You are on page 1of 195

ANGELAKI

journal of the theoretical humanities


volume 18 number 1 march 2013

A gamben’s anthropological machine serves


as a useful way to begin thinking of
the relationship between humans, animals,
and technology. Because the anthropological
machine decides each and every time in favor
of the human, it is the figure for that which
includes and excludes, that which divides EDITORIAL
inside from outside and so forms a community
of those within the anthropological circle of
INTRODUCTION
the human and those who remain on the
outside looking in:
ron broglio
Insofar as the production of man through the
opposition man/animal, human/inhuman, is
at stake here, the machine necessarily func-
tions by means of an exclusion (which is
WHEN ANIMALS AND
also always already a capturing) and an
inclusion (which is also always already an
TECHNOLOGY ARE
exclusion). Indeed, precisely because the BEYOND HUMAN
human is already presupposed every time,
the machine actually produces a kind of GRASPING
state of exception, a zone of indeterminacy
in which the outside is nothing but the exclu-
sion of an inside and the inside is in turn only
the inclusion of an outside. (37)
animal, between the open and the not-open,
The human functions as a “transcendental sig- could still produce history and destiny for a
nifier produced through the various and multi- people” (75). Dasein has a “historicity” and a
farious instances of its own failure” (Oliver 8). placeness (a polis) and the human as Dasein
The empty signifier functions as the difference has these because of our access to the open, our
which makes a difference between claimants as ability to think the question of being and
(in)human. As Agamben points out, at the distinguish between being and beings. Animals
margins humans may be judged inhuman, as captivated by their environments – their
with the Jews during the Holocaust, and the Umwelt – are unable to get outside their worlds
inhuman may be judged as human as in the and have a look around; they cannot see beings
proto-human ape-man or “missing link” of as such and distinguish this “as such” as a ques-
early natural history. tion of being. The result for Heidegger is the
Agamben points to Heidegger as the last phi- famous claim that animals are “poor in world”
losopher to believe “that the anthropological while humans are “world forming” (Fundamen-
machine, which each time decides upon and tal Concepts §42, 176). Animals are trapped
recomposes the conflict between man and within their world by their captivation while

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010001-9 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783448

1
editorial introduction

humans build a world rather than live merely outside. The animal is the symmetrically other
trapped within one. This lays the groundwork to the human within Agamben’s figuration of
for Heidegger’s later work such as “Building, the machine system of insides and outsides,
Dwelling, Thinking” where technology, think- open and non-open (Wolfe 24).
ing, and human comportment or dwelling are Could there be an outside to this symmetry, an
intertwined. We’ll return to this alignment of outside beyond the outside that is figured by and
concepts in a moment, but for now let us for the anthropological machine? In what is
return to the anthropological machine which perhaps the most promising moment within
makes possible the division between those who The Open, Agamben points to Heidegger’s
build and dwell within their world and those admission that animals may well have their own
who merely inhabit their Umwelt. open but it would be something to which
Agamben’s concern in the anthropological humans are foreclosed from understanding:
machine is humans and humanness. He is inter-
ested in which humans count as human and This question now leads us toward the dis-
which – like the Jews in Nazi Germany – are tinction we tried to express by talking of
excluded from the circle of humanity. Such man’s world-forming and the animal’s
exclusion licenses treating the excluded as less poverty in world, a poverty which, roughly
put, is nonetheless a kind of wealth. The dif-
than human, as animal. (This particular
ficulty of the problem lies in the fact that in
problem is well developed in Seshadri’s recent
our questioning we always and inevitably
book HumAnimal: Race, Law, Language.) interpret the poverty in world and the
As for the animals themselves and even the ani- peculiar encirclement proper to the animal
mality of man, these remain disarticulated from in such a way that we end up talking as if
Agamben’s concerns for the social community. that which the animal relates to and the
Agamben is not concerned with the outside as manner in which it does so were some
outside; he is not concerned about the animals being, and as if the relation involved were
as such but only as they function as a “means an ontological relation that is manifest to
of an exclusion (which is also always already a the animal. The fact that this is not the case
capturing).” The animals are included inside forces us to claim that the essence of life
can become accessible only if we consider it
the system as a figure of the outside. Or using
in a deconstructive [abbauenden] fashion.
his terms, they are captured by the system as
But this does not mean that life represents
that which is excluded from the social life of something inferior or some kind of lower
humans. As Dominic LaCapra explains in his level in comparison with human Dasein. On
critique of Agamben: the contrary, life is a domain which possesses
a wealth of openness with which the human
There is a sense in which, in Agamben’s own world may have nothing to compare. (Funda-
discourse, animals in their diversity are not mental Concepts 255)
figured as complex, differentiated living
beings but instead function as an abstract It is exactly this “wealth of openness” which
philosophical topos similar in certain provides a possible outside beyond the dialectic
respects (perhaps even functioning as a dis- of human-animal as figured by the anthropologi-
placement of) the Muselmann […] Both cal machine. It is an outside beyond Agamben’s
“the” animal and “the” Muselmann function
concern for a machine that decides on human-
as avatars of the radically “other” (albeit,
ness. Rather, such a wealth of openness is fore-
expectably, an other that is also within the
self). (LaCapra 166) closed to humans. Such a wealth is available to
“life” and what LaCapra calls “animals in their
And this other, while radically other, is still diversity.” This space of the animal open pro-
within the system of the anthropological vides a way for thinking of the assemblage
machine which inscribes, describes and animal–human–machine without deciding in
decides the difference between the inside and advance in favor of the human.

2
broglio

By invoking the wealth of openness, dialect displays – then an animality of the


Agamben (following Heidegger) turns the outside would disturb the axis of the humans
open into a problem not only for animals but and animals established by the anthropocentric
also for man. Man cuts himself off from his machine.
animal nature but he does so only to tend to It would take a revolutionary intervention to
the open and let beings be as such. Yet, as disrupt this axis of human and animal and to
Agamben declares deftly, animals “know entertain the sphere of animal openness. As
neither beings nor nonbeings, neither open I’ve posited elsewhere, an animal revolution is
nor closed, it is outside of being; it is outside such an untimely overturning. Its time is not
in an exteriority more external than any that of history which is a mark of human time.
open, and inside in an intimacy more internal Instead, animals in their openness live in a tem-
than any closedness” (91). So, to let the porality that is virtual to ours. This is to say, the
animals be would mean to keep them outside time of animals is an-other time, one parallel to
of our knowing. Such outside would have to our own. Occasionally these temporalities
include the animal man and so we risk our- collide; history meets the time of the animal.
selves, suspend ourselves. What then would In such moments, the wealth of openness and
man and animals be who are outside of the time of the animal erupt like an event on
history and outside of the anthropological to our history.
machine which separates the human from his Such events are multitude but by way of
animal nature? example we can consider the rather recent
There is a difficulty in thinking this wealth of event, the case of Santino the chimp. Prior to
openness to which we do not have access. examining Santino’s story and the animal
Agamben calls this inaccessible realm a “zone techne and worlding he proposes, consider the
of non-knowledge” or an “aknowledge.” case of the fictional ape, Red Peter from
Because it is by definition foreclosed to Kafka’s short story “A Report to an
culture, Agamben brackets out this space and Academy.” Red Peter is taken from his life in
time. At best, it becomes a figure of the messia- West Africa and placed on a ship for Europe.
nic banquet and end of history which he uses as While aboard he learns to be human by watch-
a bracketing figure in the opening and closing ing the sailors. It is not that he wants to
chapters of The Open. The end of history “ascend” to humanity but simply, while being
haunts the book but never intervenes or dis- barred up, he wants a way out: “Up until then
turbs his focus: the constitution of the human I had had so many ways out, and now I no
(who is the agent and subject of history). longer had one.” His way out is to become like
What is missing, what remains outside our the humans – to act like everyone else. Red
knowing in this wealth of openness, is an Peter begins his report by explaining that he
animal phenomenology. To take this outside in fact cannot report his life as an ape: “your
of the outside seriously would mean a hospital- experience as apes, gentlemen – to the extent
ity in thought in the zone of non-knowledge or that you have something of that sort behind
aknowledge. Such a hospitality would challenge you – cannot be more distant from you than
what constitutes thinking. Being outside and mine is from me.” To become human is to no
an aknowledge, we cannot know this world of longer be ape. Red Peter cannot translate
the animal and its wealth of openness. Put between these worlds so different in kind.
simply, we cannot know what it is like to be Kari Weil explains the ape’s predicament:
an animal from the animal’s point of view –
as Thomas Nagel so aptly displays in “What Language is at the core of Kafka’s critique of
is it like to be a bat?”; however, we do get assimilation as a process that gives voice only
glimmers of this outside as it pushes against by destroying the self that would speak.
culture. If culture is that which defines itself What is the self, Kafka’s story asks, if it
over and against animality – as Agamben’s has no memory of its past and no means of

3
editorial introduction

representing it? Must that (animal) self be a contrast, Santino bears witness to another
blank slate for others to write upon? Or world and provides another sort of voice –
might there be some other source of selfhood albeit with rock in hand. Osvath compares San-
in his body, some physical locus where tino’s craftsmanship to that of hominins:
memory may be stored and known? (6)
The behaviors also hint at a parallel to human
The Academy with all its cultural apparatus is evolution, where similar forms of stone
foreclosed from the aknowledge of the ape’s manipulation constitute the most ancient
wealth of openness. Indeed, Red Peter (before signs of culture. Finds as old as 2.6 million
being Red Peter) had “so many ways out” and years suggest that hominins carried and accu-
now has only one, acting civil. Civility is, he mulated stone artefacts on certain sites, pre-
sumably in case of future need planning.
admits, not freedom, but it provides him move-
(121)
ment and livelihood. What the Academy cannot
access is the life of the ape. Of course, this is neither human evolution nor
Enter then the case of Santino. Santino the “ancient signs of culture” but rather a present-
chimpanzee likes to throw rocks at visitors to day event in which an outside animality
the Furuvik Zoo in Sweden just north of throws a nonhuman culture against our own cul-
Uppsala. Early in the morning he combs the tural expectations.
grounds of his compound to find handy stones A standard definition of techne – one put
and piles them into a cache along the bank forth by Heidegger in “Question Concerning
next to where the visitors will gather. If need Technology” – contrasts with physis. While
be, he chips off some concrete and breaks it physis is “the arising of something out of
into a reasonable throwing projectile. It is not itself,” techne is the arising or revealing of
uncommon for chimps and apes to throw something as brought forth by another such as
things at zoo guests but what is strikingly an artisan or craftsman (317). Santino gives us
uncommon is his forethought, a characteristic an outside that cannot be assimilated into the
we have reserved for humans. “Planning for a human–animal axis of the anthropological
future, rather than a current, mental state is a machine because the wealth of openness is
cognitive process generally viewed as uniquely beyond the grasp of such an anthropocentric
human. Here, however, I shall report on a system. This exteriorization by means of
decade of observation of spontaneous planning chimp technology points to an unassimilated
by a male chimpanzee in a zoo,” and so begins uniqueness in animals and their life worlds,
Mathias Osvath’s report to the Academy in their phenomenologies. In Before the Law,
Current Biology (120). It is one of the first Cary Wolfe develops what the realm of nonhu-
well-documented cases of non-instinctual and man cultures means in terms of philosophy:
non-habituated forethought in a nonhuman.
Forethought is a characteristic fundamentally Though there is no doubt a vast qualitative
aligned with being human, so much so that Hei- difference between the developing modes of
degger uses the concept as the scaffolding for human exteriorization and “grammatization”
building Dasein. Visualizing a future allows and those of other species – a point on which
humans to plan and build, to make objects func- both Derrida and Stiegler would agree – the
tion as equipment toward future ends, and to animal behaviors and forms of communication
we have been discussing are “already-there,”
fashion technology. In response to Santino’s
forming an exteriority, an “elsewhere,” that
forethought, Osvath wrote his report and the
enables some animals more than others to
zoo keepers castrated Santino as a mode of “differentiate” and “individuate” their exist-
control over his behavior and future plans. ence in a manner only possible on the basis
Red Peter’s way out is to become human and of a complex interplay of the “who” and the
assimilate in “a process that gives voice only “what,” the individual’s “embodied enaction”
by destroying the self that would speak.” By (to use Maturana and Varela’s phrase) and

4
broglio

exteriority of the material and semiotic techni- California aquarium tugged on a valve that
cities that interact with and rewire it, leading allowed hundreds of gallons of water to over-
to highly variable ontogenies, complex forms flow its tank and flood the exhibition floors.
of social interaction, individual personalities, Aquarium spokeswoman Randi Parent says
and so on. (76) no sea life was harmed by the flood, but the
brand new, ecologically designed floors might
Other individuals with other grammatization
be damaged by the water. Octopi incidents
and other tools hurled at us from “elsewhere”
are ramped. One has been spotted carrying a
remind us that our world is not enough nor turtle shell as a shield, another creates a
our knowledge sufficient to make sense of non- kabuki-like set of camouflage routines, others
human openness. are studies by astrobiologists for possible like-
Santino’s case is but one of many incidents ness to alien bodies and alien intelligence. (Mir-
where humans, animals, and technologies aglia)
collide in a way that disturbs human worlding
and points us beyond ourselves. Consider the Cougar from elsewhere: Fish and Wildlife
following as a small sample. (In a related Services of the U.S. announce the extinction
strain, see “Vengeful Tiger, Glowing Rabbit” of cougars in New England. July 26th 2011 a
cougar shows up in Connecticut having
by Randy Malamud.)
walked 1,500 miles from the Black Hills of
Radioactive Board: In the case of the Cherno- South Dakota. Apparently this cougar had
byl nuclear disaster, the devastation wrought been reading the Fish and Wildlife Services
by technology upon the bodies of humans has reports and wanted to repopulate the area
been forgotten by many who spin the narrative or just prove the government surveyors
of technological progress as a mode of bettering wrong. The New York Times’s David
society. The better we build, the better our Baron writes: “if a cougar can walk from
lives will be – such is the thinking that begets South Dakota to Connecticut, a cougar
a building and spawns a way of dwelling. Yet, could show up anywhere” (Baron). No
invisibly lurking in the ground and in plants place is safe or immune from the possibilities
is the castoff refuse of a forgotten disaster of animality and the animal revolution. The
and a dwelling otherwise. Ingested by boars, virtual of the animal lurks and can erupt
radioactivity returns but now with tusks and and tear the fabric of the social surface at
a wild disposition. Radioactive boar roam the any moment.
streets of German towns in Bavaria. The
return of the repressed: technology gone awry
Each incident is a call from elsewhere which dis-
is now nature without domestication. Godzilla
rupts Dasein’s designated unique relationship
as a monstrous return of a repressed nuclear
disaster in Japan may be a fiction, but these to the call of/toward being. These calls of the
boar are more than awkwardly made film crea- wild from animals that “know neither beings
tures. The boar have found the weakness of our nor nonbeings” (as quoted from Agamben
strength. If our strength and happiness is our above) undo a singular call (anruf) that
ability to forget and repress, then they have awakens Dasein to itself and its destiny (Heideg-
used this forgetting as a blind spot by which ger, “Letter on Humanism” 245). The following
to invade our cities. (Hawley) collection of essays by leading authors in critical
theory and animal studies assimilates incidents,
Commando Sheep: Sheep in the Pennines, UK calls, and disruptions and in most cases such an
have learned how to roll over the cattle grid
event is occasioned through a mode of pro-
barrier to get to greener pastures. Witnesses
duction by which thought thinks differently
say that the “sheep have perfected their
version of the commando roll” and are now and at its limits.
destroying local gardens. (Wainwright) Disruption is evident in what John Mullarkey
cites as the fundamental horror in cinema. In
Technological Octopi: The curious and see- “Animal Spirits: Philosomorphism and the
mingly gregarious female octopus of a Background Revolts of Cinema” he explains:

5
editorial introduction

What will the animal revolution look like? the ‘mind’s eye’ what is forever inaccessible to
Horrifying cinema outlines it for us: its our physical senses – the radically different
many stories, told through a play of sound spatial, perceptual, temporal and affective
and light, offer us glimpses of various worlds of other animals.” Loo and Sellbach
future programmes. It tests theories by then note that Uexküll’s famous work “A Stroll
developing new logics of visibility and invisi-
through the Worlds of Animals and Men” is sub-
bility, of what it means to belong or be
expelled, to think and decide, to be vulner-
titled “A Picture Book of Invisible Worlds.”
able and to suffer, to force oneself “into a They develop how Uexküll and then they them-
community,” to be deemed alive. selves leverage the genre of the picturebook to
“creating an aesthetic medium in which new
Cinema has the power to produce couplings and unforeseen sensibilities might emerge.”
between technological apparatus and animal Tom Tyler’s “New Tricks” follows on the
Umwelt to provide a glimpse of the outside heels of his recent theoretical work Ciferea: A
beyond human conceptualization. What Mullar- Bestiary in Five Fingers. Tyler retains the influ-
key proposes is a non-philosophy (following ence of critical theorists but turns to how video
François Laruelle) which undoes philosophers’ game production reveals new ways of thinking
appropriations of animals for their own ends animal worlds. Much as Loo and Sellbach lever-
or what he calls “philosomorphism” which age the storybook, Tyler looks at how “the
shapes the animal to the ends of human thought. Smellovision technology” in the game Dog’s
Production as a mode of thinking animality, Life “mounts a genuine challenge to customary
techne and the human is most evident in thinking about the canine.” Through handling a
Marcel O’Gorman’s essay “Speculative canine avatar, players extend their way of think-
Realism in Chains: A Love Story.” He provides ing into nonhuman realms and inhuman sensory
a story of assemblages of desire between objects abilities.
in the world, techne, equipmentality and the Continuing his work on life, vitalism, and
human. For O’Gorman, we are in a world and horror, Eugene Thacker’s contribution, “Apo-
worlding that implicates our relation to objects phatic Animality: Lautréamont, Bachelard,
such that desire becomes part of our thinking and the Bliss of Metamorphosis,” looks at
of things. Given our intertwining, our chained Lautréamont’s Maldoror as a work that
relation, to objects, he proposes
itself seemed like an animal, a teratological
a new economy of care in our technocultural anomaly composed of bits and pieces, a
system, [by which] philosophers would do corpus left unfinished or untended. In con-
well to intervene directly in that system’s trast to the textuality of the animal so fre-
mode of production, namely digital pro- quently found in literary representation,
duction, offering alternative models for tech- Maldoror seems to put forth the animality
nological invention that draw attention of the text – composed of multiple ten-
sideways, to the complex entanglements of drils, leaping off the page, devouring the
human and nonhuman things. reader.

