You are on page 1of 23

A Pragmatist Theory of Social Mechanisms

Author(s): Neil Gross


Source: American Sociological Review, Vol. 74, No. 3 (Jun., 2009), pp. 358-379
Published by: American Sociological Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27736068 .
Accessed: 26/10/2014 16:38
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Sociological Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
American Sociological Review.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

A Pragmatist Theory
Social Mechanisms

of

Neil Gross
University ofBritish Columbia

Some

have

sociologists

recently

about.

This

article

action.

Building

theorists?that

action

social

that existing

argues

they rest on either

because

and

should

of social

developed

American

pragmatism

is to
come

world

are problematic

mechanisms

common

inquiry

in the social

understandings

among

in terms of social

be conceptualized

of classical

of sociological

or questionable

increasingly

insight

aim

effect relationships

accounts

inadequately

on an

the tradition

ideas from

cause

by which

identify the mechanisms

that a major

argued

of

sociological
mobilize

practices?I
a more

to develop

adequate

theoryofmechanisms. I identifythreekinds of analytical problems the theoryis


especially

to address

well poised

then lay out an agenda

and

recentdecades, sociological positivism?the


view
thatsociology should aim to identifyuni
In
versal causal laws of social life?has been sub
ject to withering critique. Leaving aside the
claims of postmodernists, skeptical of every
effort at universalization,

and humanistic

soci

ologists who worry thatpositivism objectifies


human beings, positivism has been persuasive
ly attacked on various philosophical and theo
retical grounds (see Abbott
1988, 1990;
Alexander
1982-83, 1987; Seidman 1994;
Steinmetz 2005; Zammito 2004). Critics point
out itsphilosophical naivete with regard to dis
tinctions
and

between

theory,

facts and values,

and proof

observation

and persuasion?a

prob

lem sociological positivism shares with posi


tivism as amore general philosophy of science.

Scholars

also

been

their very helpful comments on earlier drafts I thank


the ASR editors and reviewers as well as Gianpaolo
Baiocchi,
Bortolini,
Amy Binder, Matteo
Craig
Scott Frickel, Julian Go,
Charles Camic,
Calhoun,
Hans
John
Lamont,
Joas, Erkki Kilpinen, Mich?le
Levi Martin,
Robert
Mitchell
Stevens,
Sampson,
Josh Whitford,
Turner,
Stephen
Sidney Tarrow,
Christopher Winship, Matt Wray, and Stephen Vaisey.
I also thank participants
in workshops
held at the
University of British Columbia, New York University,
the Radcliffe
University

Institute for Advanced

Study, and

the

of Trento.
American

Sociological

Review,

than a century

research, few universal laws

discovered.

with more

researchers

aims

strictly explanatory

have embraced the postpositivist position that


more or
sociology should center on identifying
less

social

general

causal

processes,

or abstract

mechanisms,
that may

operate

in particular

settings and thatmay help to account


observed

outcomes.

Where

positivism

has

for

tra

ditionally searched for laws of the form "ifX


thenuniversally 7" or "ifX thenuniversally Y
generally

toNeil Gross at Department


correspondence
BC
of Sociology, 6303 NW Marine Drive, Vancouver
For
V6T
1Z1, Canada
(ngross@interchange.ubc.ca).

in more

that

As criticismsmount, sociologists grasp for


more adequate conceptions of the disciplinary
enterprise.Moralistic and political understand
ingshave attainednew popularity (e.g.,Burawoy
2005; Feagin and Vera 2008), but many

becomes

Direct

note

of sociological
have

research.

for future

more

are
likely," social mechanisms
as intermediary
understood
process

es bywhich, in certain irreducible contexts, the


probabilistic X-^Y relationship obtains. The
view thatsociology should identify
mechanisms
underlies, for instance, Kandel and Massey's
attempt to discover the means
(2002:983)

"through which [the]migratory attitudes [of


Mexican immigrants] spread through cultural
channels

to affect

behavior";

Castilla, and Moore's


mine

how

(2000)

contemporary

firms

Fernandez,

effort to deter
leverage

bene

fits inhiring by reliance on employee referrals;


and Sampson, Raudenbush, and Earls's (1997)
argument that the capacity of urban neighbor
hood residents to collectively exert informal
2009, Vol.

74 (June:358-379)

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

359

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


social control is a key mechanism mediating
structure

between

and

rates.

crime

Empirical

work in thisvein is oftendistinguished not only


frompositivism sensu stricto,but also from the
sociological traditionof "correlational analysis,"
which

examines

associations

among

variables

but pursues explanation at a high level of gen


erality (see Bunge 1997;Mahoney 2001; Steel
2004). Both approaches, it is argued, treatcausal
as black boxes (Elster 1989;
mechanisms
Hedstr?m and Swedberg 1998) and so fail to
comprehensive
provide
As more
sociologists
anism-centered

focus,

explanations.
have adopted
theoretical

a mech

formulations

of themechanisms concept have proliferated


(e.g., Hedstr?m and Swedberg 1998; Reskin
2003; Stinchcombe 2005; Tilly 2001). There
is,however, somethingparadoxical aboutmany
of these formulations: they owe their attrac
tiveness to a context inwhich sociological the
orists, applying and extending the ideas of
philosophers, have helped to undermine posi
tivism.Yet theyoften proceed from substantive
assumptions thatmany in the heterogeneous
theorycommunity do not consider viable. More
specifically, many prominent theoretical
accounts

of

social

are

mechanisms

either

beholden to some version of rational choice


theory or essentially agnostic about the nature
of social

action.1

However, amajority of theorists today doubt


thataction typically takes the form of a ration
al calculation ofmeans to ends, and also insist
that action-theoretical
into

factor

every

necessarily
assumptions
account
of social
order and

change and should thereforebe fully specified.


From

a variety

of viewpoints,

contemporary

theorists instead conceptualize social action as


a creative

enactment

over

time of social

prac

tices. Social practices are ways of doing and


thinking that are often tacit, acquire meaning
fromwidely shared presuppositions and under
lying semiotic codes, and are tied to particular
locations

in the social

structure

and

to the col

lective history of groups. Collective enactment


of such practices produces and reproduces those
structures and groups (e.g., Archer 2000;

Bourdieu 1990; de Certeau 1984; Giddens 1984;


Ortner 1984; Swidler 2001; see also Chaiklin
and Lave 1996; Pickering 1992; Schatzki 1996,
2002; Schatzki, Knorr Cetina, and von Savigny
2001).
In this article, I show how a sophisticated
theory of social action, broadly in the practice
theory family?developed
by theAmerican

pragmatist philosophers Charles S. Peirce,


William James,George HerbertMead, and John
Dewey and elaborated most recently by Joas
be extended into a robust theory
(1996)?can
of social mechanisms. I do not argue directlyfor
themerits of a pragmatist theory of action;
strong arguments to this effect have been
advanced by others (e.g., Joas 1993, 1996;
Whitford 2002). Nor do I demonstrate thatmy

approach necessarily increases the explanatory

an exception
to this generaliza
tion inTilly's work, which overlaps in certain respects
I develop here.
with the perspective
I discuss

below

of par

of the operation

ticularmechanisms, although I identify three


common analytical problems with which the
theory could be especially helpful. Rather, I
a

make

facie

prima

case

that a great many

social

mechanisms, regardless of the level of analysis


at which they operate, can be understood as
resting

on a more

solid

foun

action-theoretical

dation than existing approaches recognize. In


doing so, I offer a way to connect important

strandsof sociological theorywith the research


enterprise of "mainstream" sociology (see
Calhoun andVanAntwerpen 2007) and?taking
a differenttack from the symbolic interaction
ists?show how the traditionofAmerican prag

matism

can

provide

intellectual

coherence

to a

discipline looking to find itsway in a postpos


itivistage.

WHAT IS A SOCIAL MECHANISM?


Confusion

abounds

as

to what

exactly

a mech

anism is.A clear definition is an essential first


step toward a sociological theory of mecha
nisms. To distill such a definition, I consider five
varied conceptualizations
in recent

2
1

account

of every

power

years.2

For a more

mechanisms,

that have appeared

exhaustive

review of the literature on

see Hedstr?m

(2005);

Hedstr?m

and

Swedberg (1998); Johnson (2002); and Mahoney


(2001).

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

360

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW


as Not Necessarily
or Processes
Structures

Mechanisms
Observable

According to the first conceptualization?


advanced by Hedstr?m and Swedberg (1998)?
a social

or process

is the structure

mechanism

S by which some event or variable / leads to or


causes

change

in the state of variable

or event

O. Where some sociologists would be content


to "blackbox" S, or significant components of
it,Hedstr?m and Swedberg insist that true
explanation demands fuller specification of
its internalcontent. Such specification, in their
view, should have threefeatures. First, it should
follow the principle of methodological
indi
vidualism,

meso-

explaining

and macro-level

social phenomena by reference to the actions


of the individuals involved. Second, it should
give primacy to analytical models to be judged
by their explanatory utility and parsimony, as
much as by their realism.3 Third, the specifi
cation of S must not require thatS be directly
observable; many social mechanisms,
they
argue, cannot be observed. Although Hedstr?m
and Swedberg point appreciatively to work
done

by Coleman,

Granovetter,

and

others,

theirparadigm case of an adequately specified


social mechanism isMerton's (1968) theoryof
the self-fulfilling prophesy, by which a false
definition of a situation leads individuals to act
so as to bring that situation about, as when
belief in the insolvency of a bank leads to a run
thatcauses insolvency. This theorymeets their
criteria because itpostulates the existence of
a "general

mechanism

belief-formation

which

states that the number of individuals who per


form a certain act signals to others the likely
value or necessity of the act, and this signalwill
influence other individuals' choice of action"
(p. 21, emphasis in original).

as Observable
Mechanisms
Processes
that Do Not Require the Positing
of
Motives
For Reskin (2003), the specification of a social
mechanism need not have all the properties
demanded byHedstr?m and Swedberg. Laying

3As noted
below, Hedstr?m (2005) objects to

"instrumentalist"

that ignore realism

versions

of rational

altogether.

choice

an

out

theory

for

agenda

on

research

ascriptive

inequality, she urges scholars to stop being


concerned with models thatposit motives for
and focus instead on
unequal allocations
mechanisms
uncovering
by which "ascribed
are

characteristics"

linked

"to

outcomes

of

varying desirability" (p. 7). For Reskin, as for


Hedstr?m

and

are what

mechanisms

Swedberg,

happen inside the black box of social causal


ity?they are "processes thatconvert inputs (or
independent variables) intooutputs (or depen
dent variables)" (p. 7). She glosses mecha
nisms-based approaches to inequality as those
concerned with the question of how inequali
ties arise in allocation.4 Unlike Hedstr?m and
Swedberg, however, Reskin argues that how
questions must be answerable in terms of
observable processes; inher view, this feature
commends them over why questions from the
standpoint of realism, for themotives of indi
viduals and groups typically cannot be seen.
The

only

concerns

exception

mechanisms

pos

tulated to operate at the intrapsychic level;


and

societal,

interpersonal,

must meet

mechanisms

organizational

the observability

requirement.

as Lower-Order

Mechanisms
Processes

Social

on
Stinchcombe
(1998:267),
building
an
offers
alternative by suggesting
Coleman,
are

that mechanisms
or

theory'

'models'

that

process,

have

"bits

of

that

a causal

represent

some

true

'sometimes

actual

or

possible

empirical support separate from the larger the


ory inwhich it is a mechanism, and that gen
erate

increased

power,

precision,

or elegance

in the large-scale theories." Although not a


individualist, he argues that
methodological
all social mechanisms
ing

lower-order

units

involve

processes

affect

of analysis?processes

that in aggregate bring about the relationship


X?>Y

for higher-order

units

under

considera

tion. Stinchcombe, however, insists thatwe


may be able to show thatX causes Y without
knowing much about the underlying, lower
ordermechanisms: onlywhen such knowledge

4
Much

recent empirical work on mechanisms


of
can
seen
as
be
out
Reskin's
pro
inequality
carrying
gram (e.g., Rivera 2008; Stevens 2007).

