that it cuts precisely between correct and incorrect applications of it)
but we can always modify it, thus altering the specific way in which it cuts through
correct and incorrect applications, through reality. Any new experience, any new case
calls for us to make a new decision. Thus it calls for a reconsideration of the conceptual
web. What we decide is up to us at every point, and there are no predefined correct
decisions (at least from our point of view). How our decisions fared we can evaluate only
afterwards.
Thus, we are conceptual entrepreneurs. At every point in our life we have the
power to make decisions. By the practical ability of making and following rules we can
make concepts. And they form a web, with which we try to grasp the world. In devising
our conceptual web we are entrepreneurs, we do not know in advance if a specific
decision to form or modify a concept will turn out to be correct. We can only hope to
learn from our experience and it seems that we can just do that.

























45


V. Conclusions

The aim of this work was to show what is specific to us, as humans. The answer
was that we can move through a special realm, the conceptual one. This realm is formed
by the interplay of rules and decisions. These are two normative features but they put
emphasis on a different aspect. The two lines of thought that were followed here share the
same fundamental insight, of us as normative beings. They are complementary because
they put the emphasis differently. By focusing on rules, the first line focuses on how we
are free and able to impose a structure to the world; and afterwards on how our own rules
impose constrains on us. By focusing on decisions, the second line focuses on how we
are free to take any decision we like in dealing with the world; and afterwards on how the
world can always show that we chose unwisely. Thus, both lines of thought see us as
caught between freedom and compulsion, but they put emphasis on different freedoms
and compulsions. Combined they can give a complete picture. On the one hand, we can
invent tools (rules) but afterwards we can do only specific things with them. On the other
hand, we are free to make any step (decision) we want into the world, but only some of
them will prove to be correct and we can hope to discover which ones.
Thus, we are conceptual entrepreneurs. We are free to make rules and we are free
to take decisions. But, at the same time we are constrained by our rules and we face the
consequences of our decisions. In this process we can hope that we will improve our
conceptual web and thus, that we will grasp our world better.
46
Bibliography:



1. Brandom, Robert Making It Explicit, Harvard University Press, 1994
2. Brandom, Robert Articulating Reasons, Harvard University Press, 2001
3. Brandom, Robert Modality, Normativity and Intentionality, resource from
www.nyu.edu/gsas/dept/philo/ courses/rules/papers/Brandom.pdf
4. Hayek, Friedrich The Use of Knowledge in Society, in American Economic
Review, XXXV, number 4, September, pp. 519-530
5. Kirzner, Israel Competition and Entrepreneurship, University of Chicago Press,
1973
6. Kirzner, Israel The Meaning of Market Process, Routledge, 1992
7. Mises, Ludwig von Human Action, online version of Fourth edition at
http://www.mises.org/humanaction.asp
8. Sellars, Wilfried Realism and the New Way of Words, in Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research, volume 8, issue 4, J un 1948, pp. 601-634
9. Wittgenstein, Ludwig Philosophical Investigations, Basil Blackwell Ltd, 1958

You might also like