While Mullarkey looks at what cinema pro- Through reading this work that inspired sur-
duces and O’Gorman spurs thought by exper- realists and situationists, we discover an
iments with the chains of techne and inhuman phenomenology, “animality on a phe-
equipmentality (most notably his Mikado bike), nomenological plane, as a ‘vigorous poetry of
Stephen Loo and Undine Sellbach utilize the lab- aggression.’” Thacker pushes such phenomenol-
oratory of Jakob von Uexküll. They explore how ogy to or beyond its limit as “animality is no
this forefather of biosemiotics establishes a way reducible to animals” but rather “the
unique mode of production by which “genuine text moves from reproduction to production,
biological investigation entails a certain willing- from representation to presentation” that
ness, on the part of the scientist, to evoke to infects those whom it touches.

6
broglio

Production and event reveal something new I am very pleased to include in this issue on
in Jussi Parikka’s essay “Insects and Canaries: animality and techne Bernard Stiegler’s essay
Medianatures and Aesthetics of the Invisible.” “Doing and Saying Stupid Things in the Twen-
Here Parikka extends work he has done in tieth Century: Bétise and Animality in Deleuze
Insect Media by looking at how insects com- and Derrida.” Stiegler addresses the problem of
municate to us the state of affairs in ecologies how we become human or, as O’Gorman
that remain otherwise invisible to humans. The explains in his essay which deploys Stiegler’s
inhuman insects make palpable a world beyond recent work, how we learn to care and through
our grasp: “the animal is not only an object of care become individuals. In this essay, Stiegler
concern but is itself a surface of registration, develops Simondon’s notion of individuation
storage media and a signal of the processes to read Deleuze on stupidity [bétise]:
concerning pollution and waste.” Global
honey bee colony disorder haunts and This is the question of individuation and dis-
informs this essay that extends from species individuation. If we are able to be stupid, it
extinctions (via Ursula Heise) to art that high- is because individuals only individuate them-
lights the in/visible ecological worlds – what selves from out of preindividual funds from
Loo and Sellbach call in their essay on which they can never break free: from out of
Uexküll “the radically different spatial, percep- which, alone, they can individuate them-
selves, but within which they can also get
tual, temporal and affective worlds.” Parikka
stuck, bogged down, that is, dis-individuate
explores the video art installation by Lenore
themselves.
Malen as “A slowly progressing multiplication
of viewpoints” which produces “the becom- While Stiegler takes on the problem of indivi-
ing-animal of perception.” duation, Cary Wolfe in his recent work Before
Dominic Pettman moves from his analysis of the Law asks how humans and other animals
posthumanism, animality, and techne in become defined by the linguistic and social
Human Error: Species-Being and Media mechanisms of language, reason, and law.
Machines to another mode of production: Wolfe ruminates on the biopolitical frame
thinking animality through the bestiary. In where “before” is both antecedent to and
“Tolstoy’s Bestiary: Animality and Animosity under the diktat of the law. Critically, he asks
in The Kreutzer Sonata,” Pettman gives voice where biopower might break with the enframing
to the “figures deployed in Tolstoy’s story – of the biopolitical:
sometimes explicitly, sometimes through allu-
sion – to describe the ultimately inhuman dis- bodies are enfolded via biopower in struggle
pensation of love.” The accumulation of and resistance, and because those forces of
bestiary incidents amid the social discourse of resistance are thereby produced in specifically
The Kreutzer Sonata produces a porous mem- articulated forms, through particular disposi-
tifs, there is a chance – and this marks in no
brane by which human autonomy and civility
small part Foucault’s debt to Nietzsche (as
unravel.
both Esposito and Deleuze point out) – for
In “A Global Cinematic Zone of Animal and life to burst through power’s systematic oper-
Technology,” Seung-hoon Jeong moves through ation in ways that are more and more difficult
a number of contemporary films that entwine to anticipate. (Wolfe 32)
humans and animals. The anthropocentrism in
Project Nim and Herzog’s Grizzly Man reveal Wolfe works through not only the theoretical
the difficulty of thinking animality. It is with apparatus of animality but also the comport-
Tropical Malady that Seung-hoon Jeong finds ment of animals – from factory farming to
a mode of thinking such entwining. The film pets to play where animals do not simply
provides “an inert interface to a world larger “react” but “respond” and give a glimpse into
than human, the Virtual immanent in the animal worlding. My interview with Wolfe
Actual in Deleuze’s terms.” addresses not only his recent book but the

7
editorial introduction

University of Minnesota Press series “Posthu- Baron, David. “The Cougar behind Your Trash
manism,” which he edits, and his insight into Can.” The New York Times 28 July 2011: A27.
directions in which the field of posthumanism Print.
is moving. Hawley, Charles. “A Quarter Century after
I’m pleased to include in this issue artwork Chernobyl Radioactive Boar on the Rise in
by Allison Hunter and Steve Baker. These Germany.” Spiegel Online International 30 July
works display the complexity of multiple 2010: n. pag. Web. 1 Aug. 2012.
worlds – human and animal – entwined and Heidegger, Martin. The Fundamental Concepts of
bound with our technological worlding. Metaphysics. Bloomington: Indiana UP, 1995. Print.
Hunter’s work from her Honeycomb series
speaks to colony hive collapse and complements Heidegger, Martin. “Letter on Humanism.” Basic
Jussi Parikka’s essay on insect media as well as Writings. Trans. David Farrell Krell. New York:
HarperCollins, 1993. 213–66. Print.
the insect worlding of Uexküll’s storybook lab-
oratory. The layers of surfaces in the bee Heidegger, Martin. “The Question Concerning
works and the dragonfly work remind the Technology.” Basic Writings. New York:
viewer of the surface encounters between HarperCollins, 1993. 311–41. Print.
worlds and the organic and inorganic assem- LaCapra, Dominic. History and its Limits: Human,
blages that are wrought. Steve Baker’s “Five Animal, Violence. Ithaca, NY: Cornell UP, 2009.
Heraldic Animals (for Eduardo Kac)” works Print.
in dialogue with a number of essays in this col-
Malamud, Randy. “Vengeful Tiger, Glowing Rabbit.”
lection. On the road to human progress, we meet Chronicle of Higher Education 23 July 2012: n. pag.
(meat) the friction of animality. Our own tech- Web. 24 July 2012.
nological capacities (envisioned in the motorized
wheel) attempt to elude our animality – to trans- Miraglia, Niki. “Octopus Opens Valve and Floods
port us elsewhere – and yet fatalities do occur, as Aquarium.” Associated Press 26 Feb. 2009. Web.
22 Jan. 2012.
Baker has captured. More abstractly, the surface
and fur of the animal bodies shown here create Oliver, Kelly. “Stopping the Anthropological
patterns that echo the patterns depicted in Machine: Agamben with Heidegger and Merleau-
Hunter’s honeycomb images. Looking at the Ponty.” PhaenEx 2.2 (2007): 1–23. Print.
honeycomb and fur we seek patterns of Osvath, Mathias. “Spontaneous Planning for Future
meaning but always within these there lies Stone Throwing by a Male Chimpanzee.” Current
embedded the immanence of animality. Biology 19.5 (2009): 120–21. Print.
I hope the reader will take these essays’ exper-
Seshadri, Kalpana Rahita. HumAnimal: Race, Law,
iments, productions, and queries as ways of Language. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2012.
thinking a “wealth of openness with which the Print.
human world may have nothing to compare.”
Uexküll believed such experiments would lead Uexküll, Jakob von. “A Stroll through the World of
to “worlds strange to us but Animals and Men: A Picture Book of Invisible
Worlds.” Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a
known to other creatures, mani-
Modern Concept. Ed. Claire H. Schiller. Trans. D.J.
fold and varied as the animals Kuenen. New York: International UP, 1957. 5–
themselves” (5). The essays here 80. Print.
expand what it means to be
human in multiple ecologies. Wainwright, Martin. “Pennine Spot where Sheep
Won’t be Fenced In.” The Guardian 30 July 2004:
n. pag. Web. 1 Aug. 2012.
bibliography
Weil, Kari. Thinking with Animals: Why Animal
Agamben, Giorgio. The Open: Man and Animal. Studies Now? New York: Columbia UP, 2012.
Stanford: Stanford UP, 2003. Print. Print.

8
broglio

Wolfe, Cary. Before the Law: Humans and Other


Animals in a Biopolitical Frame. Chicago: U of
Chicago P, 2012. Print.

Ron Broglio
Department of English
PO Box 870302
Arizona State University
Tempe, AZ 85287-0302
USA
E-mail: ron.broglio@asu.edu
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

Ontology, or first philosophy, is not an innoc-


uous academic discipline, but in every sense
the fundamental operation in which anthro-
pogenesis, the becoming human of the
living being, is realized […] From the begin-
ning, metaphysics is taken up in this strat-
egy: it concerns precisely that meta that
completes and preserves the overcoming of
animal physis in the direction of human
history.
Agamben, The Open 79

john mullarkey
Muybridge seemed to be racing against the
imminent disappearance of animals from
the new urban environment. Distinct from
the stillness of photography, cinema added ANIMAL SPIRITS
the possibility of electric animation […]
The advent of cinema is thus haunted by
philosomorphism and the
the animal figure, driven, as it were, by the background revolts of
wildlife after death of the animal.
Lippit, Electric Animal 185–86, 197 cinema

introduction: the cinematic animals


shown increasing interest in the idea of the
that we always were animal as both a normative category (Derrida,

T his essay follows two lines, one that we can


call (for now) “cinematic,” the other “phi-
losophical,” towards an intersection located in
Agamben) and a metaphysical one (as when
Badiou depicts Deleuze’s philosophy as one of
“the Animal” in contrast to his own of
“the animal.” It is not that either domain is “Number” – Badiou, “Review” 55). One
drawn to the animal for its own intrinsic question that arises from this is whether or
worth, but rather that they are pushed there not these myriad philosophies mediate the
by their own “passion for the Real” (to use animal for their own philosophical purpose
Badiou’s phrase), or at least in order that they by seeing it as only an instance of aporetic
might create certain “reality effects” through différance (Derrida), proliferated becoming
the animal (Badiou, Le Siècle 75ff.). Be it the (Deleuze), bare life (Agamben), or even the
bleak picture of “bare life” drawn by very model of “bad philosophy” (Badiou). Too
Agamben, or the more positive image of the often, I would argue, the animal does indeed
“animal that therefore I am” depicted by appear as an avatar of one or other such
Derrida, philosophers of various hue have philosopheme.

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010011-19 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783439

11
animal spirits

And yet any reduction of the non-philosophical animal in their epistemological, ontological, or
presence of the animal to that of being a proxy for metaphilosophical categories are nonetheless
différance, rhizomatics, bare life, or whatever else resisted in such a way that it is the very idea
gains its apparent force in part only by ignoring of philosophy itself that must also be reshaped
other aspects of the animal that are placed in the in order for it to say anything significant about
background, namely those that do not fit (or the animal. Adopting the stance of the “non-
resist) the philosopher and his/her favoured phi- philosopher” François Laruelle, we ask
losophemes. The background revolts. It is not whether, in its (unacknowledged) attempts to
simply that Derrida’s “animots” are not like Hei- shape the animal in its own image, philosophy
degger’s “weltarm” animals, or Agamben’s, or also succeeds in refracting itself. There is a circu-
Deleuze’s, but that the ontological leverage larity of philosophical explanations (as Laruelle
acquired through reference to the animal (as finds in all philosophy in fact) that is linked to
when Deleuze sees “the agony of a rat [as] […] this sub-species of anthropomorphism: be it
the constitutive relationship of philosophy with positive or negative, inflationary or deflationary,
nonphilosophy”) always has an ineliminable such philosomorphism is indeed resisted by the
remainder, some parts of which are occupied by Real of animals by mutating or morphing what
other rival philosophical positions on the animal, counts as philosophy – thought, reason, logic –
other parts of which escape Theory altogether too. And cinema – which is a kind of animal
(Deleuze and Guattari, What is Philosophy? 109). thought in all of us – provides just such a
However, while no one philosophy may mutation.
acknowledge its own reductive abuse of the It is also worth asking why the animal should
animal as such (at least if it is serious in its be such a potent resource now, especially for
own intent), recourse to the model by which philosophy. The contemporary “animal turn”
cinematic animality is both articulated and in Theory appears timely, I would argue, in
“backgrounded” (especially in horror cinema) that the animal marks two kinds of limit for
reveals, as we will see, an isomorphism both cinematic and philosophical thinking that
between two thwarted desires. The very turn are respectively internal and external. The
to the lives, deaths, and transformations of potency of the (film) image of the animal, I’ll
animals (into humans – and of humans into argue, indicates the point of its indiscernibility
animals) in order to enhance the philosophical with film itself as animal thinking. The rep-
and cinematic Real also transcends that same resentational and affective power of cinema is
move on account of an inherent irreducibility, clearly immense, and many theories – psycho-
one that exposes it as only the latest gesture logical and philosophical – have been offered
by which thought tries to commandeer reality. to explain its effects on us: Freudian, Cavellian,
There remains, however, the very live ques- Cognitivist, and so on. The answer outlined
tion as to whether every use of animals by here, however, is that the force of cinema
Theory (perhaps philosophy especially) must simply is the power of the animal that we
amount to an anthropomorphic abuse of some (always) are when we think in images, or when
sort, be it positive or negative, inflationary or images think immanently within us. The
deflationary (as John S. Kennedy for one has capacity that film has to make us see and
argued).1 Is every philosophy of the animal a think differently is less about its representations
type of what might best be called “philoso- and more about its materiality as an animal
morphism” – refracting the animal through an mode of thought. Linda Williams, following
image of itself? Perhaps. Yet, in virtue of the Carol Clover, has famously written of the
resistance of the Real of animality to such three “body genres” of cinema that most
uses, there will also be a possible contrary move- obviously disturb our flesh (melodrama,
ment of zoomorphism, understood here as a horror, pornography) and, certainly, when we
possible non-human philosophy, whereby the let the image arouse our tears, screams and gen-
various philosophies that try to capture the italia, we do seem to approximate a Pavlovian

12
mullarkey

dog becoming over-excited by stimuli.2 Yet to emerge from the background as living, a back-
there are also more complex responses, which ground(ed) life itself that, by refusing to be
are neither thoughtless flesh nor disembodied ignored any longer, may also reform (or
reflections, but affective thoughts, seeing- morph) what we mean by philosophy itself.
thoughts, that are all the more potent because The emergence of the cinematic background hor-
they are imagistic. These images are not any rifies and “revolts” (in both political and affec-
less the animal-thinking-in-us, however, nor tive senses), and this is its new kind of thinking.5
are they either base or inhuman: they are
simply where a powerful, animal form of non-
human thinking resides. philosomorphs of the human
Of course, various different models of film
philosophers
thinking (and even film philosophising) have
been proposed by a number of film theorists As we will see in the second part of this essay,
and film-philosophers alike, be they illustrative the lives and deaths of animals have always
(film translating verbal thoughts into images) played a role in creating the reality effects of
or native (film thinking – and communicating – cinema. However, amongst the following four
through its indigenous audio-visual medium). I philosophers too – Derrida, Deleuze, Badiou,
have examined many of these models elsewhere, and Agamben – the same life and death has
especially those purporting that film thinks in its equally had real effects on their definitions of
own way (for instance, Stanley Cavell and Gilles metaphysics and politics, and even of thought
Deleuze).3 Such a claim leads one to question and philosophy. Jacques Derrida clearly
what a cinematic logic would look like: could it believes that his work on the animal opens up
ever approximate the precision of bivalent new meanings for philosophy, as seen, for
logic, for example? The challenges facing such instance, when he speculates that when “the
a thinking in images, indeed the challenge for animal looks at us, and we are naked before it.
both montage (the relations between images) Thinking perhaps begins there” (Derrida, The
and cinematography (the relations within Animal 29). Even his critique of “biological
images) could be pictured thus: what is the continuism” (Singer, Midgley et al.) as the
visual difference between “This and that” vs. basis for an animal advocacy can be seen as pre-
“This or that” vs. “This not that” vs. “If this, dicated upon his own theoretical inclination
then that”? In other words, how can one visualise towards difference over identity. Derrida is
the difference between conjunction, disjunction, not interested in erasing any demarcating lines
negation, or conditionals? One image simply fol- (to create a continuum) but prefers rather to
lowing another does not seem to be able to multiply them on all “sides,” thickening and
capture these precise differences. And yet there thinning the lines as he goes. Hence, there is
are alternative logics (and with that different no “Animal” (which may or may not include
forms of philosophical “rigour” and “consist- the human-animal), but only animals plural,
ency”) available when we look closely at the or, in the French, “animaux.” But animaux is
specifics of the production, exhibition, and a French homophone with Derrida’s neologism
reception in camera distance, frame and compo- “animot.” This phonic identity subtended by
sition, the dissolve, inter-cutting, the tracking written difference allows him to play upon the
shot, zoom, multi-screen, focus, lighting, back- written French plural for animals and the
ground and foreground, projection speed, French for word (mot), thereby revealing once
screen luminescence, etc. In this essay, it will more (as he did with différance), how writing
be the thinking of horror film (or the horrific determines linguistic meaning through differ-
mode found in all film) that will show us a new ence (Derrida, The Animal 41, 47–48, 55).
reality effect that involves the visualisation Donna Haraway’s criticism of Derrida in all
and sounding of the background. 4 It concerns this, though, is that he still remains too nega-
those putatively inert entities that film allows tively anthropomorphic – caring more for his