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

361

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


gives us a better understanding of the higher
order

example,

relationship?for

ant tomovement

the con

of

texts in which the relationship is likely to


obtain?will itbe helpful tohave a grasp of the
relevant

mechanisms.

as Triggerable

Mechanisms

Causal

Powers

sine

non of science.

qua

In their view,

across

three

ontological

the empirical,

where

scientists

movement
from

the iden

involves analytic

tification of mechanisms

domains:
access

expe

rience; to the actual, where they identify the


events

to the real,
that experience;
the causal
mechanisms?usually

that generate

wherein

lie

virtue

unseen?by
another.

to critical

Key

one

of which

realism's

understanding

a continuum

"closed"

an

from

system.

toward

"open"

A mechanism

is "that

aspect

of the structureof a thingby virtue ofwhich it


has a certain [causal] power" (Collier 1994:62).
Mechanisms, however, "operate [only] when
suitably triggered" (p. 62), and outside the lab
almost
oratory mechanisms
a host of other mechanisms,

coexist

always

processes,

with

and

fac

tors that inhibit that triggering or otherwise


interferewith the causal relationship. "Under

in other words,
conditions,"
non-experimental
in con
"we can see only what
[a] mechanism

junction with otherfactors makes itdo" (p. 33,


is, we can see it
emphasis in original)?that
operate

in an open
system.
Experi
a closed
creates
contrast,
system
by
one mechanism
from the
of nature

only

mentation,
"to

isolate

effects

to see what

of others,

that mechanism

does on its own" (p. 33). Science proceeds by


generating such isolation and thus involves nei
ther a

for covering

search

of

accumulation
searches

for an

findings.

increasingly

laws

nor

simple
science

Rather,
comprehensive

and

deep understanding of causal mechanisms, the


mechanisms

that underlie

mechanisms,

and how

the configuration of particular open systems


affects the functioning ofmechanisms.
Bhaskar and other critical realists devote par
ticular attention to the social sciences, which
they see as studying systems especially resist

relations.

resistance

This

models?the

of analytic

mecha

nisms that could have helped generate them,


and determining, through empirically ground
ed reflectionon the conditions of historical pos
sibility,whether and how those mechanisms,
with

and given

others

circumstances,

contingent

actually brought about the events (see Steinmetz


individualists,
2004). Unlike methodological
critical

are also

realists

who

emergentists

argue

thathigher-order strataof social reality emerge


those

of thisprocess is the claim thatmovement from


the empirical to the real involves movement
along

social

transforming

out of lower-order

causes

event

not

of closure,

has methodological implications (see Ekstr?m


1992). In the social sciences, explanation can
only take the form of breaking events down
into theircomponent parts, identifying?by the
elaboration

"Critical realism" provides a fourthapproach to


mechanisms. For critical realists like Bhaskar
and Collier, the search formechanisms is the

in the direction

least because of what they postulate to be the


intrinsic capacity of human beings towork at

emergent

that events within

and

ones,

are

strata

by mecha

caused

nisms unique to themand not reducible to lower


order mechanisms.5

as Transforming

Mechanisms

Events

A final framework is outlined by Tilly (2001),


like most

who,

centering

on

accounts

the search

accounts"

those

laws. He

for covering

that "consider
a

reconstructing

with

them with "propensity

also counterposes
of

con

of mechanisms,

students

trasts mechanisms-based

to consist

explanation

state

actor's

given

at

the

threshold of action, with that state variously


stipulated
organization,

as motivation,
consciousness,
need,
or momentum"
and to "systems

that "consist of specifying the

explanations"
place
in a

of some
larger

event,

...

structure,

or process

set of interdependent

with

elements"

(p. 569). Mechanisms-based


approaches, by
contrast, "select salient features of [historical]
... and explain them by identifying
episodes
robustmechanisms of relativelygeneral scope"
(p. 569). Tilly has a distinctunderstanding,how
ever, of what
events

mechanisms

consist

that alter relations

set of elements,"

and

of. They

"are

some

among
they come

specified
in three vari

eties: "cognitive mechanisms operate through


alterations of individual and collective percep
tion";

"relational

5
For a discussion

mechanisms

of social

(2005).

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

alter connections

emergence,

see Sawyer

362

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW


and

among

people,

groups,

works";

and

"environmental

net

mechanism

exert

which X

interpersonal
mechanisms

external influences on the conditions affecting


[social] processes" (p. 572).
In Tilly's

view,

social

consequently,

expla

nation should involve "pursuing] particular


across different settings" and
mechanisms
examining the role of thosemechanisms, includ
ing how

they "concatenate"

episodes.

In describing

into "social

es," in bringing about puzzling

process

historical
as events,

mechanisms

Tilly refers first and foremost to the different


kinds

can

actors

of practices

enact

together,

such as pursuing "certification" of theirpoliti


cal

as numerous

identities,

states

would-be

did

vis-?-vis theUnited Nations after


World War II,
or

actors

involving

"brokerage"
or
severing,

"establishing,

connections

realigning

among

social sites" (p. 575), which Tilly describes as


a defining feature of social life in the Soviet
Union. Tilly recognizes thatmechanisms thus
while

understood,

in nature,

general

relatively

may be instantiateddifferentlyindifferenthis
toricalperiods. For example, he notes thatmech
anisms of competition, involving "striving
several

among

actors

a reward-allocat

within

ing arena" (p. 575), are key features of the con


tentious politics waged by social movement
activists, but thatpolitics of this sort,with its
unique phenomenology, emerged only in the
nineteenth century.Analysts of mechanisms
must thereforebe attentive to time and place?
to ways

in particular,
nisms

may

in which

social

institutions,

"incorporate
and

understandings,

that have

practices

mulated

mecha

accu

historically"
(p. 570). Tilly's
(1995a: 1602) program for social research thus
involves "the historically embedded search for
causes

deep

variable

in variable

operating
and

circumstances,

sequences

combinations,

with

consequently

outcomes."

or means

by

is an

anisms

incorporate

environmental

mechanism

(not inTilly's sense), not a social one, although


itmight help establish the conditions under
which social mechanisms could unfold.6 It
might also be connectedwith other socialmech
that

and mediate

environ

mental factors, such as those thathelp explain


thegeographic positioning of thevillage or the
nature of itshousing stock.
2. Social mechanisms unfold in time. Social
mechanisms bring about causal effects through
a

of

sequence

temporal

events

or processes

occurring in the social world at themicro-,


or macro-level

meso-,

fact or phenomenon
fact or phenomenon

or across

levels. A

social

that causes

another

social

make

processes

is unimaginable;
and

up mechanisms

no

with

instantaneously,

intervening processes,

such

are always

temporally embedded. The duration of the


sequences involved may vary greatly. The
sequence

actions

matter

short?a

of a few

inter

cognitive-affective
an individual

when

example,
judges

be

may
and

another

with

low

processes?for
in a small-group
status char
external

acteristics more positively after that person


the

group

1982). The duration of a mecha

(Ridgeway
nism may

to

commitment

demonstrates

over

extend

years,

as for individuals

come

to value

in occupations involving high levels of work

place

autonomy

who

indepen

dence and self-direction (Kohn et al. 1990). Or


the mechanism

may

unfold

over

centuries,

as

in

the sequence of events bywhich theProtestant


Reformation instilled social discipline in pop
ulations, laying themicrofoundations for the
rise of strongnation-states (Gorski 2003).
3. Social

mechanisms
degrees.

are
although
general,
If a person
up in a
grows

neighborhood with a high degree of social dis

To extract a working definition of social mech


anisms

the process

community

in varying

a Definition

Toward

is rather

causes Y This process must have a


significant social component if themechanism
is to be considered a social one. A volcanic
eruption leveling a village and destroying a

from these conceptualizations,

I consider

themajor points on which the authors agree


and disagree. First the points of explicit and

organization,

has no one

exerting

informal

social

control over her, and turns to a life of crime


(Wilson 1996), a social mechanism can be said
to be at play only if theprocess ismore or less

tacit agreement:
1. Social
mediate
sequence

are

mechanisms
between
X-^Y,

cause
neither Xnor

causal
and

in that they

In the
effect.
the causal
7nor

relationship itself is a social mechanism. The

For example, mechanisms


relating to the result
as
of
levels
in Erikson's
anomie,
(1978)
ing high
classic study of Buffalo Creek, West Virginia.

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

363

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


typical of actors in similar circumstances. Every
such person need not be subject to themecha
nism, or affected by it in the same way, but a
is a causal

social mechanism

with

process

some

minimum level of generality.As Tilly's analy


sis makes

mechanisms

however,

clear,

may

sometimes be invoked to explain particular


events

historical

(e.g.,

However

ones).

much

the events typically studied by historical soci


ologists involve dramatic breaks from estab
lished social routines (Sewell 1996), they are
explicable in termsofmechanisms to the extent
that they are

of a more

instances

phe

general

nomenon, such as revolution (Skocpol 1979), or


of more

result from combinations

general

mech

anisms (see Steinmetz 2005; Tilly 1995a).


a social

4. Because
process,

mediary
elements

analyzed

mechanism

than

inter

of
composed
com
order
of
it
the phenomenon

helps explain. The nature of this hierarchical


relationshipwill vary by case, but Stinchcombe
for most

speaks

on

writers

social

mechanisms

when he argues that identifying themmeans


peering into a layerof social reality that serves
as

for

substratum

under

the phenomenon

certain

focus
action.

ship

machinery
of

lesser

thus

to greater

vis-?-vis

the causal

effecttheybring about (see Johnson 2002:230).


Ifwe let theoretical consensus be our guide,
these points of agreement should be incorpo
rated into any adequate definition of social
mechanisms. But such a definition should also
be sufficiently broad to accommodate points
of significant epistemological and method
ological disagreement:
1.Methodological individualismversus social
ontologism.Those likeHedstr?m and Swedberg,
who believe that individual persons must be
the point of departure for social analysis, take
a different approach tomechanisms than do
critical

realists,

who

recognize

the nonreductive

reality of emergent social entities. In fact,


Hedstr?m and Swedberg (1998:12) make a case
only for a "weak version" of methodological
individualism. Inmany instances, theyargue, it
may be impossible for explanation to trace all
the steps by which the actions of individuals
aggregate

to compose

a supra-individual

ty?the demand ofmethodological


ism

in its "strong

version."

Insofar

enti

individual

as this is so,

on

centered

critical

individual-level
are committed

who

realists,

versus

mechanisms.

substantive

a minimum

some

level of generality,

schol

ars are concerned with causal relationships that


obtain because of the form of the sociological
case at hand, in roughly Simmel's (1971) sense
of the term "formal."What matters here is that
anX?> Y relationship comes about because of
theformal, structuralcharacteristicsof the social
relations involved, as inBurt's (2001) argument
that social
whose
other

such

and

For

2. Formal

ation

social

on processes

Beyond the requirement thatsocial mechanisms

in some
the gears
stand in a relation

are

that mechanisms

incor

and

to a social ontologist position, by contrast, it is


acceptable?the point about analytic hierarchy
notwithstanding?to study social mechanisms
without much concern for the individual-level
phenomena by which they come about (e.g.,
Steinmetz 2005; see also Burris 2007).

investigation.All work on social mechanisms


assumes

as given

states

macro-level

porating them into the explanation" (p. 13).


Generally, however, Hedstr?m and Swedberg
believe that the analysis ofmechanisms should

have

it is necessarily
at a lower

or aggregation

plexity

is an

parsimony not only allows but requires "taking

actor's

capital

network
actors

encounter.

subjective

content

holes"

of the situ

or fail

accrue

content

where

advantage,

to actors

the "structural

The

actors

in which
an

accrue

advantages
ties span

to accrue
the

is either

of it or the ana

understanding

lyst's categorization in terms of social domain


or manifest
rectly

or latent function, matters

to Burt's

argument.