13
animal spirits

response to the gaze of his “little cat” and its our entire species in its war, aptly now re-dubbed
hypothetical response, as though the cat had “carno-phallogocentrism” (Derrida, “‘Eating
no real response of its own. How the actual cat Well’” 112). So, when Derrida turns to
actually regards him, without any reference to Bentham he does not invoke suffering as an
human interest (projected or not), is left unno- ability (à la Singer) – or indeed any other prop-
ticed amidst all of Derrida’s “worrying and erty/power such as language, consciousness, or
longing” over the cat’s response (Haraway 20). reason – but as a fundamental passivity. Suffer-
He lacks the curiosity (of a cat) to enquire ing is a vulnerability, a finitude, that we share
after its own inner life and needs, preferring (in a non-continuous way) with the animal, and
to remain within a relationship built from one- that makes us animals.
sided pity and mutual exclusion. Likewise, Finitude, vulnerability, death, difference,
Jonathan Burt highlights Derrida’s attraction thinking. The animal is here more a philoso-
to the negative, and ultimately to death, as a morphic creature than any other kind. For,
mark of his work that also mediates the conversely, Haraway’s call to attend to the
animal.6 Death refracts his thinking about animal’s own response inevitably falls foul of
animals, and the animal – as mute, as other – the usual Cartesian demand – how does she
becomes an effect of (his) morbid writing: know that she’s any more right than Derrida
for not making that attribution? Yet it is the
This anachronism in the contemporary philo-
very inevitability of this pitfall that led Mary
sophization of the concept “animal” has sig-
nificant consequences for the gaps it opens Midgley, for one, to disavow the whole anthro-
up, almost in spite of itself, between meta- pomorphism debate and remove it from the
physics (theology, ontology) and language charge sheet against philosophy and science:
on the one hand, and the animal’s specific we all do it, all the time, with other life-forms
place(s) in the contemporary world on the and with each other too, yet we don’t coin
other. The morbidity of the former runs names for our “illegitimate” paedomorphism,
deep […] The ease with which such thinking gerontomorphism, andromorphism, gynaeco-
lends itself to a grander metaphysics that morphism, or even plutomorphism and pauper-
seems far removed from the realities of morphism.7 The question is not whether we do
human–animal relations need not, in prin-
it (as it is ubiquitous and unavoidable), but in
ciple, be objected to. These traditions have
what manner do we do it?
long constituted much of our thinking
about other beings, worlds, nature, and so So, can the animal respond at all, in its own
on. But this conceptual version of the way, to the philosopher’s call for a response
“animal,” with all the connotations of mute- (from it) and (our) responsibility (to it)? For
ness and melancholy that underpin its sym- Derrida, there might be a way, but:
bolization, is a consequence of this thinking
rather than constitutive of it, despite the it would not be a matter of “giving speech
claims of the theory that sacrifice is a founda- back” to animals but perhaps of acceding to
tional act in the cultural categorization of a thinking, however fabulous and chimerical
beings. The animal is, in other words, a it might be, that thinks the absence of the
writing effect that latches onto a more gener- name and of the word otherwise, as some-
alized, and inflated, concept of otherness. thing other than a privation. (Derrida, The
(Burt, “Morbidity” 158–59) Animal 48)

It is a philosomorphic attribution that is at work Absence as more, not lack, not as privation, but
here – using the animal as one more philoso- as differentiation. This is not a differentiation of
pheme, an avatar of vulnerable, silent difference. any thing (ousia, presence, logos) but for itself
Indeed, our “crimes” against animals, according as an end in itself (ethically and metaphysi-
to Derrida, prolong the violence that begins in cally). Derrida’s philosophy of difference is per-
speech (logos), extends itself through patriarchy fectly suited to adopting the animal as one more
(phallocracy), and completes itself by implicating face for its own philosopheme. A “chimera,”

14
mullarkey

needless to say, is an animal composed from animal “so that the animal also becomes some-
parts of multiple other animals – a creature of thing else,” it is really only human becoming
montage, or assembly. Pack animals, animals that counts for them? The animals’ part in this
as assemblages of other, smaller (larval) pact is only a means to an end: “the becoming-
animals, is precisely what marks the Deleuzian animal of the human being is real, even if the
philosomorphic approach: animal the human becomes is not” (Deleuze
and Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus 238).9
We think and write for animals themselves. On the one hand, it is doubtless that this com-
We become animal so that the animal also mendation of process over product is part of an
becomes something else. The agony of a rat anti-representationalist, anti-mimetic tendency
or the slaughter of a calf remains present in in his thought: in order to “be the Pink
thought not through pity but as the zone of
Panther,” one must imitate and reproduce
exchange between man and animal in which
“nothing”; but like that big cat, one “paints
something of one passes into the other.
This is the constitutive relationship of philos- the world its colour, pink on pink; this is its
ophy and nonphilosophy. (Deleuze and Guat- becoming-world” (A Thousand Plateaus 11).
tari, What is Philosophy? 109) Deleuze’s “animal philosophy” (as Badiou has
dubbed it) is a philosophy of life that, like its
Pity, of course, would be a reactive relation that forbear in Bergson, is utterly immanentist –
does neither the dying animal nor thinking phi- there is nothing outside of becoming to
losopher any good. Derrida’s pity for the animal become. Molarity, be it of the human or the
is a morbid response that Deleuze’s vitalist non-human, is not to be imitated; even more,
thinking cannot stomach. The ethics of this it cannot be imitated (hence, what looks like
relationship is strictly affective, concerning reproduction is always a new production, a
forces, or degrees of motion and rest. It is also productive repetition). Leaving aside the
asymmetric – not in the Levinasian mode of paradox of having to commend what everything
being for the other but in the naturally aristo- and everyone is already anyway (in a philosophy
cratic mode of being for the greater good of a of absolute immanence),10 the fact remains that
healthier, more joyful relation: it is the relation there are kinds of animal that Deleuze prefers
that is the end in itself: over others in this all-encompassing molecular
becoming: domesticated (pitied) and individu-
Man does not become wolf, or vampire, as if ated (molarised) animals are unhealthy – this
he changed molar species; the vampire and being the motive behind the infamous proclama-
werewolf are becomings of man, in other
tion that “anyone who likes cats or dogs is a
words, proximities between molecules in
fool” (A Thousand Plateaus 239). Likewise,
composition, relations of movement and
rest, speed and slowness between emitted state animals (the lions, lambs, horses, and uni-
particles. (Deleuze and Guattari, Anti- corns of empires, myths, and religions) are to be
Oedipus 107) disavowed. It is the demonic or pack animal that
is the Deleuzian favourite – rats, wolves, cock-
Of course, Luce Irigaray famously took Deleuze roaches. So, qua animal becomings (rather
and Guattari to task for insisting upon a than the becoming-animal of humans), the
“becoming-woman” that would incorporate true animal is always a multiplicity (as in a
both “molar” women and men within a wolf pack) and a process (every such pack is a
greater molecular process, to the neglect of wolfing).
any real identitarian politics (whose achieve- On the other hand, however, qua becoming-
ments had only recently been hard-won by animal, what should be (at least) a two-sided
actual women).8 Might not the same be said of process involving healthy, active becomings
this “becoming-animal” in as much as, pace for all participants invariably profits only the
their assertion that Deleuze and Guattari think human. For example, in the section on
and write “for animals” and even become the “War Machine” in A Thousand Plateaus,

15
animal spirits

the nomad invention of the stirrup involves a of Deleuzian thought, it is even arguable that
human becoming-animal within a “man– the animal must remain outside genuine becom-
horse–stirrup” assemblage. Similarly, the ing if, as he says, its agony and slaughter are
bridle used in masochistic practice is itself constitutive of a zone of exchange between
derivative of a human “becoming-horse” human and animal as well as philosophy and
(A Thousand Plateaus 399, 260). It seems non-philosophy. The dying animal is the
that, as a state animal, the horse can only outside of thought, the shock to thought, and
serve a Deleuzian becoming when participating so the non-philosophical as such for Deleuze.
in human enhancement. Obviously, Deleuze is To be allowed its own life and vital becoming
fully alerted to the danger here of “becoming- would be to allow it too much philosophy, too
animal” manifesting as a mere imitation of a much thought for itself, too much anthropos.
“molar” image (playing “horsey”), or an And yet this very withdrawal of the relationship,
aspect of horseness in the abstract or as a part- or its suddenly unilateral bias, is itself a token of
object festishism: this is supposed to be a the philosomorphic use of the animal
process of re-creating certain speeds and slow- (Nietzschean, Spinozist, Bergsonist) pervasive
nesses – metamorphosis over representation throughout Deleuze’s thought.
(or metaphor). Yet Deleuze seems oblivious to Indeed, Alain Badiou’s criticism of Deleu-
the politics of his examples, horses in particular. zianism as a philosophy of the animal (over
How can a stirrup involve any kind of becoming his own of Number) spies just such a possibility
for the horse (remembering that all Deleuzian in Deleuze and actualises it (contra Deleuze’s
becomings must be active, not reactive)? How own intent) as an animalisation of the human
can the stirrup be part of any thing affirmative? that thereby strips humanity of value. Yet
A domesticated horse may take pleasure in ful- Badiou’s intervention is not only to run
filling some of its functions, but that is only Deleuze’s animals in a new direction but also
because it has been broken in, made into a sad to protect his own avowedly humanist project
animal. The technology itself is reactive – a poli- from any possible animalist extension. The
cing and controlling of life rather than its real threat is to Badiou’s universalist and
further production. And, as for the agony of a extensionalist politics of emancipation. Given
dying rat or slaughtered calf, the technologies that, according to Being and Event, no inten-
involved in “pest” control and factory-farming sive quality can be legitimised that might
can hardly be deemed life-affirming from the restrict the scope of political change (an
point of view of the animal lives involved.11 Event), it follows that the greater scope of pol-
There seems little place for the animal’s own itical vitalism promises to undo any humanist
genuine “becomings” in the alter (animal)-side agenda within such a universalism. How can
of a human becoming-animal. What of its or some parts of the universe be kept out of poli-
their “becoming-human”? Is that always and tics in order to keep the programme human?
only a token of anthropomorphism – a matter How can they be backgrounded so that the
for projection, sentimentality, and pity? Where human alone figures in the foreground? What
is the example of human and animal change as cannot be defined as “human” if one is not
a real co-becoming, such as the wasp and allowed to define the human at all intensionally,
orchid enjoy in A Thousand Plateaus, that is, that is, through some or other actual or poten-
an active, joyful “deterritorialization” for both tial quality – species-being, gender, race,
(A Thousand Plateaus 293)?12 As things nationality, civilising power, etc?
stand, the animal, demonic or domestic, is a phi- Badiou’s concept of universalism (be it in art,
losophical myth in Deleuze’s thought, a philoso- science, politics and love) has a mathematical
morph that must play a lesser part in the basis – everything can be counted (pure quan-
architecture of becoming, for any such process tity, not quality, counts). However, just as Hei-
is always evaluated from the perspective of the degger, in Being and Time, decided to approach
human alone. Indeed, such is the immanence the question of Being through Dasein as the

16
mullarkey

most appropriate method because only humans cave and Picasso. Of course, this theme
ask the question of the meaning of Being does not envelop its own variation, and every-
(despite initially arguing against confusing thing we have just said about the meaning of
Being as such with any particular beings), so the horses remains correct: they belong to
Badiou too must justify his anthropocentric essentially distinct worlds. In fact, because
it is subtracted from variation, the theme of
ontology in the most parsimonious way possible:
the horse renders it perceivable […] We sim-
through mathematical ability. Though every ultaneously think the multiplicity of worlds
thing can be counted, because only humans and the invariance of the truths that appear
can think infinitely, that is to say, can do math- at distinct points in this multiplicity.
ematics (in a sense so defined by Badiou as to (Badiou, Logics of Worlds 18)
exclude any animal facility for mathematics),
only humans can enjoy political subjectivity. With continued regard to this Platonism and
“Humans” (of a certain kind) count because politics of the Idea, in his earlier Ethics
they alone (supposedly) can count (despite all Badiou asks whether man is a “living animal
empirical continuities between human and or immortal singularity,” and answers his own
animal abilities that demonstrate the con- question by asserting that man is “an animal
trary).13 The finitude that Derrida sees as what whose resistance, unlike that of a horse, lies
animal and human share is here echoed in not in his fragile body but in his stubborn deter-
reverse for Badiou, for he emphasises the infi- mination to remain what he is” (Badiou, Ethics
nite power of human thought over its animal, 11). Unlike a horse, humans rebel against dom-
embodied finitude. This is the one intensional ination. And they do it alone, winning power
property that Badiou must willingly opt for, as through violent revolutionary overthrow rather
well as appropriately define, so as to ensure than democratic, gradualist reform (or pitying
that his humanist agenda is saved from his uni- advocacy). Consequently, the founding of the
versalist programme, and that the concept of the RSPCA in 1824 by Richard Martin or the pub-
human does not ooze into the non-human. Here, lication of Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation in
though the animal is playing a negative role 1975 could not be seen as true political events
(rather than the ostensibly positive role it for Badiou. He rejects the “contemporary
plays in Deleuzian thought), it remains crucial doxa” of the “humanist protection of all
to Badiou’s project that it keeps to that role, animals” because, firstly, animals cannot count
that it plays its philosophical part without resist- like adult humans can count (neither can
ing, that it conforms to the philosomorph human infants or some humans with specific
designed for it. disabilities, but let us not complicate things
Indeed, Badiou’s philosomorphism is openly too much). But also, secondly, every political
Platonic: when he does explicitly describe event in the name of emancipation and equality
animals, he prefers their Forms over their must come extensionally, from the “bottom
specific instances. And, as with Deleuze, it is up,” such that advocacy (“protection” as well
horses that loom large in this mediation. as representation) cannot be a true conduit for
Badiou’s Logics of Worlds opens with the Pla- a political event (again, we will have to ignore
tonic Idea of the Horse as it runs from prehisto- the fact that the examples of revolution cited
rical cave painting through to Picasso. Contra by Badiou – French 1789, October 1917 –
Antisthenes’ remark to Plato – “I do see some involved some representatives acting on behalf
horses, but I see no Horseness” – Badiou of the proletariat).14 So, while we might still per-
contends that it is nothing but Horseness that tinently ask whether equality does always come
we see: exclusively from the “bottom up,” we might
also ask what an animal revolution might look
Nevertheless, I contend that it is indeed an like, given that the appearance of a true revolu-
invariant theme, an eternal truth, which is tion (qua political event, at least on Badiou’s
at work between the Master of the Chauvet account) cannot be anticipated through any