By

contrast,

only indi
Reskin's

call for the study ofmechanisms generative of


ascriptive inequality aims to isolate mecha
nisms operative specifically in situations of
allocation. Those who takeReskin's view that
the key mechanisms to study are substantive
rather than formal typically focus on domains
rich with the relevant mechanisms, whereas
advocates ofmore formal approaches seek to
identify mechanisms
ate across
virtually
the formal

end

so abstract

all domains.

that they oper


The
a

of the continuum

closer

to

conceptual

izationofmechanisms is, the less attentive itwill


be to variation in theworking ofmechanisms
across

time

and

space.

Nearly

all

approaches,

however, proceed from the recognition that in


social life contingent circumstances cannot be
completely explained away.
3. Analytical
point

of contention

versus

realist

among

models.

those who

final

offer con

ceptualizations of social mechanisms is episte


mol?gica!: Is the goal to produce models that

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

364

allow forelegant and robustpredictions,whether


or not

the postulated

can be

mechanisms

shown

tobe present and operative in reality?Or should


one seek to identify
mechanisms thatare empir
con
Hernes (1998:78),
observable?
ically
tributing toHedstr?m and Swedberg's volume
on

social

the former

takes

mechanisms,

view:

"A mechanism is an intellectual construct that


is part of a phantom world which may mimic
real lifewith abstract actors that impersonate
humans and cast them in conceptual conditions
thatemulate actual circumstances" (emphasis in
original). Reskin takes the latterview?without
a concern

up

giving

for

she

robustness?as

would reject postulated mechanisms that are


either unobservable or diverge from processes
and

that can be observed.

of events

sequences

Taken together,these considerations suggest


the following definition:A social mechanism is
or set
or less
sequence
general
of social
a lower order
or processes
at
analyzed
cer
or aggregation
of complexity
by which?in
cause X
to
tain circumstances?some
tends

a more
events

bring about some effectY in therealm of human


social

relations.

This

or

sequence

or

set may

may not be analytically reducible to theactions


enact

who
of individuals
mal or substantive
be observed,

it,may

causal

underwrite
and

processes,
or

unobserved,

inprinciple

for
may

Recent scholarship, although helpful in shed


ding light on the term "social mechanism," is
ological
eral

theories

accounts,

it comes

to offering

of mechanisms?that
not

of

social

soci

is, gen

causality

as

philosophical concept, but of causal processes


in the realm of the social. How should such
processes be understood?What are theirbuild
ing blocks? How do theyvary?
With respect to such questions, conceptual
work

on social mechanisms

tends

to take one

of

two forms. Some work seeks to identify rela


tivelyabstract featuresofmechanisms but stops
short of laying out a fully developed theory of
them.

Stinchcombe's

and

Reskin's

of their nature.
of

nisms

offers

the mecha
of inequali

ty,but provides neither a reason to thinkher


typology exhaustive nor much detail as to the
workings of themechanisms said to fallwith
in each class. These omissions might stem from
skepticism about the explanatory gain from
general theories. They might also, however,
stem from a hesitation on the part of scholars
to both make strong assumptions about social
action of the kind that contemporary theorists
insiston and to grapple with their implications
for the understanding

of causal

processes.

A differentproblem besets another strainof


work. Perhaps because the idea of opening up
theblack box of causality to develop fullyspec
ifiedmodels appeals to sociologists who value
a certain kind of analytical rigor, there is often
an affinitybetween work on mechanisms and
theorizationproceeding from assumptions about
action thought to be highly rigorous?namely,
scholarship in the rational choice theory tradi
tion. Hedstr?m's

proper,

unob

THE PROBLEM WITH CURRENT


FORMULATIONS

when

no general
account
a
categorization
to the maintenance
relevant

and provides
Reskin

work

an

provides

example:

formerlya champion of rational choice theory

servable.

less satisfactory

cation ofmechanisms may be helpful, itdoes lit


tle todelimit the scope of possible mechanisms

contribu

tions fall into this camp. Although


Stinchcombe's work clarifies thatmechanisms
bridge levels of analysis, and offers suggestions
about the circumstances inwhich the specifi

he now

argues

that social

mechanisms

should be understood through the lens ofwhat


he calls "DBO theory." In this theory, social
action results when intentional agents have
something they desire (D), have a belief (B)
about theworld pertaining to that desire, and
confront opportunities (O) that give them
options foraction fromwhich theymust choose.
Where

rational

choice

theory

posits

"an

atom

ized actor equipped with unlimited cognitive


abilities thatallow 'him' to consistently choose
the optimal course of action" (Hedstr?m
2005:36), DBO theory assumes only that "the
cause

of an action

is a constellation

of desires,

beliefs and opportunities in light ofwhich the


action

appears

reasonable"

(p.

39). Moreover,

while at least some rational choice approaches


treat desires and beliefs as exogenous to the
explanatory

model,

DBO

theory

takes

serious

ly the notion that "individuals' attitudes and


beliefs aremolded in interactionswith others"
is at the core of
(p. 43). Such a molding
Hedstr?m's

conception

of social

mechanisms.

In his view, three types of interactionalmech


anisms?belief-,

desire-,

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

and opporrunity-medi

365

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


thebuilding blocks formore complex

ated?are
social

processes.

The problem with this strain ofwork is that


relatively few in the theory community agree
that rational

choice

theory

or variants

such

as

theory offer empirically or theoretically


adequate descriptions of social action. Several
objections are widely shared among theorists
(seeArcher and Tritter2000; Green and Shapiro
1994; Somers 1998). Rational choice theory
typically conceptualizes rationalityas an innate
and more or less equally distributed cognitive
capacity,whereas sociological theorists attend
toways inwhich differentforms of rationality
appear at differenthistoricalmoments and come
to be differentially distributed across social

DBO

Rational

space.

choice

approaches?especially

outside the "bounded rationality" framework?


assume

that,

in most

individu

circumstances,

als act rationally or at least reasonably in the


light of their clear and coherent beliefs and
desires. Leaving aside the question ofwhether
most people act rationallyor reasonablymost of
the time,many sociological theoristswould fol
low Smelser (1998:4) in holding the "psycho
logical postulate" of ambiguity to have "wide
applicability" in social life,and Swidler (2001)
inmaintaining that the logical coherence of
individuals' beliefs about theworld is the excep
tion rather

the tem

than the rule. Furthermore,

poral phenomenology of much social action


departs from that implied by rational choice
approaches. While these approaches suggest an
individual armed with beliefs and desires who
steps out of theflow of action to face and eval
uate

a choice

between

competing

means,

theo

rists note that such moments are empirically


rare, tend

to come

in a socially

about

structured

fashion, and often involve an inverse temporal


ordering inwhich goals emerge and are clari
fied only after individuals tentativelyembark on
one means
Finally,
es?like
nature

rational

those

to DBO

theory

as

conven

to more

tional rational choice models, no sociologist


who finds them convincing is likely to think
Hedstr?m's

of social

theory

mechanisms?or

cognate theories offeredby Elster and others?


promising.8
In response

to these

to

in reaction

concerns;

other developments in thehuman sciences such


as

structural

existentialism,

and

Marxism,

anthropological structuralism;and building on


other developments including phenomenology,
ethnomethodology, and work on "rule follow
ing" inspiredby the later
Wittgenstein, theorists
in recent

decades

tices?not

have

discrete

that social

argued

prac

the focus

be

actions?should

of social research at the level of the individual


or group.

are

Practices

generally

as

understood

forms of doing orways of acting and interact


ing that appear within particular communities
or groups; depend on shared presuppositions
and

often

assumptions;

have

cor

significant

poreal or material dimension; and unfold in


individuals'

lives

as a result

of active,

creative,

and less than fully conscious puttings intoplay


of those presuppositions and assumptions in
the context of various and intersecting sociobi
and interactional exigencies.
ographical
as

Conceptualized

such,

practices

are

at

the

heart of Bourdieu's (1990) theory of social


fields, Butler's (1990) analysis of the perfor
mativity of gender,Giddens's (1984) theoryof
structuration,Knorr-Cetina's (1999) investiga
tions of the "epistemic cultures" of science and
modern society, Ortner's (1984) efforts to
reground anthropological understandings of

many

sociological

choice
approach
the norm-directed
that most

action

theorists

7
Not
is

argue

that socially learned habit is amajor proximate


cause of behavior (Camic 1986).While recog
nizing that lines of habitual activity might
accord with individuals' strategicor expressive
interests,

as much

or another.
whereas

emphasizing
of action?assume

motivated,

theydid something as post hoc rationalizations


that,beyond being restricted to a prescientific
"vocabulary of motives" (Mills 1940), often
obscure thefact thatno realmotivation or choice
was involved.7 Because these criticisms apply

theorists

view most

separate

acts

com

posing those lines as not directlymotivated and


see individuals' retrospective accounts ofwhy

all theorists

in the rational

choice

tradition

are subject

to these criticisms. Macy's


(1993) "back
model
of social control" posits that
ward-looking
actors learn through experience
about the general
sense to participate
itmakes
the need for infor
action, eliminating
in every instance.
mation-intensive
calculation
8
a growing literature in the philosophy
However,
under which

conditions

in collective

of social
be

may still
argues that "false models"
in explanation
useful
(e.g., Hindriks

science

extremely

2008).

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

366

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

culture, and Sewell's

(2005)
many

among

historiography,

contributions to
other

contribu

tions (for review, see Schatzki 1996, 2002;


Schatzki et al. 2001). Nearly all specific theo
retical programs advanced under the rubric of
practice theoryhave come inforcriticism,as has
the notion of social practices itself (Turner
1994), but this has not deterred a significant
amount

into

of research

the practices

seen

as

constitutive of social life innumerous domains


and historical settings.
Students of social practices have by nomeans
ignored causality. Indeed, as Ortner notes in a
seminal 1984 article, the turn toward practice

among

contemporary

theorists,

humanistic

approaches

while

incorpo

rating notions of the active, knowledgeable,


culturally interpretiveagent that can be found
in earlier

such

as

sym

bolic interactionism, departs from the antide


that

terminism

often

characterizes

such

approaches by seeing inpatterned iterationsof


practice thebasis for the reproduction of social
in particular,

structures,

structures

of inequali

ty.Faced with causal questions such as "Why is


therenotmore intergenerationalupward mobil
ity in contemporary
who

researchers

take

capitalist
a practice

societies?"

do

approach

not hesitate topoint topractices and theircausal


effects,as inLareau's (2003) claim thatdiffer
ences in childrearing between working- and
middle-class parents instilldistinctive disposi
tions in their offspring that are differentially
rewarded in school and on the labor market.
Yet the direct production and reproduction of
social structuresof inequality bymeans of the
iterationof practices is only one kind of causal
effect thatmay interestsocial scientists.To the
extent

that it remains

unclear

how

a variety

of

other causal processes build on and intersect


with social practices?as itdoes, given thatfew
who

take

practice

approach

address

social

mechanisms?much
empirical research will
find itselfdeprived of sophisticated action-the
oretical

THE PRAGMATIST THEORY OF


ACTION
The

American

classical

were

pragmatists

philosophers, not sociological theoristsper se.


Yet as Joas shows, despite disagreement among
them and significant interpretive disputes
among

to the mean

as

scholars

contemporary

ing of pragmatism, the classical pragmatists


were for themost part united in theirunder
standing of the basic nature of human activity
vis-?-vis the social and naturalworlds. Rejecting
theCartesian view thatthoughtand action,mind
and body, are ontologically distinct, the prag
matists argued that in anthropological terms,
are

humans

problem

solvers

the function

and

of

thought is to guide action in the service of solv


ing practical problems that arise in the course
of life.From this claim, wide ranging and con

troversialepistemological implicationsfollowed.