17
animal spirits

extant situation. How might those pushed into the man-ape, the enfant sauvage or Homo
the background, the discounted, return into ferus, but also and above all the slave, the
vision when such an event is unforeseeable in barbarian, and the foreigner, as figures of
principle, or, at best, can only be glimpsed? an animal in human form. Both machines
How do animals revolt, or rather, what would are able to function only by establishing a
zone of indifference at their centers, within
a revolt and return (from revolvere) look like?
which – like a “missing link” which is
Though appearing more ambivalent in his always lacking because it is already virtually
speciesism than Badiou, Giorgio Agamben present – the articulation between human
too (in his work on Heidegger in The Open: and animal, man and non-man, speaking
Man and Animal) is alarmed by “the total being and living being, must take place.
humanization of the animal [that] coincides Like every space of exception, this zone is,
with a total animalization of man” (Agamben in truth, perfectly empty, and the truly
77). As Kelly Oliver notes, “in some passages human being who should occur there is
in The Open Agamben seems to accept a Hei- only the place of a ceaselessly updated
deggerian abyss between man and animal, an decision in which the caesurae and their rear-
ticulation are always dislocated and displaced
abyss that Agamben suggests is not wide
anew. What would thus be obtained,
enough in Heidegger’s thought” (Oliver 232). however, is neither an animal life nor a
The threat to this protective abyss is the human life, but only a life that is separated
double-sided “anthropological machine” that and excluded from itself – only a bare life.
results, in Heideggerian terms, in “a mon- (Agamben 37–38)
strous anthropomorphization of […] the
animal and a corresponding animalization of The machine creates anthropomorphs (animals
man” (Agamben 58). A monstrous anthropo- become human), but also, dangerously, therio-
morphism, born in the modern era with nine- morphs (animalised humans): the political
teenth-century biologism. But the machine dangers of abusing the latter are clear to
has a longer history to it than just this, given Agamben (as they are to Badiou), but, as
its role of creating social inclusion through a Oliver also points out, Agamben seems indiffer-
posited “missing-link” that is neither properly ent to the dangers for animals stemming from
human nor social, but animalised and “bare.” both versions of the machine, anthropomorphic
Yet the machine works in various ways, not and theriomorphic. But that is because, for
just one: Agamben, the animal already resides within
the space of the missing link: the fictions of
both the animalised human and the humanised
On the one hand, we have the anthropological
machine of the moderns […] it functions by animal are both – in terms of philosophical
excluding as not (yet) human an already worth (reasoning power, language skills, politi-
human being from itself, that is, by animaliz- cal subjectivity, and even the ability to die prop-
ing the human, by isolating the nonhuman erly, rather than simply cease to exist) – possible
within the human: Homo alalus, or the types of real animal. Because such purities
ape-man. And it is enough to move our (reason, language, subjecthood, death) are
field of research ahead a few decades, and proper to actual, real, human life alone – “the
instead of this innocuous paleontological truly human being.” The impure product of
find we will have the Jew, that is, the non- any splicing of the truly human being with the
man produced within the man, or the
animal results in and belongs with animality.
néomort and the overcomatose person, that
So Agamben is disingenuous when he argues
is, the animal separated within the human
body itself. The machine of earlier times that bare life is “neither an animal life nor a
works in an exactly symmetrical way […] human life,” for it is much closer to the
here the inside is obtained through the former in value. Akira Lippit puts the kind of
inclusion of an outside, and the non-man is speciesism at work here in a clear light. Agam-
produced by the humanization of an animal: ben’s animals are too dumb to die – and any

18
mullarkey

facility they may have for it will have to be can be a very useful methodological tool in
palmed off on the pre-linguistic powers of film ethology.15 What is too often the trouble with
(or something like it): anthropomorphism, however, is that it is one-
way and partial. What is required is a two-way
If, according to the strained logic of Western and absolute anthropomorphism: this would
metaphysics, the animal cannot die – to the
not only involve projecting some of the molar
extent that death is seen as an exclusive
aspects of human behaviour onto another
feature of subjectivity and is reserved for
those creatures capable of reflecting on being, alive or inert, in a unilateral fashion,
being as such in language – then the death but also the absolute leap of attributing every-
of the animal in film, on film, marks a thing to the other in a “principle of charity”
caesura in the flow of that philosophy of without end, as well as introjecting from that
being. The animal dies, is seen to die, in a other all that one can in the same movement.
place beyond the reaches of language. Anthropos is thus expanded, morphed, in and
(Lippit, “Death of the Animal” 18) through the non-human (but this would be in
Laruelle’s positive sense of “non-” as broad-
As Jonathan Burt glosses this idea, the animal
ened, mutated).16 An absolute anthropocentr-
never dies because it is constantly re-animated,
ism reshapes both the subject (anthropos) as
repeating “each unique death until its singular-
well as the project (animal). It is a bi-lateral,
ity has been erased, its beginning and end fused
two-way pro-jection that is also an intro-
into a spectral loop.” In that manner, cinema
jection.17 The expansion is the charitable act,
keeps the animal “alive”; away from the dialec-
the leap of faith. It is also to “give” the benefit
tics of language, it cannot undergo a “proper
of the doubt, a gift and benefit that comes
death” (Burt, “Morbidity” 165). Animals, in
before all forms of representation (stances,
terms of philosophical value, lack all perfec-
leaps, gift-giving, and even Cartesian doubts).18
tion: any putative perfections in speed, grace
In which case, rather than reject other forms
of movement, strength, etc. are always, pace
of philosomorphism (Derrida’s, Deleuze’s,
Nietzschean thought, an imperfection of sorts.
Badiou’s, or Agamben’s) as misrepresentations
And, like other humanists before him,
(as if, finally, now, we could hope to represent
Agamben must place the animal within this
things correctly), if we splice them together
Christianised version of the philosomorph – in
and review them as equal, immanent parts of a
the horror of mixture. In other words, the bare-
whole we also mutate what counts as philosophy
ness of bare life belongs properly to the animal
just as much as philosophy mutates the animal
(as a human stripped bare of its distinguishing
to its own ends. This would be a chimerical phi-
qualities). Yet it is precisely within the horror
losophical animal that is only as real as the
of this mixing of the species where we might
number of “eyes” it encompasses (as Nietzsche
see where the political threat of an animal not
once described, with an appropriately mon-
being an animal might arise. This would be its
strous metaphor, in his own non-relativist
revolt against philosomorphic thought.
perspectivism).19 Such an absolute or complete
philosomorphism also mutates philosophy
through the animal. And this would thereby
notes on non-human philosophising entail rethinking what counts as thinking and
It is not that we ask to avoid all forms of philo- vulnerability (Derrida), thinking and non-phil-
somorphism altogether – as a sub-species of osophy (Deleuze), thinking and political subjec-
anthropomorphism, so long as there is more tivity (Badiou), thinking and humanity
than oneself (that solipsism is false), then it (Agamben).
will always be the case that some kind of leap Even so, why should the axiom for this prac-
of faith, act of charity, or hermeneutical stance tice involve rethinking these “thinking ands”
is needed to understand one’s other, whatever (as if that was a presuppositionless starting
or whoever “it” may be. Anthropomorphism point for philosophy) when we already have an

19
animal spirits

alternative means of reviewing a set of human– kinds of horror film that all cinema begins as
animal chimera that is equally affective, yet less horror, that is, in the mode of the horrific no
specifically focused on human forms reasoning? matter its nominal genre – and this is quintes-
By this I mean, of course, the monstrous forms sentially so as it shows us the human and non-
of cinematic montage, especially those seen in human, the living and the inert, spliced
horror film – such will be our model for an together. The question here will be whether
expanded “thinking” (or reasoning, analysing, this also shows us where philosophy begins as
arguing, questioning, etc.). After all, in Noël well – in the horrific (at the animality of the
Carroll’s work, for example, we have the most human) as much as in wonder. If this is
interesting account of cinematic art-horror the case, seeing and feeling the horror of the
which argues that the chimerical and bareness human expanded into the non-human will be a
of life are part and parcel of the monster at new kind of thought and philosophy too – and
the heart of every horror film. The monster, to so a complete philosomorphism.
be truly horrific, must be “repulsive and abhor-
rent” (Carroll, “Film” 39). Such creatures are
“impure,” “categorically hybrid,” compound- animal-cinema/background-horror:
ing normally opposed elements: life and death what is the monster trying to
– vampires, zombies; or human and demonic –
devils, anti-Christs, and so on. But they also
show us?
compound the animal and the human in were- A number of things need to be said when
wolves, human flies, cat people, etc. Such horri- turning to the images of animals in film and
fying hybridity defies “our conceptual the animal imagery of film. Burt notes well
schemes,” horror monsters being “impossible” that “audiences often respond differently to
or “anomalous” entities (Carroll, “Why animals or animal-related practices than they
Horror?” 34, 35, 37, 39). do to other forms of imagery.” The animal
Admittedly, Carroll’s approach will be rather image is a “form of rupture in the field of rep-
too cognitivist for many looking for a proper resentation,” such that the normal suspension
alternative way of reviewing philosophy (being of disbelief does not work for animals on
too obviously party to the conceptualist side of screen as it does for humans. The animal here
things), yet a more embodied approach still becomes a “tabula rasa” that, via developing
fits this account too (after all, the monster not cinematic technologies, offers us access to alleg-
only offends our logic but also our taste – it is edly hidden realities through posited (techno-
repulsive and abhorrent). Just as Deleuze– morphic) non-human ways of seeing reality –
Spinoza say that we do not yet know what a animal point-of-view shots (Burt, Animals 11,
body can do, so in horror we are shown the 21, 53).
many ways a human body can be mutated into It is incontrovertible, of course, that animals
non-human forms. And, for Deleuze, this have always been an essential part of our cine-
morphing occurs not only in cinema but as matic experience, being there at the very start
cinema, whereby “the animal has lost the of film in the proto-filmic experiments of Muy-
organic, as much as matter has gained life” bridge and Marey. The first film stars included
(Deleuze, Cinema 1 51).20 As Anna Powell the superstar dogs of the 1920s, such as Stron-
writes in Deleuze and Horror Film, “philosophi- gheart and Rin Tin Tin, and the first films
cal thought does not have to be abstract or trans- often showed spaces where animals were on
cendental in nature. The horror film experience display: in arenas (horse races, bullfights, cir-
offers a particular quality of thought” (Powell cuses), city streets (parades, transport, cer-
154). Just as the arrival of new cinema technol- emonies) and zoos. It is noteworthy that
ogies (like 3D) are also often occasions that cruelty towards animals was often involved in
remind us that film viewing is a material sen- these spectacles: animals appearing in film
sation, so too can we be reminded by new often entailed some really horrific event for

20
mullarkey

them. Even Muybridge staged the killing of a Gorgon’s Gaze when writing that “the horror
buffalo in order to have a “guarantor of authen- film becomes the essential form of cinema, mon-
ticity” (Burt, Animals 22, 43). Animal suffering strous content manifesting itself in the mon-
and vulnerability were equally there in the early strous form of the gigantic screen.”22 We
“actualities,” such as the Edison Company’s would add that not only scale but every weird
Electrocuting an Elephant (1903), or the thing that cinema does also reveals the potential
works of the Surrealists (Un chien andalou, horror, or wonder, when perceiving unnoticed
1929). Subsequent cinematic history displays a parts of the world.
persistent recourse to pained and dying Linda Badley cites Clive Barker’s story “Sons
animals in films ranging from the sensationalist of Celluloid,” which has a “monster that feeds
– Cannibal Holocaust (1980); to the artful – on the projected emotion of motion picture
Apocalypse Now (1979), Heaven’s Gate audiences” (Badley 39). But it is more than
(1980), or Caché (2005): each record of violence the audience’s emotions that are at stake here,
serves to heighten the “authenticity” of their it is every sensation; for as Steve Shaviro
spectacle.21 notes, “cinematic perception is primordial to
Going further, there is also a long history in the very extent that it is monstrously prosthetic.
cinema of humanising the animal (anthropo- It is composed, one might say, of the uncon-
morphism) and animalising the human (therio- scious epiphenomena of sensory experience”
morphism), through hybrids of animal and (Shaviro 30). Even in realist horror, such as
human beings (werewolves, insect-men, lizard David Lynch’s theriomorphic Elephant Man
men), or animal and human behaviour, as in (1980), what is truly monstrous and horrific
feeding (vampires, zombies, cannibals) or poli- reveals itself to be cinema itself. Lars Nowak
tics (invading aliens, ostracising “freaks”). writes:
And horror film itself, in its origins and con-
Merrick is […] presented as being the off-
cepts (genres), can always be seen rethinking
spring of an animal. By being labeled “the
its internal relations (between filmic elements elephant man” in the freak show, he is trans-
like sound, editing, performance, and so on) formed into a hybrid of man and elephant.
and external relations (in terms of such basic This animalization is elaborated upon by
questions as “is horror ethical?,” “what is the film itself, in which Merrick is identified
horror?,” or even “what is cinema?”). Horror with several fictitious animals […] the inter-
shows this, it demonstrates this. It splices twinement of Merrick’s genesis and that of
humans and animals together, through story, film draws an analogy between the two. It
special effects, and its very technological basis. suggests that, just as Merrick is not his
Turning to the etymology of horror’s “mon- parents’ legitimate offspring, but a mon-
strous deviation, film is also not photogra-
sters,” the question as to what the monster is
phy’s legitimate descendent [sic], but a
trying to show us could simply be this – that
monstrous one. (Nowak 72, 77)
it can “show” at all, that it has an image it can
show. What horror (or the horrific) does is So again: film is horrific in its origins – the
play with images in order to show continuities Arrival of a Train at La Ciotat makes this
and discontinuities between human and non- plain. Film makes things live, it animates
human images such that cinema itself, as a them (or rather, it re-animates those that have
constant sensory mutant, always borders on become dead to our eyes – it is the great re-ani-
the horrific (at its best). Paul Wells moves in mator). Cinema makes an animal, an ani-
this direction when he says that “‘shape- mate, of all. Indeed, Alan Cholodenko has
shifting’ is a chief determining concept at the argued that all cinema is animation: “not only
heart of the horror film, whether this be in the is animation a form of film, film, all film, film
metamorphoses of the monster or the context ‘as such’, is a form of animation […] Put
in which it exists” (Wells, The Horror Genre simply, for us animation is the first, last and
34); while Paul Coats goes even further in The enduring attraction of cinema, of film”

21
animal spirits

(Cholodenko 1). As Deac Rossell has also do look back: animist spirits and the
observed, before the cinema of narrative, revolt of the background
before even the “cinema of attractions” was
prevalent, the earliest film exhibitions In Japanese horror films (“J-Horror”) like
astounded people less for their foregrounds of Ringu (1998) and Ju-On (2003), then, it is the
moving people (already seen long ago in magic image itself that is monstrous: black and
lantern shows), than for the background move- white, silent, and emerging from the screen’s
ment of things normally left unnoticed, such background – like the Lumière brothers’ train.
as the shifting leaves in the trees.23 Astounding, And what is this image trying to show us if
or horrific. It is not that the horror is in the story not that it is alive? Film – best known through
qua narrative genre, or in the presence of the the old names, Biograph, Vitascope, Bioscop –
monster, or in the performances, or any other animates whatever it shows: it is the re-animat-
element of the mise-en-scène: it is potentially ing process as such. Ringu is a film that plays
in all of these contents in as much as film can with images in order to show ties connecting
make things weird and horrific in all sorts of the living and the inert – in photographs,
small ways. It is in the how, how these contents videos, telephones, all optical and audio
are shown, how they appear (or make them- media. And it is Japanese animism that lies at
selves appear) out of the background. The how the heart of not just J-Horror but the very
of film, when horrific, is a way of showing horror, and wonder, of cinema itself.
and sounding that renews the optical and the This animist element must not be underesti-
auditory. mated.26 As Koji Suzuki, the author of the
When the horrific is seen as this modal Ringu books, said in a 2005 interview:
process, then, and not as a genre, we get
beyond any idea of generic essence, or rather, in America and Europe most horror movies
we forward the horrific as the essence of non- tell the story of the extermination of evil
essence, as the process of hybridisation: creating spirits. Japanese horror movies end with a
new ideas of the generic, the general, and genre. suggestion that the spirit still remains at
Horror then becomes a kind of (philosophical) large. That’s because the Japanese don’t
regard spirits only as enemies, but as beings
conceptualisation and generalisation, whereby
that co-exist with this world of ours.
concepts mix and mutate and everything (Balmain ix)
oozes, becomes “weird.”24 The best horrors
fail to conform to a “standard cinematic form” Of course, there is also the inorganic life of
therefore: things are slightly too close, or too things that “animates the inanimate” in
far away, askew, too loud, or too quiet; they German expressionist horror such as Nosferatu
renew the optical and auditory with weirdness, (that Deleuze himself points to).27 But in
such that when a human body, for example, is Ringu, Ju-On and much contemporary Asian
seen up close too much, it is no longer human horror (such as Shutter or Pulse), it is television
at all but becomes a mass of pitted matter. For sets, photocopiers, and photographs that come
an anthropocentric phenomenology such as alive, such that the animism is of the optical
Merleau-Ponty’s, these normative terms like machine itself.28 Stephen Asma puts this is
“too close” or “too far” indicate that the Freudian terms: Ju-On and Ringu are explora-
“true” meaning of the thing itself, in this case tions of “the uncanniness of mundane objects,
the human living body, only becomes manifest motions, and lights” (Asma 318 n. 24). Yet we
within a certain range of distances (Merleau- should not let the horrific descend into the
Ponty 302).25 But to a non-human philosophy Oedipal pit: the uncanniness here does not
– such as is found in horror cinema – it concern a return of a repressed familial past
reveals new lives that normally remain in the but a direct, optical non-human present, emer-
background. ging from our background into our foreground.