More

in the present

important
is the

er,

response

claim

corollary
to problem

howev

context,
that

involves

situations,

as

action,

an

alternation between habit and creativity.The


main

way

humans

solve

problems,

the prag

matists held, is by enacting habits?those


learned through social experience or frompre
vious individual effortsat problem solving. By
habits, thepragmatistsmeant not rotebehavior,
to ways or
but "acquired predisposition[s]

modes of response" (Dewey 1922:42, empha


sis in original) ofwhich actors are typicallynot
in the moment.

conscious

Only

when

preexist

ing habits fail to solve a problem at hand does


an action-situation
sciousness
argued,
ativity

rise

to the forefront

of con

as

the pragmatists
Then,
problematic.
for cre
humankind's
innate
capacity

comes

into play

as actors

dream

up pos

sible solutions, later integrating some of these


into their stocks of habit foruse on subsequent

occasions.9

foundations.

I argue thata solution to thisproblem can be


found by developing a theoryof social mecha
nisms on the basis of an approach to social
action thathas affinitieswith other strains of
practice theorybut is less reductive at the level
of action than theories like Bourdieu's. This
approach is the one taken by the classical
American

andMead and elaborated toward a sociological


theoryof action by Joas (1996).

pragmatists

Peirce,

James,

Dewey,

prevent me from offering a


or considering
of pragmatism
the implications
for sociology
of a pragmatist epis
of science. The one point 1
temology or philosophy

more

constraints
Space
nuanced account

regard to the latter is to reject the idea that


to
for pragmatists
that "works"
any action model
yield a robust explanation will suffice. As Joas shows,

make with

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


Blumer (1969), formulating the program of
symbolic interactionism,downplayed thisalter
nation between habituality and creativity,but
correctly noted thatmeaning is also central to
a pragmatist view of action. Problem situations
present themselves to actors through the lens
es of thecultural environments inwhich theyare
immersed.

Such

environments

to

give meaning

and help provide the content of the goals, ori


entations,

identities,

vocabularies

of motive,

and otherunderstandings of the action situation


thatactors come tohave. They also provide the
basis for intersubjective judgments about the
adequacy of problem solutions. All habits are
thus enacted on the basis of culturallymediat
ed interpretationsof the situation one faces (see
Alexander 1988), not least interpretations of
the intentions

of interaction

partners.

Why should sociologists take a pragmatist


approach to action seriously? A full treatment
of this question goes beyond the scope of this
article,

but

I can outline

some

reasons

one

why

might preferpragmatism toboth rational choice


theory and practice theory approaches such as
Bourdieu's.

Pragmatism is oftenmisunderstood as a form


of utilitarianism,but thereare at least fiveways
inwhich itdiffers from?and is superior to?
rational choice theory (for discussion, see
Beckert 2002; Joas 1996;Whitford 2002). First,
pragmatism does not equate problem solving
with themaximization of utility.To be sure, the
situations

humans

experience

involve
need

utility maximization?for
to generate
of businesses

as

problems

may

example,
revenue.
But

the
the

kinds of problems of concern to pragmatists


range much more widely and include all the
difficulties humans or collective actors face in
life,from theneed to remain healthy to theneed
to findmeaning and purpose in existence. To
reduce these to the desire tomaximize on a
preference function is to ignore the phenome

nological diversity involved in the experiencing


of problem situations. Second, to reiterate the
point about meaning, pragmatists insist that
problem situations are always interpreted
through cultural lenses. Even in situations of
instrumental

([1910] 1978, [1920] 1982, 1922), James ([1907]

classic con
1975), and Peirce (1992,
1998). Beside
tributions to symbolic interactionism, previous efforts
at bringing pragmatist insights into sociology
include
Lewis

and

Smith

Maines,

(1980),

Sugrue,

and

Katovich (1983),Mills (1966), Seidman (1996), and


Shalin

(1986).

For discussion,

see Gross

(2007).

are

actors

rationality,

enmeshed

inwebs ofmeaning that indicate the significa


tion of the ends

they

are

trying

to pursue,

con

Third,

prag

strain the choices theymake by setting limitson


the thinkabilityofmeans, and sustain the social
must be
relationships inwhich instrumentality
embedded. Rational choice theorymakes little
room

for culture

matists

thus understood.
against

argue?directly

most

utilitari

ans?that much action ishabitual and typically


involves
ends.

no

conscious

Fourth,

weighing

of means

maintain

pragmatists

and

that instru

mental rationality itself,when itdoes appear, is


a kind of habit, a way that some humans can
learn

we

to respond

to certain

situations,

and

that

should be as interested in the historical


processes bywhich thehabit of rationality?in
its various

and

forms?develops

is situational

ly deployed as we should be in its effects.


Finally, pragmatists suggest thatmeans and
ends

are

not

always

given

to action,

prior

as

assumed inmost rational choice models, but are


often emergent from action, as lines of activity
are initiated that lead actors to see themselves
innew ways, to value differentkinds of goods,
and to become attached to problem solutions
they could not have imagined previously
(Whitford 2002).
Thus described, pragmatism, in its under
standingof social action, sounds similar towork
in the practice theory tradition.A number of
commentators

point

to commonalities

at

the

level of action theorybetween pragmatism and


the thought of Bourdieu (Aboulafia
1999;
Dalton 2004; Emirbayer and Goldberg 2005;
Shusterman 1999). Bourdieu himself noted that
"the affinities

the epistemology
of the classical
pragmatists was
on
their
premised
anthropology. My view of the tra
dition draws from many
texts, especially
Dewey

367

and

convergences

are

quite

strik

ing" and that his approach, like Dewey's,


"grant[s] a central role to the notion of habit,
understood

as an active

and

creative

relation

to

the world, and rejectfs] all the conceptual


dualisms upon which nearly all post-Cartesian
philosophies are based: subject and object, inter
nal and external, material and spiritual, indi
vidual and social, and so on" (Bourdieu and
Wacquant 1992:122). If pragmatism and prac
tice theory,at least of theBourdieusian variety,

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

368

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

are so similar,why should sociologists prefer the


former?
Some might argue that they should not.
Similar though the two approaches may be in
certain respects, the claim could be made that
there is one crucial difference.Practice theorists
like Bourdieu routinely tie their analyses of
to questions

practices

of social-structural

pro

duction and reproduction,which have not been


a

concern

major

of scholars

in a prag

working

matist framework. The objection here is not


simply that thework has not yet been done to
link pragmatist understandings of action with
of meso-

accounts

and macro-level

to

ignore

conse

and

systematic

quential patterns in the distribution of habitu


ality?by social class position, for example. To

my mind,

this argument

however,

of pragmatism.

Because

counts

in favor
to prac

approaches

tice theory like Bourdieu's aim primarily at


accounting for social reproduction, theyend up
placing far toomuch emphasis on the strategic
dimensions of action. Although Bourdieu does
not see every individual act as motivated, he
does view most lines of activity as connected to
actors' interests in leveraging themselves into
favorable positions inmultidimensional social
hierarchies, and thus as tied to themaintenance
or transformationof those hierarchies.
As critics of Bourdieu have pointed out (e.g.,
Alexander 1995), however, thisanalytical reduc
tion

as ration

in its own way

is as problematic

al choice

theory is in its. In Bourdieu's

framework,

practices

tend not to be

seen

as sub

scribed to on thebasis of relativelyautonomous


identity

or ultimate

commitments,

connected

from broader

values

social-structural

dis
posi

tionings, or by virtue of the sheer force of


tradition or institutionalization. Yet evidence
from domains as diverse as religion (Smith
2003), politics (Stryker, Owens, and White
2000), intellectual life (Gross 2008), and inti
macy (Gross 2005) suggest thatfactors of iden
tity,morality,

or tradition

can

underlie

certainly

the adoption of a social practice by a group, as


well as shape individuals' enactmentsof it.Such
factors must

not be

seen

as residual

or

epiphe

nomenal elements but as coexisting and in some


cases

intersecting

with

strategic

for

the habituality-creativity continuum,

social

is meant

for pragmatists,

also

reproduction?but

to encompass

rather

than substitute for other forms of action, while


giving pride of place tomatters of identityand
is better

meaning?pragmatism

to accom

able

modate

the diversity of action and practice.


Although nothing in a pragmatist approach
would deny that some practices are closely
bound up with the reproduction of social
inequality, thevery thinnessof themodel at the
meso- and macro-levels gives it a flexibility
and range lacking in other approaches.

phenome

na, sociology's typicalobjects of explanation.As


important, the lack of such linkage may lead
pragmatists

account

because

concerns

over

social positioning. In part because pragmatist


understandings of action were not designed to

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF
MECHANISMS
The key claim to advance in constructing a the
ory of social mechanisms on these foundations
is this: Pragmatists
as
composed
actors confronting

view

would

nisms

problem

mecha

social

or aggregations

of chains

situations

of

and mobi

lizingmore or less habitual responses. I noted


above that alternation between habit and cre
ativity is at the heart of pragmatism, and that

pragmatists

see

this alternation

as underlying?

not substituting for?other action forms (Joas


1996). These characteristics of the approach,
combined with the focus on meaning, yield
unique

leverage

over

the notion

of mechanisms.

see why, let us follow Hedstr?m


and
Swedberg at least partway and describe a social

To

mechanism

as

the

structure

or process

by

which some input/leads to outcome O. A prag


matist theoryofmechanisms would hold that to
understand S, we must examine the individual
and collective actors Ax_n involved in the 1-0
relationship. For each, our goal should be to
understandwhy and how,when confrontedwith
problem situationPn and endowed with habits
of cognition and action Hn, along with other
resources,

response

the most

Rn becomes

like

ly.S will then consist of all the relations A x_n


?P\-n

?H\_n -R\-n

that, in aggregate

or sequen

tially,bring about the1-0 relationship.


For

example,

suppose

we

are

interested

in

the relationship between race and income


inequality and follow Pager (2003) in consid
eringAfrican American men and the effects of
a criminal record and "negative credentialing"
on the likelihood of gaining employment.Many
kinds of actors, problem situations, and habit
ual responses make up thismechanism, but a

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

369

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


pragmatist approach might concentrate on
understandinghow, foremployers tryingtomeet
staffingneeds with reliable workers, and in the
context of prevailing racial-juridical cultural
structures,certain habits of thoughtand action
are employed according to which potential
employees are coded in termsof trustworthiness
depending on theirrace and historywith thejus
tice system, giving rise to discriminatory allo
cation decisions. Aggregated across employers,
an A-P-H-R

such

is the mechanism

chain

of

negative credentialing in this case.


I hypothesize thatmost social mechanisms
can

be

in this way?as

understood

of actors,

aggregations

in some

ty, greater

and

situations,

problem

habitual responses?always

or

chains

with thepossibili
than others,

circumstances

that a novel way of responding to a problem


could emerge for any of the actors involved,
potentially altering theworkings of themech
anism.

social

pragmatist

science

concerned

with mechanisms would aim to uncover the


nature of such chains: the types intowhich they
may be classified, the actors involved in their
operation, the habits employed by such actors
and theirorigins, the circumstances inwhich the
mechanisms operate, their interconnectionwith
and

other mechanisms,

their causal

effects.

Note the centrality ofmeaning in the Pager


example; themechanism is interpretiveall the
way down. For pragmatists, humans inhabit
worlds ofmeaning. Pragmatism isnot a formof
individualism; it does not
methodological
require

that mechanisms

at the meso

operating

or macro-levels be explained exclusively in


termsof the actions of the individuals involved,
or otherwise.

meaning-interpretive

It does

insist,

however, thatthepotential contributionof indi


vidual action to theoperation ofmechanisms be
taken

into account.

This

requires

that we

grasp

how the relevant individuals understand the sit


uations

before

standings,

them

helping

and

act

on

those

under

thereby to enact

the

mechanism.
In this respect,

pragmatism

comes

close

to the

weak version ofmethodological individualism


championed by Hedstr?m and Swedberg.
Hedstr?m (2005), in particular, makes belief
central tohis account of social action,mobiliz
ingWeber's stress on subjective meaning to
argue thatactors' beliefs about the social world
are as importantas theirdesires and opportu
nities in explaining their actions, and hence

social

mechanisms.

then, with

How,

of meaning,

questions

to

respect

a pragmatist

does

approach tomechanisms differfromHedstr?m's


approach?

Drawing inspiration in part from Peirce's


work on semiotics (see Deledalle 2000), prag
matists would
insist that meaning
is not

reducible tobelief inHedstr?m's sense of propo


sitions about theworld thatactors hold tobe true
(e.g., thata bank is or isnot solvent). In theprag

matist view, consistentwith otherwork follow


ing from the cultural or linguistic turn, such
while

propositions,

mean

become

important,

ingfulonly insofar as they string together sym


bolic elements thatacquire their individual and

relational meanings in larger cultural systems


and structures.The belief thata bank is or isnot

solvent, for example, and that its solvency has


implications forwhether actors should with
draw their deposits, presupposes that actors

understand what a bank is,what itmeans to


say thatan institution like a bank can have sol
vency,

that actors

see

themselves

as

others

and

oriented toward themaximization of theirshort


termand individual or familialmonetary inter

ests, that they had enough trust in the


institutional order to place theirmoney in a
bank in the firstplace, that theyare acclimated
to a system
Merton's

of monetary

postulated

exchange,

and

so on.

of the self-ful

mechanism

filling prophesy functions in this case only


actors

because

are

in cultural

positioned

systems

fromwhich theyderive these assumptions and


orientations, and hence have the beliefs they
do. A pragmatist approach, takingmeaning seri
ously, would

argue

cannot

that mechanisms

be

adequately understood without an analysis of


such assumptions. This implies thatthe studyof
social

mechanisms

must

be undertaken

along

side a project of cultural interpretation.


Social mechanisms
that affect collective
actors
be

(e.g.,

analyzed

firms,

states,

or

organizations)

in the same way.

Collective

can
actors

also face problem situations and respond in


habit-bound, culturally mediated ways, and
social mechanisms involving collective actors
consist of chains or aggregations of such
responses,

whether

or not

there

value in furtherdecomposing
vidual-level

action.

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

is explanatory

them into indi

3 70

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

A FURTHER SPECIFICATION OF THE


THEORY
The pragmatist theory of social mechanisms
outlined here can be furtherdeveloped and elab
orated?and
preemptively defended?by
responding to fourobjections itmight encounter
on firsthearing.
The first concerns the theory's emphasis on
Will such an approach
cultureand interpretation:
inevitablyneglect the centralityof resources, and
struggles over them, in social life? The prag
matist response comes into relief by compari
son with Sewell's
(1992) account of the
structure.
of
Reformulating aspects of
"duality"
Giddens's and Bourdieu's
theories, Sewell
with
Giddens
agrees
(1984) that "rules" and
must

"resources"
sis on rules

as

into any understanding


Giddens's
empha

factor

recasts

structure. He

of social

how

procedures,"

"generalizable

ever, arguing that the rules thathelp constitute


structures"should be thoughtof as including all
the varieties of cultural sch?mas that anthro
have

pologists

:not only

uncovered...

the array

of binary oppositions thatmake up a society's


fundamental tools of thought,but also the var
ious conventions,

scenarios,

recipes,

principles

of action, and habits of speech and gestures


built up with these fundamental tools" (pp.
6-7). Schemas in this sense are habits. Yet
Sewell's
entail

on cultural
sch?mas
emphasis
a loss of concern
for resources.

tinguishes

two types:

He

resources

"human

are

"are

tions

from
...

resources
and

Yet
of power."
sch?mas:

media

unconnected

may

be

cultural sch?mas," while


amount

resources]

"human

as manifesta
thought of
of the enactment

to as

of

"what [nonhuman

resources

is largely

consequence of the sch?mas that inform their


use" (p. 11).
Schemas

and

are

resources

interre

indeed

lated, but a pragmatist understands this rela


tionship somewhat differently from Sewell.
According

to pragmatists,

when

actors

confront

a problem situation theymobilize theirhabits,


including some of the capacities described by
Sewell

as human

resources.

Yet

this mobiliza

tion typically also involves putting nonhuman


resources

to work?for

example,

money.

while

the

the habits

actors

use

to resolve

them,

the avail

ability of resources is, from a pragmatist view


point, a potentially important aspect of every
social

mechanism.

A second potential objection revolves around


thenotion of habit. Isn't this concept too vague
and poorly specified tomake sense of causal
mechanisms operating at multiple levels of
analysis? This objection highlights theneed to
distinguish among kinds of habits. Inmy view
there are threekinds:
1.Individual cognitive-affectivehabits. These
are habitual ways individual actors have of
understanding and responding emotionally to
situations in general, resulting from theirpsy
chosocial experience or theirbiological endow
ments

or

Someone

propensities.

is

who

clinically depressed and sees theworld through


a glass half-empty is displaying a cognitive
affectivehabit; so too is a person continually ori
or the
ented toward sexual
conquest
of goods

consumption

and

services.

Insofar

as

the tendencyto employ one cognitive schema for


interpretingtheworld rather than another also
this analytic
rubric, cognitive-affec
are major
sites of cultural-interpre

tive activity, and they refer outward towider


is

neither

cultural

consequences

power"

at her disposal,

availability of resources?an objective feature


of problem situations?may help instill in her
distinctive habits. Insofar as social mechanisms
are decomposable intoproblem situations and

tive habits

strength,

physical

resources

nonhuman

falls under

(p. 9). Both types, he

dexterity, knowledge"
argues,

are

or manufactured,

occurring
objects
naturally
or maintain
to enhance
that can be used
and

dis

resources

"nonhuman

...

not

does

pragmatist understanding, thehabits an actor is


endowed with will affect theways inwhich she
understands the significance of and uses the

In a

cultural

frameworks

internal

neural

while

also

revolving

around

processes.

2. Individual behavioral habits. These habits


involve thedisposition to enact specific behav
ioral responses or routines when individual
actors are faced with particular kinds of prob
lem situations.They derive primarily from indi
vidual and social experience. For example,
Bittner (1967:702) argues that inmany social
disorder

situations,

"policemen

not only

refrain

from invoking the law formallybut also employ


alternative

sanctions,"

ranging

from warnings

for offenders to "direct disciplining." This is an


individual behavioral habit learned on the job
and throughexposure to thepolice subculture.
3.A thirdcategory of habits consists of those
that are collectively enacted: that is,ways that
groups of individual actors, including those

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

371

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


who comprise collective actors of various kinds,
have of working together to solve problems. I
noted earlier that of the main conceptual
approaches tomechanisms, Tilly's is theone that
seems unobjectionable
in action-theoretical
terms.Complementarities between his approach
and my own are such thatan example fromhis
work can help illustratewhat I have inmind by
thiscategory of habits.10 InPopular Contention
inGreat Britain, Tilly (1995b) argues that the
best way to explain a major transformation in
theBritish political structurebetween themid
eighteenth and early-nineteenthcenturies?the
of "ordinary
"capacity"
... in national
affairs"

growing
intervene
account

for the emergence

of contention."

By

of new

repertoire

people
(p.

...

14)?is

to
to

"repertoires
he means
"a

limited set of routines thatare learned, shared,


and acted out through a relatively deliberate
process of choice" (p. 42). By repertoiresof con
tention,he means the routines by which "pairs
of actors make and receive claims bearing on

each other's interests" (p. 43). A repertoire of


contention can thus be understood as a set of
habits or practices enacted collectively bymem
bers of a group tomake political claims and
attempt to resolve problems theymay be facing,
from political disenfranchisement to econom

icmarginalization. The idea of repertoires of


contention is of considerable importance for
the social analysis of politics (Tarrow 1996), but
I see it as simply one type of habit that actors

can enact jointly to solve problems. "Group


style," as analyzed by Eliasoph and Lichterman
patterns of interaction
(2003:737)?"recurrent
that arise from a group's shared assumptions
about what constitutes good or adequate par
ticipation in the group setting," such as how
group members talk about personal commit
ments or politics?is another typeof collective
habit. So too are organizational routines and

1993; Feldman and


repertoires (Clemens
Pentland 2003).
4. Alongside this differentiatedunderstand
ing of habit, I would argue that habits often
come bundled in habit sets. These are relative
ly coherent repertoires for thinkingand acting
vis-?-vis a set of problems, as inTilly's idea that
theremay be specific repertoiresof contention,
such

as

arose

in early-nineteenth-century

Britain. To say thathabit setsmay be relatively


coherent does notmean the cultures of practice
or lifeworldstheystructureand informare seam
less culturalwebs, but only thatsome habits tend
to appear alongside otherswhen they are dis
played by individuals or groups, and that there
may be systematic relationships between them
at the level ofmeaning and action. The distinct
epistemic cultures that shape knowledge-mak
ing practices in physics and biology (Knorr
Cetina 1999) are good examples of habit sets,
as are sharplydefined occupational subcultures
(Hughes 1971).
Unpacking thenotion of habit helps explain
how mechanisms operating at various levels
can reston a foundationof habit;we can add that
pragmatists would see social mechanisms as
varying in abstraction and clustering into an
indefinitenumber of types.Mechanisms under
lying specific cause and effect relationships
(e.g., between racial heterogeneity in cities and
elite investment in social control resources) are

at the low end of abstraction (Jackson and


Carroll 1981). At thehigh end aremore gener
al processes that recur across many kinds of
such

situations,

as mechanisms

of brokerage.

These poles correspond to thedistinction drawn


above between substantive and formalmecha
nisms.While itmay be easier to see how sub
stantive
model,

mechanisms
formal

conform

mechanisms

can

to a pragmatist
also be under

stood in terms of actors, problem situations,


and habitual response. For example, to say that
an outcome

or event?such

as

the

1950s

Mau

revolt inKenya as analyzed byMcAdam,


Tarrow, and Tilly (2001)?involved
brokerage
is to say that a subset of the actors involved
faced problem situations that they sought to

Mau
10
these complementarities,
Tilly never
Despite
for his
laid out the action-theoretical
foundations
of practices or made clear how practices
conception
the full range of causal mechanisms
might underlie
More
his
to sociologists.
of interest
generally,
tomechanisms
may be too closely tied to
approach
his own

orientation,
interests, methodological
to serve
theoretical commitments

substantive
conceptual

framework

for the discipline

and
as a

as a whole.

resolve by mobilizing habits ofmaking social


connections between disparate parties. In this

understanding,

brokerage

mechanisms

revolve

around a particular kind of practice (a point


McAdam et al. also make); to understand the
nature of the situations those actors faced, the

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

372

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

actors' habits, and theireffects is to understand


the mechanism.

Pragmatists

would

also

agree

with scholars such asMcAdam and colleagues


that there is value in cataloging thewide vari
ety of social mechanisms found in social real
ity,which presumes thatmechanisms fall into
distinct types and clusters. Yet the pragmatist
theory is uniquely poised to understand how
this presumption could be valid. According to
the theory,what makes mechanisms different is
precisely the configuration of actors, problem
situations,habits, and patterns of aggregation of
which theyare composed, so that theproject of
cataloging them becomes one of cataloging
types of A-P-H-R chains. Similar kinds of
recur across

chains may

the extent of recurrence


ness

diverse

circumstances;

determines

the abstract

of the mechanism.

This discussion raises a thirdobjection:What


about formalmechanisms that seem to operate
behind actors' backs and to involve few
moments of situational interpretation?Many
such postulatedmechanisms concern theformal
structure of social networks. The pragmatist
view overlaps Emirbayer and Goodwin's
(1994:1445-46)
critique of network analysis,
which, theyargue, neglects cultureby failing "to
thematize more explicitly ... the inherently
constructed nature of individual and collective
identities ... [and] the complex ways inwhich
actors'

social

identities

as well

mativer^

as

and nor
culturally
determined."
societally,
are

Glossed anotherway, theirpoint can be gener


alized and squared with the theory presented
here by invoking a critique of formalism going
back to Durkheim's ([1900] 1960) attack on
Simmel: although the formal structureof social
relations

can

indeed

shape

and

constrain

action,

the situations inwhich actors act are always


characterized by particularity of content, and
such particularity should never be ignored in
social explanation. An actorwho finds himself
"the strength of weak ties"
possessing
(Granovetter 1973), for example, does so not
abstractly but in regard to specific situations
such as finding a job. These situations involve
configurations

of objective

elements

and mean

ing thatmake possible and set the parameters


for the causal effectof network structure.
To

give

another

example,

whom

one

knows

may strongly influence the likelihood of find


ing an apartment inNew York City,with special
advantages flowing to thosewith many acquain

tances rather than a few close friends, but this


depends on the degree to which information
about thehousing market is decentralized and
nontransparent,

on whether

erty managers

favor

landlords

and prop

arrangements

legalistic

over those requiring trust between parties,


whether city living is seen as so desirable that
people will do so despite thedifficultyand cost
involved,

and

so on.