22
mullarkey

The return of the oppressed. These animate and conclusion: towards a


animal spirits “co-exist” with us, though nor- non-philosophy of animal revolt
mally only as consigned to the background.
This can be seen, for example, in the US With the return of the (evental) subject in Con-
remake of Ju-On, which plays fast and loose tinental philosophy through Badiou’s work, one
with the original multiple family-centred story- might have thought that there could be an eman-
lines, yet is extremely faithful to its key, horri- cipatory politics for animal subjects that is not
fic, optical situations. Jay McRoy gets this top down and anthropomorphic but bottom up
right when looking at the work of Takashi and “animalist,” or even vitalist. Indeed, one
Shimizu (the director of Ju-On): might even ask whether such a politics could
be one of Badiou’s non-philosophical truth con-
by vacillating between limiting what we see ditions, or explore its connections with the
and revealing the objects of our fear in “nonphilosophy” Deleuze relates to the suffer-
groundbreaking ways that separate him
ing animal, or Agamben’s definition of “first
aesthetically from other directors, Shimizu
philosophy” in terms of the “becoming human
creates a text that may well alter forever the
way that some viewers process cinematic of the living being.” Can such a suffering or
horror. By frequently relegating frightening (for Derrida) “vulnerable” animal be a political
images to the extreme edges of the frame, subject, can it too “become human”? Badiou is
thereby investing them with the power of a adamant that it cannot: quoting one of his
fleeting, yet troubling figure glimpsed per- masters, Sartre, he is dogmatically against the
ipherally but never completely, Shimizu art- possibility of animals being political subjects;
fully manipulates the audience’s gaze, after all, “every anti-communist is a dog.”32
creating the impression that we may have Hence, his Logics of Worlds concludes by
just witnessed a flash of something disquiet- returning to its introductory attack on what he
ing – as if from the corner of our collective
portrays as our current age of vitalism or
eye. (McRoy 181)29
“democratic materialism,” which Badiou
J-Horror goes beyond the intermingling of molar decries as merely living a life “without Idea”
humans and animals that characterises Western (as opposed to a “living for an Idea” that he
horror such as The Wolfman, and instead claims to find in materialist dialectics).
mixes the living and the inert, the optical fore- However, other critics, such as Katerina Kolo-
ground and background, centre and periphery.30 zova, make exactly the opposite point by empha-
But it does so in order to show, to demonstrate as sising a “solidarity” with the suffering, animal
only film can, that what we saw as dead is actu- body as a non-philosophical basis for politics.33
ally alive and always was: animism is not a haun- Real, horrific, pain is the basis for a true “political
tology. J-Horror is not object-oriented horror (as universal,” a “lived revolution.” And, in extrapo-
a kind of “spooky physics,” as Gerald Edelman lating from the non-philosophy of Laruelle, with
might label it); it is background-oriented, her we too can posit a non-human politics and
looking back and “thinking backwards” or in thought that can show us what a bottom-up poli-
“reverse” (undoing the Kantian anthropocentr- tics of the animal might look like – through cine-
ism and philosomorphism of the Real). Or matic thought.34 The “non-human” is not a
rather, it is when the background will no longer negation but an extension, a mutation of the
be ignored and reasserts itself as a kind of human into the animal and vice versa. What
optical and audio subject, a kind of human that Agamben describes as the “non-man produced
was never, in-itself, an object at all, but only within the man” is not the opposite of first phil-
seemingly so through our disregard. This is its osophy (or “anthropogenesis”) but its fulfilment
revolt, its return that forces us to look back in the non-philosophical extension of the
at it.31 human, a “human-without-humanism.”35 In

23
animal spirits

Forme et objet, Tristan Garcia cites the view of The newfound object of enquiry for philos-
anthropologist Eduardo Viveiros de Castro that ophy, animals, not only mediates our understand-
what counts as human is entirely perspectival, ing of the animal but also our image both of
such that “in the world for us, an animal what counts as a proper philosophical object
species amongst others, we are ‘human’, but in and even of what counts as proper philosophy
the world of the jaguar, another animal species, (and so “non-philosophy”) itself.36 Philosophy
the jaguar is ‘human’ for itself” (Garcia 240). is no longer unconditioned, free thought, but
This is also Laruelle’s absolute democracy, becomes highly conditionable. The reality
which democratises what democracy means, and effects of both cinema and philosophy are
who it stands for, in the non-human and non- indeed Pavlovian in essence, because both con-
person (or “in-person”), always expanding the verge on the animal from internal and external
sense of these terms by mutation. Whether any directions, centripetally and centrifugally. Their
of these non-philosophical and non-humanist shared power points to the conditionable animal
strategies escape the charge of being anthropo- immanent within “us” (as currently defined).
morphic or even another form of philosomorph- And this affects politics too, being the idea
ism remains moot. Indeed, the real question most consistent with Alain Badiou’s and
may be whether they actually need to escape it Jacques Rancière’s view that the political
at all. An absolute philosomorphism refracts event is one that remaps what counts as the pol-
and mutates both the (non-human) animal and itical and non-political as such, and so who
(human) philosophy into something new. counts as one amongst the polis, as my neigh-
In “Thought Creatures,” Eugene Thacker bour or companion – as a “who,” not a
writes: “what.” There are others that perceptibly help
make my self, that are “like” what it is like to
Political vitalism is the sovereign correlative be me – mirror-others, other-humans. But
to the kind of vitalism-without-content that many others may only emerge through an
Agamben critically speaks of. It is the “ani- expanded alterity. They are Laruellean in the
mation” of sovereign power as legitimized sense of being “non-”human actors, “strangers
by a higher order, or by a vital principle [who] insert themselves ‘by force’ into a com-
that is not immanent to the field within
munity,” in zones of affectivity and oppres-
which politics possibly takes place […]
Thus the question: What would we have to
sion-revolt – mutual regards which can be
“abandon” in the political-as-human in seen, have affects on each other, if only initially
order to think beyond this political vitalism in horror (Laruelle, “The Generic” 240). They
and consider a different kind of “vital poli- are animals who sense each other’s joy and
tics”? (Thacker, “Thought Creatures” 328) pain, and feel a “solidarity” with those affects.
The background revolts of cinema are forms
Our answer to this question is that, far from aban- of multiple philosomorphism that force us to
doning the “political-as-human,” we expand it in a attend to other morphisms, ones that change
genuine universalism. Absolute anthropomorph- us, change what counts as philosophy, what
ism is projection for its own sake, a charitableness counts as thought, what counts as the political,
without end, or total benefit of any doubt. And this and what counts as human. The political under-
indefinite charity only works through a simul- ground is the background. What will the animal
taneous introjection from the animal that extends revolution look like? Horrifying cinema outlines
the human. The animal is like me because I it for us: its many stories, told through a play of
change (morph, mutate) like the animal. It is the sound and light, offer us glimpses of various
openness to sharing, to ex-change, that we share future programmes. It tests theories by develop-
(not any same fixed powers of sensibility, reason, ing new logics of visibility and invisibility,
language, or whatever else). It is not a matter of of what it means to belong or be expelled,
knowing what it is like to be x, but feeling open to think and decide, to be vulnerable and to
to becoming x. suffer, to force oneself “into a community,” to

24
mullarkey

be deemed alive. And the audience – so-called by the character of Lord Chandos in Hugo von
“human-animals” at the cinema – participate in Hofmannsthal’s epistolary fable. See Lawlor.
this too. Why, though, is this glimpse so abject 12 In A Thousand Plateaus (Deleuze and Guattari
to some and so desirable to others? Or, in the 316) there is the example of the Stagemaker bird
terms set by this essay, why is an emergence as a kind of artist (“the stagemaker practices art
from the background horrific to some and won- brut. Artists are stagemakers, even when they
drous to others? In The Enigmatic Body, Jean- tear up their own posters”), but this is on
Louis Schefer writes that “at bottom, the account of the transversal and inhuman nature of
cinema is an abattoir” – a public spectacle of art rather than the becoming-human of the bird
death and deformation (Schefer 120). And, as per se.
Michael Grant glosses this, it may be that a 13 For a full critique of Badiou’s illegitimate exclu-
monster is “nothing other than a perpetual suf- sion of animal advocacy from his concept of the
fering of love and its animal political event, at least as described in Being and
lament” (Grant 130). Perhaps Event, see Mullarkey, Post-Continental Philosophy
there is also some guilt at the 117–21.
core of the horrific, but therewith 14 Remember that we cannot sidestep this charge
also the possibility of reparation (of top-down class-representationalism being
alongside its threat. operative within an event) by saying that at least
all involved were human, because that begs the
question as to what/who counts as human (that
is, it predefines the human intensionally).
notes
15 See the essays collected in Daston and Mitman.
1 See Kennedy.
16 The “non-” in “non-philosophy” should be seen
2 See Williams; Clover. in terms of the “non-” in “non-Euclidean” geome-
3 See Mullarkey, Philosophy. tries, being part of a “mutation” that locates philos-
ophy as one instance in a larger set of theoretical
4 See Thomas for the difference between “mode” forms – it is not its negation but a “generalisation”
and “genre” here. of philosophy. See Laruelle, En tant qu’un 8, 99ff.;
5 For more on the philosophical background to idem, Philosophie 247.
this non-philosophical use of the term “back- 17 Compare this: Indeed, panpsychist thought has
ground,” see Mullarkey, “Spirit.” often been accused of anthropomorphisation; of
6 This is something that Derrida himself avows – “retrojecting purely human mental traits into the
“I who always feel turned toward death” (H.C. for non-human world” (Harman 212). That is, rather
Life 36). than stopping at the point of saying ice has a
world – its own “psychic reality” (ibid.) – some
7 See Midgley 349 n. 21. panpsychists might go as far as to say the ice is
8 See Irigaray 141. dreaming of the time when it was water. Likewise,
much panpsychist thinking seems to leave the hier-
9 Deleuze continues that this is true of the becom- archy and ontological distinction of human and
ing of the animal as well, in its “becoming some- non-human intact: “Panpsychists typically see the
thing else.” But his oblique reference to human mind as a unique, highly-refined instance
“something else” is in clear contrast with the of some more universal concept. They argue that
order of human becomings (from woman mind in, say, lower animals, plants, or rocks is
through animal to imperceptible) – animal becom- neither as sophisticated nor as complex as that of
ing does not interest him in as much as it might par- human beings” (Skrbina). But the response to this
ticipate in anything affirmative for it. is not to say that humans and stones or humans
and ice are the same. It is to establish a horizontal
10 See Mullarkey, Post-Continental Philosophy 36–41.
continuum where human thought may be con-
11 The reference to the dying rat cited in the strued as “a more complicated variant of relations
above quotation stems from the use of rat poison already found amidst atoms and stones,” but

25
animal spirits

without assuming that more complicated necess- morphisms – isn’t that enough of a definition?
arily equals better or more important or valuable The closer the anthropos comes to this distri-
or deserving of greater rights (Harman 212). bution, the more human it is. The farther
away it moves, the more it takes on multiple
18 We must recognise that such a “leap” has
forms in which its humanity quickly becomes
always already been made, that this leap is a retro-
indiscernible […]
active construction. See Laruelle, Non-philosophy
Project 92–93.
It is this loss of discernibility that is horrific to the
19 See Nietzsche 119. self-styled “humans.” Matt Hills’ event-based defi-
nition of art-horror looks at Blair Witch, The Haunt-
20 It will be in recent Japanese horror where inan- ing and Event Horizon in terms of which they all fail
imate matter, especially optical devices, takes on to conform to a “standard cinematic form” (to use
life, that the horror in and of cinema becomes C.S. Tashiro’s term) built on “middle distances, the
most perspicuous. cutting patterns of spaces calculated to human
21 See Mullarkey’s Philosophy for an analysis of the scale” (Hills 146ff.).
double-edged nature of this specific attempt at a
reality effect created through manipulating real 26 It has even been proposed that a “Japanese
death. National Science” could “reconcile us with nature
instead of opposing it.” Here we see the possibility
22 Coats cited in Cohen 24 n. 39. of an identification of the human with the inert that
would be less likely to bring with it the usual con-
23 See Rossell.
notations of a horrifying reduction in value: see
24 On weird horror, see Miéville. Stengers 133.
25 If there is an appearance of essentialism as 27 See Powell 27.
regards both the meaning of horror and the
28 There are apparently possessed photographs in
animal for this essay too, one must keep in mind
Western horror films like The Omen or Final Desti-
the processual and perspectival “nature” of the
nation 3, The Shining and The Others, as well as
two that is being forwarded; that is, these
seemingly demonic televisions in Poltergeist and
“revolting” animals only indicate an abyss –
mirrors in Mirrors, but these are usually signs of,
wherein everything lives (the “animal” here really
or portals, to other realms of life, rather than
being a place-holder or Trojan-horse for
living entities in themselves.
animism) – to an anthropocentric point of view,
which is itself always shifting. (Though, of course, 29 And again:
these shifts in what counts as anthropos may be
rationalised as the discovery of the same human the film thus associates ubiquitous techno-
essence in new populations, rather than a mutation logical mediation – that is, the cameras,
of that essence – which is really to say that it has no television sets, videocassette recorders, tele-
essence.) Hence, the revolting animal is both “hor- phones and other such hardware fore-
rific” in Carroll’s terms (repulsively interstitial) and grounded throughout the film – with the
political (because it redraws the lines around what/ intrusion of “posthuman” otherness into
who count as living beings). But those lines are contemporary cultural life. (41)
always perspectival. Latour (137) captures this
thought in the following: 30 As Dennis Giles writes (37): “cinema is never
the raw vision of desire […] the experience of
The expression “anthropomorphic” con- cinema is simultaneously a screening and a screen-
siderably underestimates our humanity. We ing off.”
should be talking about morphism. Morphism 31 See Mullarkey, Reverse Mutations.
is the place where technomorphisms, zoo-
morphisms, phusimorphisms, ideomorph- 32 Cited in Badiou, Infinite Thought 127.
isms, theomorphisms, sociomorphisms, 33 See Kolozova.
psychomorphisms, all come together. Their
alliances and their exchanges, taken together, 34 The following all-too-condensed discussion of
are what define the anthropos. A weaver of Laruelle’s work can be supplemented with readings

26
mullarkey

contained in Mullarkey and Smith which aim to explain Burt, Jonathan. Animals in Film. London: Reaktion,
as best as possible the challenging and novel aspects of 2002. Print.
Laruelle’s very “non-standard” philosophy.
Burt, Jonathan. “Morbidity and Vitalism: Derrida,
35 See Laruelle, Struggle and Utopia. Bergson, Deleuze, and Animal Film Imagery.”
Configurations 14 (2006): 157–79. Print.
36 Eugene Thacker also links this non-philosophy
to a horror of the non-human world “[…] Carroll, Noël. “Film, Emotion, and Genre.”
‘horror’ is a non-philosophical attempt to think about Passionate Views: Film Cognition, and Emotion. Ed.
the world-without-us philosophically” (In the Dust of Carl Plantinga and Greg Smith. Baltimore: Johns
this Planet 9). And further: Hopkins UP, 1999. 21–47. Print.
Carroll, Noël. “Why Horror?” Horror Film Reader.
what genre horror does do is it takes aim at Ed. Mark Jancovich. London: Routledge, 2002.
the presuppositions of philosophical inquiry 33–45. Print.
– that the world is always the world-for-us
– and makes of those blind spots its central Cholodenko, Alan. “The Animation of Cinema.”
concern, expressing them not in abstract Semiotic Review of Books 18.2 (2008): 1–10. Print.
concepts but in a whole bestiary of imposs- Clover, Carol J. “Her Body Himself: Gender in the
ible life forms – mists, oozes, blobs, slime, Slasher Film.” Representations 20 (1987): 187–228.
clouds, and muck. Or, as Plato once put it, Print.
“hair, mud, and dirt.”
Cohen, Jerome J. Monster Theory. Minneapolis: U of
Minnesota P, 1996. Print.
bibliography Daston, Lorraine, and Gregg Mitman, eds. Thinking
Agamben, Giorgio. The Open: Man and Animal. Trans. with Animals: New Perspectives on Anthropomorphism.
Kevin Attell. Palo Alto: Stanford UP, 2004. Print. New York: Columbia UP, 2006. Print.
Asma, Stephen T. On Monsters: An Unnatural History Deleuze, Gilles. Cinema 1: The Movement-Image.
of our Worst Fears. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2009. Print. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam.
London: Athlone, 1986. Print.
Badiou, Alain. Being and Event. Trans. Oliver
Feltham. London: Continuum, 2006. Print. Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. Anti-Oedipus.
Trans. Robert Hurley, Mark Seem, and Helen
Badiou, Alain. Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding
R. Lane. London: Athlone, 1984. Print.
of Evil. Trans. Peter Hallward. London: Verso,
2001. Print. Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand
Plateaus. Trans. Brian Massumi. London: Athlone,
Badiou, Alain. Infinite Thought: Truth and the Return
1987. Print.
to Philosophy. Trans. and ed. Oliver Feltham and
Justin Clemens. London: Continuum, 2003. Print. Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. What is
Philosophy? Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Graham
Badiou, Alain. Logics of Worlds. Trans. Alberto
Burchill. London: Verso, 1994. Print.
Toscano. London: Continuum, 2009. Print.
Derrida, Jacques. The Animal that Therefore I Am. Trans.
Badiou, Alain. “Review of Gilles Deleuze, The Fold:
David Wills. New York: Fordham UP, 2008. Print.
Leibniz and the Baroque.” Gilles Deleuze and the
Theatre of Philosophy. Ed. Constantin V. Boundas Derrida, Jacques. “‘Eating Well’, or the Calculation
and Dorothea Olkowski. London: Routledge, of the Subject: An Interview with Jacques Derrida.”
1994. 51–69. Print. Who Comes after the Subject? Ed. Eduardo Cadava,
Peter Connor, and Jean Luc-Nancy. Trans. Peter
Badiou, Alain. Le Siècle. Paris: Seuil, 2005. Print.
Connor and Avital Ronnell. London: Routledge,
Badley, Linda. Film, Horror and the Body Fantastic. 1991. 96–119. Print.
Westport: Greenwood, 1995. Print.
Derrida, Jacques. H.C. for Life, That is to Say. Trans.
Balmain, Colette. Introduction to Japanese Horror Laurent Milesi and Stefan Herbrechter. Palo Alto:
Film. Edinburgh: Edinburgh UP, 2008. Print. Stanford UP, 2006. Print.