Such

are usually

factors

incorporated intoformalmodels by virtue of an


implied ceteris paribus clause, but insofar as
they represent the conditions for themecha
nism

as
postulated,
the mechanism

we

operating

understand

cannot

unless

we

really
under

stand the conditions. Instead,pragmatismwould


suggest thatmechanisms resulting from the for
structure

mal

of social

relations

are best

seen

as

more or less obdurate features of the problem


situations individual or collective actors con
front?that

is, features

that enable

or constrain

lines of activity. How actors understand and


respond to the situations theyfacewill be no less
important in the context of such confronta
tions.11

A fourthpossible objection follows from the


third.Many mechanisms of interestto sociolo
gists, itwould seem, are not formal, as I have
been

using

the term, but center

on processes

of

aggregationwhose effectsequally appear not to


depend on actors' possessing and mobilizing
culturally mediated habits. For example,
Schelling's (1971) model of residential segre
gation postulates that ifwhites and blacks hold
even mild preferences for not being outnum
bered in theirneighborhoods by people from the
other racial group, therewill be no equilibrium
inhousing patterns and neighborhoods will seg
regate and resegregate over time, even if this is
not desired by any individual. How can a prag
matist

model

accommodate

such

a mecha

1'

Pragmatists would have a similar attitude toward


"environmental mechanisms."
These create problem
situations to which actors must attempt to respond.

The distinctiondrawnbyTilly (2001) andMcAdam


and colleagues

(2001)?between
cognitive/disposi
tional, relational, and environmental mechanisms?
run
is thus a false trichotomy: all social mechanisms

through the nexus of habituality, creativity, and


pretation. This is not to deny thatmechanisms
as relatively more dispositional,
be classified
tional, or environmental.

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

inter
may
rela

373

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


is aggregative and, at the indi

nism?which
vidual

seems

level,

to involve

no more

than

simple decision-rule?let alone shine new light


on it?
The answer to the firstpart of thequestion is
that themechanism can be respecified as an
aggregation of individual actors' effortsat prob
lem solving?the problem being to live in a
neighborhood inwhich one is comfortable, and
a key feature of themechanism being that the
kinds of situations actors confront depend on
problem-solving activities enacted previously by
their neighbors, which may have altered the
composition of a neighborhood beyond some
demographic tipping point. But what, in this
case,

would

be

tion? Beyond

the value

a respecifica

of such

the intrinsic value of greater

action-theoretical

a pragmatist

adequacy,

approach would allow preferences forvarying


levels of racial homophily inone's neighborhood
and the tendency tomove if those preferences
are violated?the

decision-rule

in question?to

be profitably reconceptualized as individual


behavioral habits. This would permit such pref
erences to remain latentwithout losing their
causal

relax

power;

information

and

calcula

bility assumptions and replace them with a


focus on interactionallyand culturallymediat
ed experiences of comfort within socially
defined neighborhood boundaries; put greater
emphasis on the social and historical condi
tionsunderwhich the relevanthabits formed for
and are enacted by the social groups inquestion,
including those bywhich they came to see one
another in racial or other categorical terms; and
allow the possibility thatunder different con
ditions?for

in societies

example,

placing

more

emphasis onmulticultural tolerance?different


habits might be in place, resulting in different
aggregate-level
Would
such

increase

the explanato

ry power of Schelling's model? Taking this


opportunity to speak to the issuemore generally,
I hold ittobe an empirical question whether the
theory of mechanisms laid out here will give
sociology

more

explanatory

purchase.

Researchers who are persuaded by the theory to


reconceptualize themechanisms they studywill
either find such reconceptualizations helpful
inproducing more robust explanations or they
will not. Because the theory is offeredas a flex
ible conceptual toolkitforcomprehending social
mechanisms,

to demonstrate

not a set of postulates

about

social

the theory's

value

explanatory

priori.What I can do is identify threekinds of


analytical problems forwhich a pragmatist the
ory ofmechanisms seems particularly helpful.
1. The problem of specifying scope condi
tions.Alongside challenges to sociological pos
itivism in recent years have been calls from
various quarters for sociologists to clarify the
circumstances inwhich theyexpect theirexpla
to hold.
nations of social phenomena
Postpositivist historical sociologists, for exam
ple, point to social and cultural differences sep
arating societies at differenthistorical junctures
and the constraints they impose on the project
of social-scientific generalization (see Adams,
Clemens, and Orloff 2005). Similarly, Abbott
(2001), influencedby a vision of social process
es as heavily dependent on place and time?in
particular, geographic location and sequential
that sociology not overstep certain
ly?insists
boundaries with respect to the scope of the
explanations itpursues. Inter alia, these lines of
thinkingdemand a better specification of scope
conditions, and I argue thata pragmatist theo
ry ofmechanisms could be helpful infleshing
out what thismeans. First, the theory views
social

mechanisms

as

into prac

decomposable

tices qua habits thatare always located in time


and space, emergingprimarilyfrom social expe
rience. Specifying scope conditions means, in
part, accounting

for such habits.

Second,

the the

ory insists thathabits, and themechanisms they


compose, function as theydo only in conjunc
tionwith broader, historically specific cultural
codes and repertoires.And third,reconceiving

mechanisms

effects.
a move

life fromwhich a broader sociological theory


could be deduced, it is impossible to predict
the specific forms that explanations informed
by the theorywill take and equally impossible

in terms of A-P-H-R

chains

draws

attention to their intrinsictemporalityand hence


to time-dependent sequential processes. To the
extent thatthe theorythuspoints theway toward
relatively rich specification of the conditions
under

which

particular

mechanisms

operate,

we should expect improvements in theprecision


of explanatory

accounts.

2. The problem of accounting for behavior

where

cultural

among
vary widely
meanings
action
In a pragmatist
all social
model,
involves
cultural
But phenome
interpretation.

actors.

na obviously vary in thedegree towhich actors


interpretproblem situations in similar ways.

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

3 74

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

For

in the

example,

economic
rates

interest

whereby

lowering
ic activity, one component

3. The problem
of accounting
mechanisms.
Change
are obvious
of every
features

phenomenon
spurs econom

of the operative

tices and

mech

anism is thatcompanies find itcheaper toborrow


cash

and

so

do

to make

investments.

capital

variation

occur

may

across

sectors

firms

and

in

how lowered interest rates are viewed, but not


much.

By

contrast,

in the case

of the mechanism

by which differential resource availability in a


household is linked tovariation in fertilityrates,
differentactorswhose behaviormight be covered
by

causal

single

model

(e.g.,

recent

immi

grants fromMexico, poor African Americans in


the inner city, and upper-middle-class

suburban

white professionals) may well understand child


bearing and itsmeaning in theirlives inquite dif
ferent terms. The difference between these
examples isnot thatthefirst is economic and the
second familial. Rather, social and historical
circumstances

(e.g.,

of

processes

institutional

isomorphism and the secure instirutionalization


of capitalist social relations) render the relevant
interpretive

processes

or

more

less

homoge

neous in the firstcase but not in the second. A


pragmatist approach tomechanisms may have
particular explanatorypayoff in situationswhere
interpretive
homogeneity across actors is low,for
here we should expect cultural differences to
have a significant effecton how problem situa
tions are understood and responded to, and on

how the social mechanisms thus constituted


function.12The growth of cultural sociology in
recentyears owes littleto a pragmatist theoryof
action ormechanisms, but the theory I propose
implies a substantially broadened disciplinary
role for cultural sociology, in part because it
that, where

suggests
actors,

cultural

explanatory

vary

meanings

interpretation

may

among

generate

more

of mechanisms.13

specifications

12
To return to the Schelling
example,
often faced by ethnographers

cumstance

this is a cir
who

study
studies

race and neighborhood


change. Exemplary
to exam
beyond a simple preferences model
ine the interplay of structural factors and complex,
on the part of residents of
variegated understandings

move

what makes

for a good

2008).

13
One might
from symbolic

ask how

neighborhood

(e.g., Hyra

the theory I propose


which
also

interactionism,

importantaspect of social change is the emer


of new

gence

Differences ineconomic positioning aside, some

differs
claims

new prac
for
and dynamism
and an
society,

How

practices.

do

these

come

about? Inmost of the versions of practice the

ory

discussed

processes

above,

of social

the answer

centers
new

reproduction:

on

practices

emerge as elites struggle tomaintain (or chal


lengers contest) patterns of social domination
in the face of exogenously generated reconfig
urations of the social field. Nothing in a prag
matist model would deny that social practices,
understood as habits, may indeed have their
origin in such strategic efforts,but themodel
would view practices emerging in thisway as
responses to only one kind of problem situation
actors may

face?that

is, the need

for strategic

repositioning. In thepragmatist view, thereare


many kinds of problem situations, and how
actors act to resolve the fullrange of thesewhen
existing habits prove inadequate is a major
source of new practices, with implications for
the socialmechanisms with which they intersect.
A pragmatist theoryofmechanisms therefore
encourages

researchers

to examine

the diversi

ty of problem-solving activities thatmay lie


behind new practices. When accounting for
social change is critical and the dynamics of
social reproduction do not tell thewhole story,
this theory should offer greater explanatory
leverage thanwould strains of practice theory.
For

example,

a major

change

has

taken

place

since the 1960s in how North American and


European police forces deal with social protests.
In the 1960s, police viewed protests as chal
lenges to social order and routinely contained
them by force; today, protests have been nor
malized and police often cooperate with activist
groups to ensure thatprotests do not get out of
hand (Delia Porta and Reiter 1998; McCarthy

roots. Space
limits prevent engaging this
stresses agency
question
fully, but interactionism
and contingency farmore than causality. Focusing on

pragmatist

the creativity end of the action con


to be
tinuum, as I do, allows a pragmatist perspective
better reconciled
with the aspirations
of a proba
the habit over

causal
and to provide
social
science,
bilistically
action-theoretical
foundations for such a science that
neglect neither the interpretive nor the agentic aspects
of social experience.

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


andMcPhail

1997). This change has important


for
contentious politics and the
implications
mechanisms surrounding it. Ithas loweredphys
icalrisks forprotestersbut also renderedprotests
less symbolically potent. How and why did the
new practices come into being? A pragmatist
approach would focus on the complex prob
to which

lem-situation

they

were

a response:

the

need of police forces to deal with events hap


pening with increasing frequency,which were
costly in terms ofmanpower and outside dom
inantorganizational repertoires of crime-fight
ing, and that posed a high risk of loss of
legitimacy.Organizational experimentation and
innovation followed, with police forces near
college campuses taking the lead, and thenewly
emergent practices diffused across the organi
zational field. Few could have predicted the
specific form the response took: itarose through
trialand error, indialogue and negotiation with
politicians,

and

administrators,

university

activists that altered police understandings of


theirgoals, inan institutionalcontext thatsome
times inhibitedinnovation,and against theback
drop of broader cultural changes in which
came

protests

to be

seen

as more

legitimate.

pragmatist approach would not deny that the


new practices strengthenedthehand of the state,
contributing to processes of social reproduc
tion,but itwould look skeptically on the claim
that elite demands for social containment ade
quately explain their emergence. A similar
explanatory logic could be pursued inmany
research

areas

where

accounting

for the emer

gence of new practices and habits could shed


important light on operative social mecha
nisms.14

the American

The growing interest in social mechanisms


salutary.

I argue,

conceptualizations
problematic

because

however,
of

social

that several
mechanisms

they are constructed

is

leading
are
around

inadequate understandings of social action.


Championing the theoryof action developed by

14
There

are important similarities?and


a pragmatist approach

ferences?between

some dif
as applied

to the study of organizational


change and approach
es to the topic informed by "new institutional theo
and Ventresca
ry." See Washington
(2004).

that

approach

has important affinities with more popular


strains

of practice
theory?I
I argue
that social

native.

an alter

propose

mechanisms?the

nuts and bolts processes by which cause and


effect relationships in the social world come
about?are

best

or aggre

of as chains

thought

gations of problem situations and the effects


thatensue as a result of thehabits actors use to
resolve them.This project of theoretical clari
fication aims not just at offering sociologists a
better understanding of what they are doing
when they identifysocial mechanisms, but also
at reforming sociological practice. The value of
the theory is ultimately an empirical question,
but I offer reason to think that conceiving of
in the manner

mechanisms

result

may

proposed

inbetter specified, and very likelymore robust,


accounts.
explanatory
These
considerations

suggest

a clear

research

agenda: sociology should aim to identify the


main social mechanisms by which cause and
effect relationships in the social world thatare
of moral, political, or intellectual importance
come about. This entails breaking complex
social phenomena into theircomponent parts to
see

how

or

aggregations

of

chains

actors

employing habits to resolve problem situations


bring about systematic effects.
Such a project will necessarily be multi
Qualitative

methodological.

research?ethno
and

interview-based,

graphic,

historical?is

necessary to identifymechanisms, the habits


theyare composed of, and thekinds of problem
situations in which those habits tend to be
deployed. Cultural and historical research is
needed to understand the origins of habits and
habit

CONCLUSION

pragmatists?an

375

sets,

and

hence

of mechanisms,

along

with theirmeanings for the actors involved and


the broader cultural configurations inwhich
thosemeanings become possible. Quantitative
research is required to establish the variable
associations that lead us to inquire into cause
effect relationships in the first place, to test
across

large

number

of

cases

whether

one

posited mechanism rather than another is pro


ducing the effect, to analyze patterns of aggre
gation, and to establish numerically how habit
sets are distributed across groups and individ
uals. Finally, sociological theory is needed to
establish new and fruitfulconceptual vocabu
laries for thinkingabout problems and to iden
tifypreviously unrecognized social processes

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

376

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

and dynamics that have ramifications across


empirical domains. Sociology can thenmark its
progress bywhether, for any social outcome of
interesttous, we are able to identifyreasonably
well theoftenhidden socialmechanisms respon
sible for it; gain some insight into how those
or

mechanisms,
under

different

related

ones,

might
and,

circumstances;

play out
as a result,

interveneeffectivelytobring society intogreater


conformitywith our values and ideals.
at
Professor
of Sociology
and the incoming
of British Columbia
editor o/Sociological
Theory. His first book, Richard

Neil

is Associate

Gross

the University

of an American
Rorty: The Making
Philosopher, was
last year by the University
published
of Chicago
Press.

REFERENCES
Abbott, Andrew.

1988. "Transcending

General

Linear

Reality." Sociological
Theory 6:169-86.
-.
1990. "Positivism
and Interpretation
Sociology:
History
5:435-58.
-.

for Sociologists
from the
Forum
of Stress Research."
Sociological
Time Matters:

2001.
Method.

in

Lessons

On

and

Theory
IL: University of Chicago Press.
in
1999. "A (neo) American
and
Mead,
Pp.
Pragmatism."

Chicago,
Mitchell.

Aboulafia,
Paris: Bourdieu,
153-74 m Bourdieu:

A Critical Reader, edited by


Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
S. Clemens,
and Ann Shola
Adams,
Julia, Elisabeth
Politics,
Orloff, eds. 2005. Remaking Modernity:
R.

Shusterman.

and

History,

1982-83.
Alexander,
Jeffrey C.
in Sociology.
4 vols. Berkeley,
California
Press.
-.
Giddens

J. Turner.

and

Press.
University
1988. Action
a New

Duke

Theoretical
CA:

Logic
of
University

1987. "The Centrality of the Classics."


Pp.
in Social
edited by A.
Theory
Today,

11-57

-.

NC:

Durham,

Sociology.
Press.

University

Synthesis.

Stanford,

CA:

Stanford

and Its Environments:

New York: Columbia

Fin

1995.

de

Relativism,
London,

Reduction,
UK: Verso.

Si?cle
and

Toward

University

Social

theProblem

Theory:
of Reason.

The
S. 2000.
Archer, Margaret
Being Human:
UK: Cambridge
Problem
of Agency. Cambridge,
Press.
University
Archer, Margaret
2000.
Rational

S.

and

Jonathan

Q. Tritter,

eds.

Choice

Resisting
Theory:
London, UK: Routledge.
theMarket:
The Social
Jens. 2002. Beyond

Colonization.
Beckert,
Foundations
Harshav.

of Economic

Herbert.

Blumer,

Trans,

Efficiency.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

by B.
Press.

1969.

on Skid-Row:

Police

American

Sociological

Interactionism:

Symbolic

and Method.
Perspective
Prentice Hall.

Cliffs, NJ:

Englewood

Trans.
Pierre. 1990. The Logic of Practice.
Bourdieu,
Stanford University
Stanford, CA:
by R. Nice.
Press.
Pierre
and Lo?c Wacquant.
1992.
Bourdieu,
to Reflexive
Invitation
Sociology.
Chicago,
of Chicago
Press.
University
Bunge, Mario.

1997. "Mechanism

Philosophy
of the Social
Michael.
2005.
Burawoy,

Sciences

An
IL:

and Explanation."
27:410-65.

"For Public
Sociology."
Review 70:4-28.
Sociological
in U.S.
2007. "Fordism
and Positivism

American
Burris, Val.

Social Science History


31:93-105.
Sociology."
2001. "Structural Holes versus Network
Burt, Ronald.
as Social Capital."
in Social
Closure
Pp 31-56
edited by N. Lin,
Capital:
Theory and Research,
K.

and R.

Cook,

Burt.

New

Gruyter.
Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender
the Subversion
Calhoun,

Craig

"Orthodoxy,
'Mainstream'

Aldine

de

Feminism

and

York:

Trouble:

of Identity. New York: Routledge.


2007.
and Jonathan VanAntwerpen.
and Hierarchy:
Heterodoxy,

367^410

and its Challengers."


Sociology
in Sociology
inAmerica: A History,

ed by C.

Calhoun.

Press.
Chicago
Charles.
Camic,
American

Seth

Pp.
edit

IL: University

Chicago,
1986.

Journal

Chaiklin,

Matter

"The

of

of Habit."

91:1039-87.
of Sociology
Jean Lave,
and
eds.

1996.

on Activity
Perspectives
UK:
Cambridge
Cambridge,

Practice:

Understanding
and Context.

Press.

University

Elisabeth

S. 1993.
"Organizational
and Institutional Change: Women's
Repertoires
and the Transformation
of U.S.
Politics,
Groups
American
1890-1920."
Journal
of Sociology

Clemens,

98:755-98.
Andrew.

Collier,

Press.
-.

1967. "The
Egon.
Study of Peace Keeping."
Review
32:699-715.

Bittner,

UK:

1994.

Critical

toRoy Bhaskar's

Introduction

Realism:

Philosophy.

An

London,

Verso.

Dalton, Benjamin.
Social Products
Incorporating
22:603-22.

2004. "Creativity, Habit, and the


of Creative Habit: Revising
Joas,
Bourdieu."
Theory
Sociological

de Certeau, Michel.
1984. The Practice
of Everyday
Trans,
CA:
Berkeley,
Life.
by S. Rendall.
University
Deledalle,
Philosophy
Semiotics.

of California
G?rard.

Press.

2000.

of Signs:
Bloomington,

Charles

Essays
IN:

S. Peirce's

in Comparative
Indiana University

Press.
Delia

Porta, Donatella

Policing

Protest:

and Herbert Reiter,

The Control

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

eds.

1998.

of Mass

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


in Western

Demonstrations
MN:

Minneapolis,

University

Democracies.

of Rational
Press.

ofMinnesota

Dewey, John. [1910] 1978.How We Think. In The


Works of John Dewey,
Vol. 6.
1899-1924,
IL: Southern Illinois University Press.
Carbondale,

Middle
-.

inPhilosophy.
[ 1920] 1982. Reconstruction
In The Middle
Works of John Dewey,
1899-1924,
IL: Southern
Illinois
Vol.
12. Carbondale,
and

Nature

New

Psychology.
and Company.

Holt

York:

Durkheim,Emile. [1900] 1960. "Sociology and its


Pp. 354-75 m Emile Durkheim,
OH:
edited by K. Wolff. Columbus,
State University
Press.

Scientific

Field."

1858-1917,
Ohio

Ekstr?m, Mats.
Action:
The
Critical

of Social
Explanation
of Max Weber
and of

1992. "Causal
Contribution

to a Generative

Realism

in Social

Explanation
35:107-22.

Science."

View
Acta

of Causal
Sociol?gica

2003. "Culture
Eliasoph, Nina and Paul Lichterman.
in Interaction." American
Journal
of Sociology
108:735-94.
Elster,

Jon.

Sciences.

1989. Nuts

and Bolts
UK:

Cambridge,

the Social

for

Cambridge

University

Mustafa

2005.

and Chad

Goldberg.
and Collective
Emotions
Bourdieu,
"Pragmatism,
& Society
in Contentious
Politics."
Theory
34:469-518.
Mustafa

Emirbayer,
"Network
Agency."
99:1411-54.

the Problem

of

of Sociology

1978.

Joe R.

and Hern?n

Vera.

2008.

Liberation

Publishers.
Boulder, CO: Paradigm
Sociology.
S. and Brian T. Pentland.
2003.
Martha

Feldman,

Organizational
"Reconceptualizing
Source of Flexibility and Change."
48:94-118.
Science Quarterly
Fernandez,
Moore.

Roberto
2000.

M.,
"Social

and Employment
Journal of Sociology

Emilio

Capital
at a Phone

Routines

Modern

Center."

Chicago

American

Europe.
Press.

Sociological

Theory

UK: Cambridge
Press.
University
Peter and Richard
1998.
Hedstr?m,
Swedberg.
An Introductory Essay." Pp.
"Social Mechanisms:
1-31

of Society:
Berkeley,

IL: University

in Social

An Analytical
edited by P. Hedstr?m
UK:
Cambridge
Cambridge,

Mechanisms:

to Social
Approach
and R. Swedberg.
Press.
University
Gudmund.
Hernes,
in Social
74-101

Theory,

1998.

Theory,

Pp.
Virtuality."
An Analytical

edited by P. Hedstr?m
UK:
Cambridge

Cambridge,

Frank. 2008.

Engines."
38:334-60.

"Real

Mechanisms:

to Social
Approach
and R. Swedberg.
Press.
University

"False Models

as Explanatory
Sciences

of the Social

Philosophy

Everett C.
1971. The Sociological
Eye:
Hughes,
Selected Papers.
IL: Aldine-Atherton.
Chicago,
The
Hyra, Derek S. 2008. The New Urban Renewal:
Economic
Bronzeville.

and
Transformation
of Harlem
IL: University
of Chicago
Chicago,

of

1973. "The Strength of Weak


Granovetter, Mark.
78:1360-80.
Ties." American Journal of Sociology
P. and Ian Shapiro.
1994. Pathologies
Green, Donald

1981. "Race
Irving and Leo Carroll.
on Crime:
The
Sociopolitical
in
ofMunicipal
Police Expenditures

Jackson, Pamela
and
the War
Determinants

90 Non-Southern
Sociological
James, William.

Review

U.S.

Cities."

American

46:290-305.