27
animal spirits

Garcia, Tristan. Forme et objet. Un traité des choses. Lawlor, Leonard. “Following the Rats: Becoming
Paris: PUF, 2011. Print. Animal in Deleuze and Guattari.” SubStance 37.3
(2008): 169–87. Print.
Giles, Dennis. “Conditions of Pleasure in Horror
Cinema.” Planks of Reason: Essays on the Horror Lippit, Akira. “The Death of the Animal.” Film
Film. Ed. Barry Keith Grant and Christopher Quarterly 56 (2002): 9–22. Print.
Sharret. Lanham, MD: Scarecrow, 2004. 36–49.
Lippit, Akira. Electric Animal. Minneapolis: U of
Print.
Minnesota P, 2000. Print.
Grant, Michael. “On the Question of the Horror
McRoy, Jay. “Case Study: Cinematic Hybridity in
Film.” Dark Thoughts: Philosophical Reflections on
Shimizu Takashi’s Ju-On: The Grudge.” Japanese
Cinematic Horror. Ed. Stephen Jay Schneider and
Horror Cinema. Ed. Jay McRoy. Edinburgh:
Daniel Shaw. Lanham, MD: Scarecrow. 120–37.
Edinburgh UP, 2005. Print.
Print.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. The Phenomenology of
Haraway, Donna. When Species Meet. Minneapolis:
Perception. Trans. Colin Smith. London: Routledge,
U of Minnesota P, 2007. Print.
1962. Print.
Harman, Graham. Prince of Networks: Bruno Latour
Midgley, Mary. Beast and Man: The Roots of Human
and Metaphysics. Melbourne: Re:press, 2009. Print.
Nature. London: Routledge, 1978. Print.
Hills, Matt. The Pleasures of Horror. London:
Miéville, China. “M.R. James and the Quantum
Continuum, 2005. Print.
Vampire: Weird; Hauntological: Versus and/or
Irigaray, Luce. This Sex Which is Not One. Trans. and and/or or?” Collapse IV (2008): 105–28. Print.
Catherine Porter with Carolyn Burke. Ithaca, NY:
Mullarkey, John. Philosophy and the Moving Image:
Cornell UP, 1985. Print.
Refractions of Reality. Basingstoke: Palgrave
Kennedy, John S. The New Anthropomorphism. Macmillan, 2010. Print.
Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992. Print.
Mullarkey, John. Post-Continental Philosophy: An
Kolozova, Katerina. The Lived Revolution: Solidarity Outline. London: Continuum, 2006. Print.
with the Body in Pain as the New Political Universal.
Mullarkey, John. Reverse Mutations: Laruelle and
Skopje: Evro-Balkan, 2010. Print.
Non-human Philosophy. Forthcoming. Print.
Laruelle, François. “The Generic as Predicate and
Mullarkey, John. “Spirit in the Materialist World:
Constant: Non-philosophy and Materialism.” The
Revisionary Metaphysics and the Horrors of
Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and
Philosophy.” Angelaki. Spec. ed. on Immanent
Realism. Ed. Levi Bryant, Nick Srnicek, and
Materialisms: Speculation and Critique. Ed.
Graham Harman. Melbourne: Re:press, 2011.
Charlie Blake and Patrice Haynes. Forthcoming.
237–60. Print.
Print.
Laruelle, François. The Non-philosophy Project:
Mullarkey, John, and Anthony Paul Smith, eds.
Essays by François Laruelle. Ed. Gabriel Alkon and
Laruelle and Non-philosophy. Edinburgh: Edinburgh
Boris Gunjevic. New York: Telos, 2012. Print.
UP, 2012. Print.
Laruelle, François. Philosophie et non-philosophie.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morals
Liège: Mardaga, 1989. Print.
and Ecce Homo. Trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J.
Laruelle, François. Struggle and Utopia at the End Times Hollingdale. New York: Vintage, 1989. Print.
of Philosophy. Trans. Drew S. Burke and Anthony Paul
Nowak, Lars. “Mother’s Little Nightmare:
Smith. Minneapolis: Univocal, 2012. Print.
Photographic and Monstrous Genealogies in
Laruelle, François. En tant qu’un. La Non-philosophie David Lynch’s The Elephant Man.” Journal of
expliquée au philosophes. Paris: Aubier, 1991. Print. European Popular Culture 1.1 (2010): 69–83. Print.
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern. Trans. Oliver, Kelly. Animal Lessons: How they Teach us
Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, to be Human. New York: Columbia UP, 2009.
1993. Print. Print.

28
mullarkey

Powell, Anna. Deleuze and Horror Film. Edinburgh:


Edinburgh UP, 2007. Print.
Rossell, Deac. Living Pictures: The Origins of the
Movies. New York: State U of New York P, 1998.
Print.
Schefer, Jean-Louis. The Enigmatic Body: Essays on
the Arts. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1995. Print.
Shaviro, Steven. The Cinematic Body. Minneapolis: U
of Minnesota P, 1993. Print.
Skrbina, David. “Panpsychism.” Internet Encyclopedia
of Philosophy. 2007. Web. 15 Jan. 2013. <http://
www.iep.utm.edu/panpsych>.
Stengers, Isabelle. Power and Invention. Trans. Paul
Bains. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1997. Print.
Thacker, Eugene. In the Dust of this Planet: Horror of
Philosophy Vol. 1. Ropley: Zer0, 2011. Print.
Thacker, Eugene. “Thought Creatures.” Theory,
Culture and Society 24 (2007): 327–29. Print.
Thomas, Deborah. Beyond Genre: Melodrama,
Comedy and Romance in Hollywood Films. Moffat:
Cameron, 2000. Print.
Wells, Paul. The Animated Bestiary: Animals,
Cartoons, and Culture. Chapel Hill, NC: Rutgers
UP, 2009. Print.
Wells, Paul. The Horror Genre: From Beelzebub to
Blair Witch. London: Wallflower, 2000. Print.
Williams, Linda. “Film Bodies: Gender, Genre, and
Excess.” Film Quarterly 44.4 (1991): 2–13. Print.

John Mullarkey
Film and Television Studies
School of Performance and Screen Studies
Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences
Kingston University, London,
Kingston upon Thames,
Surrey KT1 2EE
UK
E-mail: j.mullarkey@kingston.ac.uk
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

Agency is, I believe, distributed across a


mosaic, but it is also possible to say some-
thing about the kind of striving that may be
exercised by a human within the assemblage.
This exertion is perhaps best understood on
the model of riding a bicycle on a gravel
road. One can throw one’s weight this way
or that, inflect the bike in one direction or
toward one trajectory of motion. But the
rider is but one actant operative in the
moving whole.
Jane Bennett, Vibrant Matter

How do you know but ev’ry bird that cuts the


airy way marcel o’gorman
Is an immense world of delight, closed by
your senses five?
William Blake, “Marriage of Heaven
and Hell”
SPECULATIVE REALISM
IN CHAINS
A t the 2009 conference of the Society for
Literature, Science and the Arts (SLSA),
I delivered a paper designed to investigate the
a love story
meaning of the shift from the cyborg to the
animal in posthumanist philosophy. This shift to “things” was already well underway; it was
is evident in the archives of SLSA panel titles, underscored at the conference by a series of
and is registered most palpably in Donna Har- panels on Whitehead and a keynote address by
away’s abandonment of cyborg theory for a Ian Bogost on “Alien Phenomenology.”
tongue-kissing session with her dog. I opened Bogost’s radical speculation delivered in earnest
the talk with a reprogramming of this scene what I was attempting to deliver as rhetorical
from Haraway’s When Species Meet, a poem irony. My attempted provocation, then, was not
of sorts designed to provoke fellow delegates radical at all. Still, I would like to revisit my
on an animal studies panel. Ultimately my de-ironized text in order to rescue its grounding
ruse was to ask: “Why stop at the animal? concept, which is that the trajectory of posthuma-
Why not consider insects, trees, even rocks as nist philosophy would ultimately land in the
objects of posthumanist speculation?” W.J.T. world of things, and this would be driven by:
Mitchell asked this very question in his Fore- (a) a desire to connect with the nonhuman
word to Cary Wolfe’s Animal Rites. What world in ways that ignore the lessons of post-
both Mitchell and I had failed to realize is that structuralism; and (b) a romantic wonder about
this posthumanist shift from cyborg to animal the infinite world of things acting in the universe.

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010031-13 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783440

31
speculative realism

For indeed, romance is what drives this attraction I’m sure our genomes are more alike than
to the cyborg, the animal, and more recently, the they should be. Some molecular record of our
inorganic thing. And by “romance” I mean not touch in the codes of living will surely
only the literary genre – I am unabashedly leave traces in the world, no matter that we
talking about love. Above all, this is an essay are each reproductively silenced males, both
fixies.
about posthumanist love.
We have given each other scars, worn each
other down. Mikado has intruded deeply
into my flesh, with all its eager immune
requiem for the cyborg system receptors. Who knows where my chemi-
cal receptors carried his messages or what he
Mikado continues to colonize all my cells – took from my cellular system for distinguish-
a sure case of what the biologist Lynn Mar- ing self from other and binding outside to
gulis calls symbiogenesis. I bet if you were inside?
to check our DNA, you’d find some potent Mikado is quick to shriek and squeal if I
transfections between us. We inhabit not push too hard, and has thrown me to the
just different genera and divergent families ground in response to poor handling. We have
but altogether different orders. Yet I can’t had forbidden conversation; we have had
resist the feel of him nestling deep in my rectal intercourse; we are bound in telling
sensitive backside. Together, generating story on story with nothing but the facts.
galvanic friction, we’ve worn out the crotch We are training each other in acts of com-
of many a pair of black Levi’s. munication we barely understand. We are, con-
I’ve had to tether him outside my lab, stitutively, companion species. We make each
where he waited patiently as I taught a other up, body to body, broken-down frame to
class in such worn jeans, pantlegs stained broken-down frame. Significantly other to
with dirty lubricant. I’ve also had to leave each other, in specific difference, we signify
him in suspense, behind the locked doors of through our bodies a nasty developmental
an old shed, vulnerable to the dilations infection called love. This love is a historical
and contractions of a Canadian winter. aberration and a naturalcultural legacy.
These thoughts trouble me.
How would we sort things out? Biped, This plagiaristic reworking of Haraway’s text
bipedal; working man, workhorse; saddle- marks a turn from the animal to the thing in post-
weary rider, seasoned courser. One has a humanist speculation. In short, anything
photo ID Ontario Driver’s license; the other
Haraway can say about her dogs, I can say
has a serial number etched on his underside.
about my bike, with no less care or concern, no
One has an Irish name in spite of his
French descent; the other has a Japanese less love. We might label this passage as fetishis-
name but cannot trace his origins beyond tic, vitalistic, animistic, or anthropomorphic. It is
Canada. perhaps all of these things, but above all it is an
One of us, product of a complex organic act of empathetic imagination, a generative text
assemblage, is called “white male.” The designed to provoke thought about the relation-
other, product of an intricate inorganic ship between humans and things, or, more radi-
assemblage, is called “bicycle.” Each of cally, about humans as things. The text is
these names designates a different racial therefore an “evocative object,” a concept I will
and gendered discourse, and we both discuss in greater detail below. For the moment,
inherit their consequences in our bodies.
let’s stay seated on the bicycle, ever chased by
One of us is too old for adventure racing,
Haraway’s dog, and consider what it means to
but denies it in spite of himself; the other is
visibly rusty, but still runs like a well-oiled shift gears from animal to inorganic thing in post-
machine. And we race together on rough humanist thought.
trails at the county landfill where Mikado In When Species Meet, Haraway notes the
will surely be laid to rest some day, each common misconception that “when people
outing bringing him closer to this demise. hear the term companion species, they tend to

32
o’gorman

start thinking about ‘companion animals,’ such them not yet invented […] Instead of aloof
as dogs, cats, horses, miniature donkeys, tropi- reflections on the enframing mechanisms of
cal fish, fancy bunnies, dying baby turtles, ant technology, it ought to be possible to
farms, parrots, tarantulas in harness and potbel- discuss subways and radio telescopes. And
lied pigs” (17). This list, despite its heterogen- enough with clever references to the “dice
throw” as an avant-garde literary image:
eity, is too delimiting in Haraway’s view,
dice and slot machines and playing cards
which posits that the term “companion themselves should be our theme – as should
species” should be considered less “a category fireworks, grasshoppers, moonbeams, and
than a pointer to an ongoing ‘becoming with,’ wood. (19–20)
[…] a much richer web to inhabit than any of
the posthumanisms on display after (or in refer- What the list achieves for both Harman and
ence to) the ever-deferred demise of man” (17). Bogost is the micro representation of an infinity
It takes very little imagination, then, to add to of things jostling up against one another,
Haraway’s list of companions a bicycle. This “rubbing shoulders,” as Bogost puts it, in a
shift in gears toward the inorganic, yet another fractal dance of becoming: “It happens fast
strategy for decentering the speciesist human and hot, the universes of things bumping and
subject, is evident in the recent growth of specu- rubbing against one another in succession,
lative realist (SR) philosophies and object- chaining together like polymers” (Alien Phe-
oriented ontology (OOO). But the shift could nomenology 25). The overt eroticism of this
not be accomplished without love, a love that statement reveals the truth: in the final analysis,
is apparent both in the recital of a list (“ant OOO is a “fast and hot” love story.
farms, parrots, tarantulas”) and in the concept To Bogost’s chaining of polymers we might
of “becoming-with.” link Jane Bennett’s use of the term “assem-
For the collector of things, the list is an object blage,” borrowed from Deleuze and Guattari.
of love. It is at once an indicator of finitude The concept of assemblage challenges notions
(here’s what I have) and infinity (here’s what I of phenomenological verticality or speciesism,
desire). Just as importantly, it is an indicator permitting Bennett to “rattle the adamantine
of possession (this is what I own, this is what I chain that has bound materiality to inert sub-
know). Ian Bogost has coined the term Latour stance and that has placed the organic across a
litany, inspired by Bruno Latour’s “parliament chasm from the inorganic” (57). Bennett’s
of things,” to describe this tendency toward avowal of love rings clear in her commitment
listing in posthumanist philosophy. The list, to an ethics of caring concern, which unfolds
Bogost suggests in his blog, “underscores the in her assemblages of human and nonhuman
rich diversity of things” in a way that cannot actants, assemblages that call for increased
be accomplished with ordinary narrative logic attention to and responsibility for the material-
and syntax. Bogost owes his own list-obsession ity of being:
more to Graham Harman than to Bruno
I am a material configuration, the pigeons in
Latour. Harman’s litanies are a key rhetorical
the park are material compositions, the
device in his OOO, as evidenced in the following viruses, parasites, and heavy metals in my
passage, which sums up the entire thesis of the flesh and in pigeon flesh are materialities, as
book Tool Being: are neurochemicals, hurricane winds,
E. coli, and the dust on the floor. Materiality
inanimate objects are not just manipulable is a rubric that tends to horizontalize the
clods of matter, not philosophical deadweight relations between humans, biota, and
best left to “positive science.” Instead, they abiota. It draws human attention sideways,
are more like undiscovered planets, stony or away from an ontologically ranked Great
gaseous worlds which ontology is now Chain of Being and toward a great appreci-
obliged to colonize with a full array of ation of the complex entanglements of
probes and seismic instruments – most of humans and nonhumans. (111–12)

33
speculative realism

Whereas Ian Bogost’s lists allow him to luxuri- Nineteenth Century,” by pushing fashion “to
ate in speculative ruminations on the infinite its extremes” Grandville “revealed its nature,”
modalities of being, Bennett’s horizontalizing and that nature involves human desire, inor-
ontology is a vehicle for ecocritical care. In ganic matter, sex, and death. Fashion, in Grand-
spite of these rather different uses for OOO, ville’s cosmology, “prostitutes the living body
both are invocations of love. In response to Ben- to the inorganic world. In relation to the living
nett’s romantic confession of an “irrational love it represents the rights of the corpse. Fetishism,
of matter” (61), we have Ian Bogost’s orgiastic which succumbs to the sex appeal of the inor-
pronouncement that “anything is thing enough ganic, is its vital nerve” (79). And yet it is essen-
to party” (Alien Phenomenology 23). But tial not to confuse fetishism, via Marx and
neither of these invocations confesses with Freud, with the sex appeal of the inorganic. Per-
honesty to the fast and hot eroticism that is at niola is not after a Marxist critique of speculat-
play in the groupings and becomings of specu- ive phenomenology (a project that would
lative realism. It’s time to get seriously certainly be worthy of pursuing); rather, by
horizontal. forcing such speculation to its extreme, he
Haraway’s make-out scene with her dog is reveals its sensual and especially erotic under-
emblematic of the erotic thrust of posthumanist side. All that rubbing together of “the stuff of
philosophy and its desire to make contact with being” (Bogost, Alien Phenomenology 27)
nonhuman others. This desire, as Bogost documented in the work of Harman and
demonstrates, is being pursued to pornographic Bogost, and those vibrant “entanglements”
extremes in a contest of unchained empathy that (Bennett 112) of organic and inorganic matter
assigns agency to increasingly exotic or “alien” in the work of Bennett and Bryant reveal a uni-
nonhuman entities. At its worst, this contest verse of becoming determined by the sense of
reeks of an anthropocentric colonization, albeit touch, or put more plainly, a “world of things
unwitting, as in Graham Harman’s will to “colo- that feel” mobilized by the sex appeal of the
nize” inanimate objects “with a full array of inorganic (44).
probes and seismic instruments” (19). Perniola’s positioning of sex appeal at the
Harman’s choice of words speaks for itself core of a speculative exercise, an exercise that
here, revealing a colonial and phallogocentric is less pornographic than it is pornohaptic, is
drive that threatens to undermine the otherwise perhaps best explained on his own terms,
posthumanist, post-gender, post-subject bent of quoted here at length so that the reader can
OOO. In this boys’ club context, Bogost’s term witness the erotic foreplay in Perniola’s
“unit operations” takes on a whole new phallic rhetoric:
meaning. At times, the unit seems to be
running the show for a philosophy of subli- Lie down in a state of absolute rest with your
mated desire. eyes closed as if you were dead. You are deaf,
At the other end of the spectrum, marking mute and blind and you remain like this
the obscene end of OOO well before Bogost’s despite any appeal, incitement or solicitation.
intervention, is Mario Perniola, who describes Of all the senses only the sense of touch is left
his erotic ontological aphorisms as a form of but you cannot exercise it actively. All your
“speculative extremism.” Perniola, lifting the attention is concentrated on what brushes
veil on the erotics of speculative realism, against you, touches, you, feels you and
only on the basis of this pressure are you
pushes to obscenity the desire for contact with
able to picture the form and the shape of
the inorganic (1). Inspired by Walter Benja-
the hands that touch you and caress you,
min’s description of the anthropomorphic that penetrate into the folds and into the cav-
drawings of plants and clothes rendered by ities of your flesh. You have never seen, or
J.J. Grandville, Perniola’s speculation takes heard anything, or know the meaning of the
root in the “sex appeal of the inorganic” (3). silent question of what plods panting over
As Benjamin suggests in “Paris, Capital of the you. Also, all reaction or reflex is precluded

34
o’gorman

to you. You must not give any sign of life, or that Perniola pushes speculative realism to its
laugh if you are tickled, or utter moans, cries, breaking point:
or react minimally to any stimulation that
becomes progressively more intrusive, that When you find the realization of the Carte-
persists in provoking a reaction, that does sian thing that feels in the cunnilingus or in
not withdraw but attacks those parts that the fellatio of your partner, when you notice
they imagine are the most sensitive. (34) in the coherent and rigorous unfolding of
philosophic prose the inexorable movement
What might otherwise look or feel like a maso- that brings you to lick the cunt, the cock or
chistic act of submission is not, however, tied the arse of your partner who has become a
neutral and limitless extension of cloth var-
to any sort of violence or domination. Perniola’s
iously folded, when you yourself are able to
inorganic things, which include human things,
offer your body as a desert or a heath so
are not “manipulable clods of matter” that it can be traversed by the detached and
(Harman 19); rather, the relationship between inexorable examination of the eye, the
things here is a matter of “interpenetration,” hands and the mouth of your lover, when
of haptic relationality within the “unlimited nothing else interests you or excites you or
space opened up by the disappearance of the attracts you besides repeating every night
subject” (44). As Perniola notes, “this faked the ritual of the double metamorphosis of
death […] is without frigidity. Your abandon- philosophy into sex and sex into philosophy,
ment does not exclude: on the contrary it then, maybe, […] you have celebrated the
implies that whoever devotes himself to you triumph of the thing over everything, you
have led the mind and the body to the
will move your legs, open your mouth, lift
extreme regions of the non-living,
your head if he wishes” (34). The sex appeal of
where, perhaps, they were always already
the organic lays bare the horizontality of posthu- directed. (16)
manist thinking, which is ultimately a discourse
of openness to promiscuous intercourse, Here, speculative realism is laid bare, revealed
linking, joining together – a discourse of not as an ontology at all but as philosophical
copulation. calisthenics, a sort of Kegel exercise designed
Discourse – more specifically, philosophical to improve the quality of human intercourse
discourse – is truly what is at stake here. Recal- with things. In this sexual-philosophical
ling Perniola’s image of the thing in submission, encounter, a radical objectification of the
it is essential to note that “flat ontology,” as human is chained to an equally radical subjecti-
Manuel DeLanda and Levi Bryant have called fication that can only be manifested in and
it, requires a certain suspension of subjectivity, through philosophy. What Perniola’s scene of
an end to what Perniola calls the “orgasmoma- intercourse reveals is that, ultimately, extreme
nia” of contemporary philosophy. But this speculation of the brand described in this
does not mean an end to sex, an abstention or essay may not be rooted in physical eros at all
ascesis, which is how one might describe the but in language, in a philosophical intercourse
philosophy of Heidegger, whose prophylactic akin to Socrates’ understanding of love in Phae-
logic fails to shelter him from the sex appeal drus. Above all, this scene of copulation
of the inorganic. According to speculative between humans freed of subjectivity, this
realism, try as you might to resist, there is no “metamorphosis of philosophy into sex and
choice but to rub and jostle against other sex into philosophy,” reveals a veiled desire
things in the infinite, fractal, horizontal orgy for unity and holism, for a perfectly transparent
of being. What Perniola suggests, without communication, a philosophical interpenetra-
reserve, is that the orgy is reserved for philoso- tion that, properly understood, is more about
phers, for those who are able to fully give them- love than it is about sex.
selves over to the inorganic. It is here, in his It is time to confess that, thus far, I have been
description of “philosophical-sexual cyborg,” rather unrigorous with my use of the term

35
speculative realism

“love.” I have identified a potential erotic under- But for another gives its ease,
belly in the work of speculative realist thinkers. And builds a heaven in hell’s despair.”
But eros is not the only type of love that charac-
terizes the work of SR and OOO; it is simply the So sung a little Clod of Clay,
most obvious manifestation of a love for objects Trodden with the cattle’s feet,
But a Pebble of the brook
that might also be characterized as both philia
Warbled out these metres meet:
(love by filiation, brotherly love serving
mutual goals) and agape (self-effacing, Chris- “Love seeketh only Self to please,
tian love, selfless love such as that professed in To bind another to its delight,
the gospels). As I noted in the first paragraph Joys in another’s loss of ease,
of this essay, in his introduction to Cary And builds a hell in heaven’s despite.”
Wolfe’s book Animal Rites, W.J.T. Mitchell
unwittingly gestures toward the OOO phenom- In this poem of contraries, typical of Blake’s
enon in a statement designed to be a provocative Songs of Innocence and Experience, we see
exaggeration: divergent perspectives on love: one innocent
and the other experienced to the point of cyni-
Let us suppose, finally, that all these issues cism. The first love illustrates the very well-
have been worked out and the rights of all known concept of love as agape, selfless Chris-
animals, high and low, have been established. tian love. The second love, on the other hand,
Would that be the end? Or would it then be
might be identified as philia, which in Nicoma-
time to turn to the rights of fruits and
chean Ethics (Book VIII), Aristotle describes in
vegetables? Erasmus Darwin noted long ago
that “the loves of plants” are essential to terms of a business transaction, a relationship of
their lives. Does that give them a claim to utilitarian, mutual enjoyment. Perhaps both of
some sort of rights? (xi) these loves are present in the work of Bennett,
Bryant, Harman, Bogost and others. Bennett’s
What Mitchell is attempting to do here is dis- vitalist, ecocritical materialism seems motivated
tance Wolfe’s philosophical project from the by a Christian ethics, a version of “love thy
“self-indulgent breast-beating that encourages neighbor as thyself” that includes as neighbors
moralistic, sentimental posturing while doing pigeons, hurricane winds, and E. coli, among
nothing to change the lot of animals” (x). other vibrant things. Bogost’s love, on the
Animals have the potential, in Mitchell’s other hand (and we should remember Perniola
mind, to be the “latest candidates in an here as well), which revels in the “chaining
endless procession of victims – women, min- together” of tiny universes, seems to “bind
orities, the poor – clamoring for rights and another to its own delight” for the sake of gen-
justice, or just a modicum of decent treatment” erating a radical ontology. Mitchell could not
(x). To illustrate how this procession might have predicted that even Blake, in his conspicu-
extend to plants and then inanimate objects, ous anthropomorphism, could not match the
Mitchell quotes William Blake’s anthropo- extremes to which OOO would go in its procla-
morphic poem “Ah! Sunflower.” Had Mitchell mation of philial love for objects. If you were to
quoted Blake’s “The Clod and the Pebble,” he throw Blake’s clod into the warbling brook and
would have demonstrated greater foresight watch it disperse into a myriad individuated par-
about the philosophical turn toward objects ticles, then you would have a better sense of the
that was to follow animal studies. For this is a love-sickness that is OOO.
turn rooted in love. With that, I quote Blake’s The term “love-sickness” brings to mind
poem here in full to further develop the love Socrates’ discourse on love in Phaedrus, as men-
story that is OOO: tioned briefly above. Of central interest here is
Socrates’ description of the four forms of
“Love seeketh not itself to please, madness, the fourth being mad love, which he
Nor for itself hath any care, defends as a divine state of being, the lover’s

36
o’gorman

glimpse of a once-unified body and soul mani- wholeness that it has been the work of poststruc-
fested in the beautiful object of love. In his turalism to unravel and debunk. The work of
defense of the mad lover, Socrates introduces both psychics and SETI, Peters suggests, deals
the term anteros, a counter-eros that binds
philia and eros together in a mutual and self- with the most poignant human concerns:
reflexive eroticism: mourning, cosmic loneliness, contact with
the dead and distant (psychical research) or
And thus he [the mad lover] loves, but he alien and distant (SETI). Both are moved
knows not what; he does not understand by faith in the other’s existence without the
and cannot explain his own state; he ability to take hold of a sure connection.
appears to have caught the infection of blind- Both imagine a universe humming with con-
ness from another; the lover is his mirror in versations we are unable, for whatever
whom he is beholding himself, but he is not reasons, to tap. (248)
aware of this. When he is with the lover,
both cease from their pain, but when he is The more alien and distant the other we attempt
away then he longs as he is longed for, and to contact, the greater the act of love, the greater
has love’s image, love for love (Anteros) the potential for proving a cosmic unity that
lodging in his breast, which he calls and binds all things. In Peters’ words, “empathy
deems not love but friendship only, and his with the inhuman is the moral and aesthetic
desire is as the desire of the other, but lesson that might replace our urgent longing
weaker; he wants to see him, touch him,
for communication” (248). Seen in this light,
kiss, embrace him, and not long afterwards
his desire is accomplished. (117)
Bogost’s alien phenomenology, within which
even the Roswell alien might “rear its head,”
The mutual love of anteros emerges when both can be seen as a philosophy of empathetic
lovers recognize beauty – in its Platonic, prelap- imagination, of love, driven by cosmic loneli-
sarian ineffability – in one another. As John ness and a desire to be recognized by and
Durham Peters suggests in Speaking into the connect with a seemingly inaccessible universe.
Air, “Sexual desire thus is not demeaned as As I have alluded to in a previous pun, this
base by Socrates but considered an intimation desire can be described as romantic in both
of cosmic homesickness” (44). There is the literary and amorous sense of the word,
perhaps some of this cosmic homesickness in and it is thus nothing new or provocative. As
the work of OOO and SR, and I will suggest Julia Martin argues, Blake’s philosophical cos-
that it allows us to chain together Plato, the mology, in which “every particle of dust
Romantics, and OOO, which are all bound by breathes forth its joy” (Europe, lines 18–19),
a desire for holism, unity, and the overcoming requires “acts of imaginative identification that
of impossible barriers to communication. are involved in sympathy or love or com-
Peters’ wide-ranging examination of com- passion” (60). Echoing Jane Bennett, Martin
munication media and human desire takes him suggests that the romantic identification with
from Plato’s dialogues, to the gospels of the things as exemplified in Blake’s work emerges
New Testament, to nineteenth-century from a view of the cosmos as an “interdependent
mystics, and finally to contemporary communi- network of care,” which calls for awareness
cations media. All of these attempts at com- about ecological issues, in all their political
munication, he suggests, from Plato’s and philosophical complexity (53). It does not
dialogues to SETI’s extraterrestrial hailing, are take a suspension of disbelief to see a trace of
emblematic of the human desire to overcome romanticism in OOO. This is most prevalent
the “gap between sending and receiving” perhaps in the work of Bogost, whose desire to
(151). In spite of what might be described as flee “from the dank halls of the mind’s prison
Peters’ uncareful dismissal of poststructural- toward the grassy meadows of the material
ism, he provides another way of understanding world” is conspicuously reminiscent of Blake’s
OOO as an attempt to regain a lost unity, a desire in Marriage of Heaven and Hell to

37
speculative realism

open the “doors of perception” (Bogost, Alien which OOO emanates, further demonstrating
Phenomenology 39; Blake 39). Blake’s goal its status as a philosophy for lovers.
was to flee the Single Vision which he, like Given the romantic tendencies of OOO and
Bogost, “identified in the reductionist gaze of SR, it is no surprise that Alien Phenomenology
eighteenth-century rationalism” (62). Bogost ends with an essay on the importance of inject-
could easily adopt Los’s motto from Blake’s ing wonder into contemporary philosophy.
poem Jerusalem: “I must Create a System or Citing Graham Harman, Bogost writes that
be enslav’d by another Mans” (153). “wonder is a sort of allure that real objects
It may be more accurate to view Bogost’s use to call at one another through enticement
work not as a romantic ideology but more and absorption […] Wonder is a way objects
specifically as technoromantic, following in the orient” (125). This is a philosophy shared by
footsteps of such writers as Michael Heim and many in the field of ecocriticism, which una-
Howard Rheingold. In “Cyberspace and Hei- bashedly accepts its genealogy of romantic
degger’s Pragmatics,” Richard Coyne identifies thought. As David Sander suggests, “it is pre-
a distinctly romantic ethos in rhetorics about cisely in the moment of wonder that the imagin-
technoculture, one that would lead him to coin ation is challenged to understand and
the term technoromanticism: apprehend the environment, opening a space
in literature for the negotiation of the human
The dominant ethos is now romanticism: a and the nonhuman” (286). Of course, Bogost
focus on subjectivity, a new metaphysics of is writing philosophy, not “literature.” Still,
proximity, a revival of the early socialist though he is well aware that his attempts to
dream of community, a disdain for the con- inhabit the “native logics” of a “flour granule,
straints imposed by the body, embracing
firearm, civil justice system, longship,
the holistic unitary patterning of chaos
fondant” (125) are merely instances of “speak-
theory, the representation of the object
world, a hope for its ultimate transcendence ing into the air” (as Peters would put it),
through the technologies of cyberspace, and Bogost nevertheless pursues his project as a defi-
a quest for a better, fairer more democratic ance of the “tradition of human access that seeps
future. (349) from the rot of Kant” (Alien Phenomenology
4). As Bogost suggests, “metaphysics need not
Object-oriented ontology unquestionably shares seek verification, whether from experience,
many, if not all, of these characteristics, except, physics, mathematics, formal logic, or even
of course, that its hope for transcendence reason. The successful invasion of realist specu-
derives not from pondering the infinity of cyber- lation ends the reigns of both transcendent
space but from pondering the infinite possibili- insight and subjective incarceration” (5). This
ties of object being. It is fitting, then, and not at language recalls not only the emancipatory
all random or coincidental, that the term rhetoric of Blake’s poetry but also, and in an
“object-oriented,” as Bogost reminds us, uncanny way, the rhetoric and philosophy of
comes from computer science. Just as OOO pro- André Breton. As forecast by the dizzying juxta-
vides an outlet for mourning the lost unity of position of found objects in the work of OOO
language after poststructuralism, it also pro- and SR – the meeting of a flour granule and
vides an opportunity to assume a technoroman- firearm on an operating table – the reification
tic ethos after the debunking of emancipatory of “wonder” about the universe of objects is
cybernarratives, from Heim’s erotics of cyber- not only typically romantic but is also a corner-
space to the idealistic claims of George stone of surrealist philosophy and aesthetics.
P. Landow and other hypertext theorists of the Perhaps the best place to trace a link between
1990s. I will leave this evocative genealogy surrealism and OOO is in Breton’s quirky book
from cyberrhetoric to OOO for another essay. Mad Love, in which he introduces the concept
To avoid straying too far from love, I would of “objective chance,” exemplified by the
like to focus on yet another tradition from shared discovery with Alberto Giacometti of