A New
1975. Pragmatism:
[1907]
Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University
Press.
Chicago,
Gaines
Chicago

Revolution:
The Disciplinary
in Early
the Rise
of the State
Chicago,

of Chicago
Press.
Peter. 2005. Dissecting
On
the Social:
Hedstr?m,
thePrinciples
ofAnalytical Sociology. Cambridge,

1993. Pragmatism
and Social
Theory.
IL: University
Press.
of Chicago
1996. The Creativity of Action. Trans, by J.
and P. Keast.
IL: University
of
Chicago,
Press.
James.

2002.

Migrate:
Hazards

"How Conceptual
Problems
Choice,
Interpretation, and the
of Pluralism." Annual Review of Political

Science

5:223-48.

Johnson,

S. 2003.
and

of

Detraditionalization

inAmerica:
A History,
edited by C.
IL: University of Chicago Press.
Chicago,
2008. Richard
Rorty: The Making
of an
IL:
American
University
Philosopher.
Chicago,

Joas, Hans.

J.Castilla,
and Paul -.
atWork: Networks

1984. The Constitution


Anthony.
Outline
of the Theory of Structuration.
Press.
of California
CA: University
Philip
Calvinism

as a

Administrative

105:1288-1356.

Giddens,

Gorski,

"The

Press.

in Its Path:
Everything
in
the
of Community
Buffalo Creek
New York: Simon & Shuster.

Flood.
Feagin,

1994.

Jeff Goodwin.

and

and
Culture,
Analysis,
American
Journal

Kai.
Erikson,
Destruction

CT: Yale

in
and Phenomenology
"Pragmatism
American
Pp. 183-224
Sociology."

2007.

Hindriks,

Press.
Emirbayer,

2005.

Intimacy Reconsidered."
23:286-311.

20th-century
in Sociology

An -.

Conduct:

to Social

Introduction

Haven,

Calhoun.

University
1922. Human

Henry

Theory. New

Press.

University
Gross, Neil.

-.

Press.

-.

Choice

377

Rational

S. Massey.
and Douglas
2002. "The
Kandel, William
A Theoretical
Culture ofMexican
and
Migration:
Social Forces
80:981-1004.
Empirical Analysis."
Karin.
Knorr-Cetina,
the Sciences Make

1999. Epistemic Cultures: How


MA:
Knowledge.
Cambridge,
Harvard University
Press.
Kohn, Melvin
L., Atsushi Naoi, Carrie Schoenbach,

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

378

AMERICAN SOCIOLOGICAL REVIEW

Carmi

M.

and Kazimierz

Schooler,
"Position

1990.

in the Class

Functioning
Psychological
Japan and Poland." American

in the United
Journal

2003.

Annette.

CA:

and Family Life. Berkeley,


Press.
of California

Race,

of Sociology, Harvard
paper, Department
University, Cambridge, MA.
and
Robert
J., Stephen W Raudenbush,
Sampson,
and Violent
Felton Earls.
1997. "Neighborhoods
Working

Childhoods:

Unequal

Class,

University

J. David
L. Smith.
and Richard
1980.
Lewis,
American
and Pragmatism:
Mead,
Sociology
Interaction.
and Symbolic
Sociology,
Chicago
Press.
IL: University
of Chicago
Chicago,
Macy, Michael W. 1993. "Backward-Looking
American

Control."

Crime: A Multilevel

Social

Schatzki,

David
Maines,
A. Katovich.
H.

Mead's

Forum

R., Noreen M. Sugrue,


1983. "The Sociological
of the Past."
Theory
Review

Sociological

McCarthy,
Institutionalization
Pp. 83-110
Contentious
D. S. Meyer

of Protest

in The

1997.

in theUnited
Movement

Social

Politics for a New Century,


and S. Tarrow. Lanham, MD:

C. Wright.
1940.
Mills,
Vocabularies
of Motive."

"Situated

"The

American

Society:
edited by
Rowman

Seidman,
-.

and Social

Sociological

Higher

The
and Pragmatism:
Sociology
inAmerica. New York: Oxford
Learning
Press.

-.

Peirce, Charles
1867-1893,
-.

Bloomington,
1998.
1893-1913,

S.

Essential

Peirce.

Vol.

1,

Vol.

2,

as Practice

1992. Science
IL: University

of Chicago

Press.
in
Reskin, Barbara F. 2003. "Including Mechanisms
Our Models
of Ascriptive
Inequality." American
Review 68:1-21.
Sociological
Ridgeway,

Cecilia

L.

1982. "Status

in Groups:

in

Turn

Routledge.
of
Models
Sociology

Knowledge:
Blackwell.

Social

H.,

Agency,

Jr. 1992. "A Theory of Structure:


American
and Transformation."

98:1-29.
of Sociology
Events
1996.
"Political

as

Structural

at the
Inventing
Theory & Society 25:841-81.
2005. Logics
Social
Theory
of History:
IL: University
and Social Transformation. Chicago,
Revolution

and Social
"Pragmatism
American
Review
Sociological

51:9-29.

and C. Kloesel.
edited by N. Houser
IN: Indiana University
Press.

Bloomington,
ed.
Pickering, Andrew,
and Culture. Chicago,

and Eike

A
& Sociology:
to Clough,
and Richardson."
Denzin,
Response
The Sociological
37:753-59.
Quarterly

Interactionism."

and C. Kloesel.
edited by N. Houser
IN: Indiana University
Press.
The

of
PA:

of Chicago
Press.
Dmitri N.
1986.

of Sociology
Peirce.

Knorr Cetina,
The Practice

1994. Contested

Shalin,

108:937-75.
1992. The Essential

Park,

University
Press.
State University

Bastille."

of a Criminal

Journal

the Social:
of
of the Constitution

Transformations:

in Anthropology
in Society
Studies

"The Mark

2003.
Pager, Devah.
American
Record."

Site

MA:
Theory Today. Maiden,
1996.
"Pragmatism

Duality,
Journal

1966.

Ortner, Sherry B. 1984. "Theory


Since the Sixties." Comparative
and History
26:126-66.

The

Steven.

-.

5:904-13.

University

University

Cambridge

Exploration
and Change.

Sewell, William

and

Review
-.

Activity and

1:143-86.

States."

Actions

Practices:

Social
toHuman

Theory. London, UK:


Contemporary
C. 1971. "Dynamic
Thomas
Schelling,
Journal
ofMathematical
Segregation."

& Littlefield.

Robert K.
1968. Social Theory
Merton,
Structure. New York: Free Press.

1996.

Pennsylvania
Schatzki, Theodore R., Karin
von Savigny,
eds. 2001.

Tilly.
UK:

Cambridge,

2002.
Philosophical
Social
Life

Import of G.
American

Press.
University
John and Clark McPhail.

Cambridge

-.

and Michael

and Charles

Efficacy."

Press.

48:161-73.

Sidney Tarrow,
of Contention.

McAdam,
Doug,
2001. Dynamics

R.

Theodore

Wittgensteinian
Approach
the Social. Cambridge, UK:

James.
"Review:
2001.
Beyond
Mahoney,
in
Recent
Innovations
Correlational
Analysis:
Sociological

Study of Collective

\9n-2A.

Societies
Sawyer, R. Keith. 2005. Social Emergence:
as Complex
New
York:
Systems.
Cambridge
Press.
University

58:819-36.

and Method."
Theory
16:575-93.

211

Science

Review

Sociological

Sociological

in the
Reproduction
in Job Interviews."

Rivera, Lauren. 2008. "Cultural


Labor Market:
Homophily

States,

of Sociology

95:964-1008.
Lareau,

American

Importance ofMotivation."
Review 47:76-88.

Slomczynski.
and
Structure

The

1999. "Bourdieu
and Anglo
A
Pp. 14-28 inBourdieu:
Philosophy."
Critical Reader, edited by R. Shusterman. Oxford,
UK: Blackwell
Publishers.

Shusterman,
American

Richard.

and Social
1971. On Individuality
Simmel, Georg.
Forms: Selected Writings, edited by D. N. Levine.
Press.
IL: University
of Chicago
Chicago,
Skocpol, Theda.
A Comparative
China.

New

Neil
Smelser,
Ambivalent

1979. States and Social

Revolutions:

and
Russia,
Analysis
of France,
York: Cambridge
Press.
University
J. 1998.

"The

in the Social

Review
63:1-16.
Sociological
2003. Moral,
Smith, Christian.

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Rational

Sciences."

Believing

and

the

American
Animals:

A PRAGMATIST THEORY OF SOCIAL MECHANISMS


Human

Personhood

Oxford

and

New

Culture.

1998. "We're No Angels:


Somers, Margaret.
and Relationality
Rational
Choice,
Science."

1996. "The People's Two Rhythms:


Tarrow, Sidney.
Charles
of Contentious
and the Study
Tilly
in Society
and
Politics."
Studies
Comparative
38:586-600.
History

York:

Press.

University

Journal

American

Realism,
in Social

Charles.
Tilly,
Processes."

of Sociology

104:722-84.
Steel, Daniel.
Inference."

2004.

and Causal

Mechanisms

"Social

of the Social

Philosophy
2004.

George.

"Odious

Stevens, Mitchell
Admissions
Cambridge,
Stinchcombe,

in the
of Method
Its
Positivism
and

The Politics
Others.

NC:

Durham,

Duke

Creating a Class: College


the Education
of Elites.
Press.
Harvard University

MA:

Arthur

L.

1998.

"Monopolistic

a Mechanism:

as

Universities,
Fields."
Pp.

and Nation-States
267-305

in Social
to Social

Corporations,
in Competitive
Mechanisms:

An

Minneapolis,
Press.

MN:

University

Strategies,
15:82-97.

of Higher
1874-1995."

Education
Organization

of

Culture
2001.
Talk of Love: How
Swidler, Ann.
Press.
IL: University of Chicago
Matters.
Chicago,

Visibility
Science

Whitford, Josh. 2002. "Pragmatism and theUntenable


Dualism
ofMeans
and Ends: Why Rational Choice
Theory Does Not Deserve
Paradigmatic
Theory & Society 31:325-63.

Research.

Press.
IL: University
of Chicago
Chicago,
and Robert W
Stryker, Sheldon, Timothy J.Owens,
and Social
eds. 2000.
White,
Self, Identity,
Movements.

567-88

Springer.
P. 1994. The Social
Turner,
of
Theory
Stephen
Practices:
Tacit Knowledge,
and
Tradition,
IL: University
of
Presuppositions.
Chicago,

Incorporation

Theory, edited by P.
UK:
Cambridge,

Approach
and R. Swedberg.
Press.
Cambridge
University
2005.
The Logic
of Social

in Handbook
of
J.
edited
Theory,
by Turner. New York:
Pp.

Press.
Chicago
Marvin
J.Ventresca.
2004.
and Marc
Washington,
"How
Role
of
The
Organizations
Change:
in the
Institutional
Mechanisms
Support

L. 2007.
and

Competition

Analytical
Hedstr?m

Processes."

Theory

Sociological

Sciences:

Epistemological
Press.
University

Minnesota

in Great
Contention
Popular
MA:
Harvard
1758-1834.
Cambridge,
Press.
University
-. 2001. "The Historical
of Political
Analysis
1995b.

Sociological

ed. 2005.
Human

Comparisons:
Study, and 'Small

the Case

22:371^00.

-.

Political
Explain
Journal
of Sociology

"To

Britain,

Incommensurability,
N's'
in Sociology."
-,

1995a.
American

100:1594-1610.
-.

Sciences

34:55-78.
Steinmetz,

379

Wilson,

William

Julius.

1996.

Privilege."

When

Work

The World of the New Urban Poor.


Disappears:
New York: Knopf.
John H. 2004. A Nice Derangement
Zammito,
of
in the Study of Science
Epistemes:
Post-positivism
to Latour.
from Quine
Press.
Chicago

Chicago,

This content downloaded from 200.31.75.101 on Sun, 26 Oct 2014 16:38:42 PM


All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

IL: University

of

You might also like