38
o’gorman

evocative and erotic objets trouvés at a flea surrealists were interested in instantiations and
market in Paris. In Breton’s words: not classification, objects placed in the ‘wrong’
categories” (Technoromanticism 191).
the finding of an object serves here exactly Recalling Lyotard’s focus on the sublime in
the same purpose as the dream, in the sense both romanticism and avant-garde art, what
that it frees the individual from paralyzing matters most in surrealism as in OOO is that
affective scruples, comforts him and makes
the sublime object has the potential to disrupt
him understand that the obstacle he might
traditional categories. Bogost gives a clear
have thought insurmountable is cleared. (32)
outline of this disruptive process when, citing
Of special importance to Breton is that the Latour’s animistic description of actants as
objects found at the flea market were discovered “troubled souls that have not been offered a
together, by both he and Giacometti. The found decent burial,” he describes alien ontology as a
object therefore achieves something that the “bestiary of the undead” (Alien Phenomenol-
dream cannot – a mutual experience that ogy 133):
Breton describes as a sudden atmospheric con-
In the face of the undead, we exhibit terror.
densation, “producing flashes of lightning” Troubled souls seek relief, silence, release.
(33). This condensation, achieved by an object They operate by broken logics, ones recogniz-
mediating between humans, is at once Platonic, able as neither alive nor dead but striving for
romantic and surrealist, exhibiting the desire one or the other. We fear them because we
for contact and unity described above. Here, have no idea what they might do next. (Ibid.)
as Richard Coyne suggests, Breton also exhibits
a prescient desire for the “holistic unitary pat- As tempting as it is to diagnose OOO as a form
terning of chaos theory” (Coyne, Technoroman- of necrophilia (viz. Nathan Gale’s “zombie
ticism 249): ontology”), following perhaps Eric Fromm’s
apocalyptic view of technoculture as a world of
It is as if suddenly, the deepest night of machine-love, it is more productive perhaps to
human existence were to be penetrated, consider OOO as a flight from finitude, one
natural and logical necessity coinciding, all that is less a philosophy than a form of creative
things being rendered totally transparent, writing, a poeisis that resists the closure of
linked by a chain of glass without one link mechanical theories of “human access”
missing. If that is simply an illusion, I am
(Bogost, Alien Phenomenology 4). To borrow
ready to abandon it, but then it must be
the words of Stanley Cavell, OOO represents
proved an illusion. Otherwise, if, as I
believe, it may be the beginning of a “the human effort to escape our humanness,”
contact, unimaginable dazzling, between which is delimited by both the finitude of our
man and the world of things. (40) decaying bodies and the finitude of communi-
cation (86). And as Cary Wolfe suggests,
Breton’s mad love shares with OOO an object- acknowledgement of this finitude calls for a
oriented metaphysics that “need not seek verifi- philosophy that “can no longer be seen as
cation,” a metaphysics that unchains him from mastery, as a kind of clutching or grasping via
the shackles of “subjective incarceration” analytical categories and concepts” (71).
(Bogost, Alien Phenomenology 5). It may Perhaps OOO is such a philosophy; however,
seem counterintuitive to mount a philosophy its immersion in wonder and the sublime do
of objects as a strategy against subjective incar- not suggest an acknowledgement of finitude,
ceration, but there is nothing objective about but a reveling, with varying ethical concern, in
the surrealist object, nothing categorical or tax- the infinite.
onomical. As Richard Coyne suggests, “to valor- As Lyotard suggests, the ultimate fate of the
ize the notion of the decontextualized (or ineffable and sublime object of surrealism was
recontextualized) object may seem to contradict commodification, as is evident in a conspicu-
the subjective focus of surrealism, but the ously taxonomic exhibition of “Surreal

39
speculative realism

Things” hosted by the Art Gallery of Ontario in Furthermore – and with all due respect to
2009. Object-oriented ontology, which Bogost Bogost’s characterization of academics as
describes as an “event” of anticorrelationism, “insufferable pettifrogs who listen or read first
is an attempt to resist such closed taxonomies. to find fault and only later to seek insight”
Having suggested that the avant-garde’s com- (Alien Phenomenology 91) – by limiting
modification marks the end of the sublime aes- himself to “memory addresses and ROM data,
thetics, Lyotard proposes that “sublimity is no or webpages and markup” (109), Bogost
longer in art, but in speculation on art” (211). misses an opportunity to engage in a richer
These words ring clear today if we consider diversity of philosophical things, such as green-
OOO as a sublime philosophy, a philosophy of houses, treadmills, dirt, canoes, radish seed-
sublimation even, taking into account the lings, antique wedge-shaped coffins,
various definitions of this term, from chemistry cockroaches, retro arcade cabinets, and penny-
(a state of becoming), psychology (the diversion farthing bicycles.
of sexual energy into socially acceptable mani- This self-indulgent litany emerges from pro-
festations), and finally, as a neologism, from jects conducted by the Critical Media Lab
artistic practice (the production of sublime (CML) at the University of Waterloo, where
objects). With this in mind, I would like to the production of critical objects is also
look carefully at Bogost’s turn from written phi- informed by an applied philosophical method.
losophical speculation to philosophy as One recent project involved wiring a stationary
carpentry. penny-farthing bicycle with digital sensors so
Taking a literal suggestion from Harman’s that a pedalist’s speed and heart rate controlled
description of OOO as “the carpentry of the velocity and appearance of a projection
things,” Bogost suggests that “the job of the flying across a walkway over the main street in
alien phenomenologist might have as much or Kitchener, Ontario. This project, entitled
more to do with experimentation and construc- Cycle of Dread, was at once an embodiment of
tion as it does with writing or speaking” (109). William Blake’s own applied philosophy (the
Armed with this nascent methodology, Bogost flying projection was that of William Blake’s
describes several of his digital media projects, Soul of the Strong, Wicked Man) and an inves-
including Latour Litanizer, I am TIA, and tigation of Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi’s theory of
Deconstructulator, as “artifacts” of alien phe- cognitive flow (1990) as it is manifested in
nomenology. It is in this move toward an both physical exercise and immersion in a
applied philosophy, I would suggest, that digital interface. Whereas Bogost calls his
Bogost’s work is the most productive, the work carpentry, as I have written elsewhere,
most resistive to the reification, commodifica- the CML adheres to a method called applied
tion, and Kantian classification of things. Unfor- media theory (2012). I make the comparison
tunately, the term carpentry seems to be a between methods here to suggest, following
misnomer here, as Bogost’s projects are clearly Bogost, that carpentry might be extended to
not the product of hammer and nail but of include other forms of investigation in philos-
microprocessor and screen. As such, they fold ophy and in other humanities disciplines
alien phenomenology back into technoromantic, (Bogost, Alien Phenomenology 109). Cycle of
emancipatory rhetorics. Bogost’s applied work Dread, for example, is designed to resist the
is admirably cross-disciplinary, pointing the sedentary activity and narratives of disembodi-
way toward applied philosophical modes that ment prevalent in technoculture by pointing
can help redefine the way research is conducted backward to William Blake’s radical aesthetics,
and disseminated in the humanities. However, and by pointing forward to new possibilities in
his version of carpentry, which involves “con- interactive gaming that combine laboring
structing artifacts that illustrate the perspec- bodies with digital spectacle. The ultimate goal
tives of objects,” lacks Jane Bennett’s of this project, however, is not to point back-
commitment to political intervention. ward and forward, but to point sideways.

40
o’gorman

Fig. 1. Cycle of Dread. Critical Media Lab., University of Waterloo.

The curious penny-farthing in Cycle of Dread, those neurological objects in the human brain
a bike without a chain, channels our attention that are responsible for attention and that are
toward the alien objects against which we bump the target of an increasingly invasive “attention
and rub in what Bogost calls the “chaining economy” that vies for our “brain time.” As
together” of “tiny universes” (25). Recalling Bernard Stiegler puts it in Taking Care, digital
Jane Bennett’s version of flat ontology, object- media, as currently wielded by the cultural indus-
oriented methods in the humanities have the try, form a “network of pharmaka that have
potential to draw “human attention sideways, become extremely toxic and whose toxicity is sys-
away from an ontologically ranked Great Chain tematically exploited by the merchants of the
of Being and toward a great appreciation of the time of brain-time” (85). Rather than calling
complex entanglements of humans and nonhu- for a Luddite rejection of digital media in his
mans” (111). In the case of Cycle of Dread, atten- therapeutics of care, Stiegler suggests that the
tion is drawn sideways not to revel in the cognitive toxicity of contemporary technoculture
infinitude of object being but for the sake of can be overcome
intervening in a technoculture possessed by a
technoromantic idealism. This is a culture that through the invention of a new way of life
relies on the disposability of objects, including that takes care of and pays attention to the

41
speculative realism

world by inventing techniques, technologies, Bogost, Ian. Alien Phenomenology or What it’s Like to
and social structures of attention formation Be a Thing. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2012.
corresponding to the organological specifici- Print.
ties of our times, and by developing an indus-
Bogost, Ian. “Latour Litanizer.” Weblog entry. Ian
trial system that functions endogenously as a
Bogost – Videogame Theory, Criticism, Design. 16
system of care: making care its “value
Dec. 2009. Web. 11 June 2012. <http://www.
chain” – its economy. (48)
bogost.com/blog/latour_litanizer.shtml>.
To invent a new economy of care in our techno- Breton, André. Mad Love. Trans. Mary Ann Caws.
cultural system, philosophers would do well to Lincoln: U of Nebraska P, 1987. Print.
intervene directly in that system’s mode of pro-
Cavell, Stanley. This New Yet Unapproachable
duction, namely digital production, offering
America. Albuquerque, NM: Living Batch, 1989.
alternative models for technological invention
Print.
that draw attention sideways, to the complex
entanglements of human and nonhuman Coyne, Richard. “Cyberspace and Heidegger’s
things. Perhaps the best way to achieve this Pragmatics.” Information Technology and People
attentional mode is through an interlinking of 11.4 (1998): 338–50. Print.
digital media and conspicuous objects-to-think- Coyne, Richard. Technoromanticism. Cambridge,
with: penny-farthing bicycles, cockroaches, MA: MIT P, 1999. Print.
canoes, and copper plates. To complement
Csikszentmihalyi, Mihaly. Flow: The Psychology of
Jane Bennett’s ecopolitics of things, I am recom- Optimal Experience. New York: Harper, 1990. Print.
mending a techno-noopolitics of things, one that
acknowledges at once the infinite intermingling Gale, Nathan. “Zombies Ate my Ontology.”
of things and the finitude of human being. Such Weblog entry. An Un-Canny Ontology. 17 Aug.
2009. Web. 11 June 2012. <http://uncannyontol-
acknowledgement is a necessary component of a
ogy.blogspot.ca/2009/08/zombies-ate-my-ontol-
therapeutics of care (sorge), which begins with a
ogy.html>.
rejection of the flight from finitude. The object-
oriented labor of love I have attempted to Haraway, Donna. When Species Meet. Minneapolis:
describe here points the digital humanities in a U of Minnesota P, 2007. Print.
new direction that intervenes in Harman, Graham. Tool Being: Heidegger and the
the production of technoculture, Metaphysics of Objects. Chicago: Open Court,
vying with the cultural industry 2002. Print.
to gain a stake in that very
Latour, Bruno. We Have Never Been Modern.
limited natural resource known Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1993. Print.
as human attention.
Lyotard, Jean-François. “The Sublime and the
Avant-Garde.” Trans. Lisa Liebmann, Geoffrey
Bennington, and Maria Hobson. The Inhuman.
Cambridge: Polity, 1991. 89–107. Print.
bibliography Martin, Julia. “The Speaking Garden in William
Benjamin, Walter. “Paris, Capital of the Blake’s The Book of Thel: Metaphors of Wisdom
Nineteenth Century.” The Arcades Project. Ed. and Compassion.” JLS/TLW 19.1 (2003): 53–81.
Rolf Tiedemann. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, Print.
1999. 62–82. Print.
Mitchell, W.J.T. “The Rights of Things.” Foreword
Bennett, Jane. Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of to Cary Wolfe, Animal Rites: American Culture, the
Things. Durham, NC: Duke UP, 2010. Print. Discourse of Species, and Posthumanist Theory.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2003. ix–xiv. Print.
Blake, William. The Complete Poetry and Prose of
William Blake. Ed. David V. Erdman. New York: O’Gorman, Marcel. “Broken Tools and Misfit Toys:
Anchor, 1995. Print. Adventures in Applied Media Theory.”

42
o’gorman

Canadian Journal of Communication 37.1 (2012):


27–42. Print.
Perniola, Mario. The Sex Appeal of the Inorganic:
Philosophies of Desire in the Modern World. Trans.
Massimo Verdicchio. London: Continuum, 2004.
Print.
Peters, John Durham. Speaking into the Air: A History
of the Idea of Communication. Chicago: U of Chicago
P, 1999. Print.
Plato. Six Great Dialogues. Trans. Benjamin Jowett.
Minneola, NY: Dover, 2007. Print.
Sander, David. “‘Habituated to the Vast’:
Ecocriticism, the Sense of Wonder, and
the Wilderness of the Stars.” Extrapolation
41.3 (2000): 283–97. Print.
Stiegler, Bernard. Taking Care of Youth and the
Generations. Trans. Stephen Barker. Palo Alto,
CA: Stanford UP, 2010. Print.
Wolfe, Cary. Animal Rites: American Culture, the
Discourse of Species, and Posthumanist Theory.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2003. Print.
Wolfe, Cary. What is Posthumanism? Minneapolis:
U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print.

Marcel O’Gorman
Department of English Language and
Literature
University of Waterloo
Hagey Hall of Humanities Building
Waterloo
Ontario N2L 3G1
Canada
E-mail: marcel@uwaterloo.ca
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

the banquet

I n the opening chapter of his book The Open,


Giorgio Agamben describes a thirteenth-
century miniature depicting the messianic
banquet where the members of humanity who
remain are illustrated with animal heads.
Agamben reads the image to suggest that on
the last days of the world, human and animal
natures will be transformed, in the sense that
stephen loo
humans will become (like) animals, reconciled undine sellbach
with their animal natures so to speak.
In the miniature, the guests are just about to
eat together. For Agamben, this is an image of a
coming community – the animal-headed creatures
A PICTURE BOOK OF
at the table represent different parts of the animal INVISIBLE WORLDS
kingdom – the eagle, the ox, the lion, the ass and
the leopard – bounded by the act of eating. Two semblances of insects and
musicians, also with animal heads, entertain the
guests; one plays a fiddle and has the face of a
humans in jakob von
monkey. In coming together to enjoy music and uexküll’s laboratory
food, new sets of relations emerge between
animals and humans, and, Agamben speculates,
between animals themselves.
together. In particular, one might begin to
[T]he idea that animal nature will also be wonder about those members of the animal
transfigured in the messianic kingdom is kingdom not included in the picture. There
implicitly in the messianic prophecy of are no insects, for example, or other invert-
Isaiah 11:6 […] where we read that “the ebrates recorded at the banquet. Yet once one
wolf shall live with the sheep, / and the reflects on this absence it begins to feel as
leopard lie down with the kid; / the calf
though these small creatures might already be
and the young lion shall grow up together,
there – under the table, in the food perhaps
/ and a little child shall lead them. (The
Open 3) and certainly in the guts of the guests. It is
also imaginable that in anticipation of salvation,
The little child is a reminder that the messianic the stomachs of the righteous fill with butter-
banquet is a Bible story presented to us in the flies, their thoughts buzz and their skin crawls.
form of a Picture Book. If we attend to this This suggests that new sets of human–animal
frame, the scene may be read as an invitation relations are not merely cognitive ones – they
to imagine, with the child, how the guests are felt and imagined by different parts of the
might be rearranged through the act of feasting body.1

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010045-20 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783441

45
invisible worlds

Agamben does not ask whether there might Dorion Sagan, in his introduction to the new
also be insects attending the banquet. Neverthe- translation of Uexküll’s A Foray into the
less, the main scenes of eating he goes on to Worlds of Animals and Humans and A
describe in The Open all involve insects and Theory of Meaning observes: “at one and the
other invertebrates in a laboratory setting.2 same time Uexküll is a kind of biologist-
This shift is striking. If, as Agamben imagines, shaman attempting to cross the Rubicon to non-
the table is the place where the relations human minds, and a humble naturalist closely
between humanity and animality could one observing and recording his fellow living
day be reconfigured, then the laboratory seems beings” (Uexkü ll, A Foray 20). Here, Uexküll
to be the place where the distinction between is understood in two contrasting ways. On the
human subject and animal behaviour is most one hand, we see the “humble naturalist” pre-
powerfully drawn. In one laboratory experiment empting current research into animal percep-
in The Open, a bee is placed in front of a cup of tion and emotion, biosemiotics,3 and the
honey. As the bee begins to drink, its abdomen agency of self-regulating systems. On the
is cut away, but yet it is observed to keep other, the “biologist-shaman” gestures to a
sucking as the honey flows out of its open transcendental realm, where the complex web
stomach (52). As Agamben points out, this of relations lived by different organisms plays
experiment is used by Heidegger to distinguish out in a vast “symphony” of Nature (ibid. 189).
the instinctive captivation he believes is typical What neither of these readings adequately
of animal behaviour, from the openness particu- recognizes is that for Uexküll there is always
lar to human existence. something fabulous, fabricated and child-like
Yet by placing these two scenes of eating side about the whole enterprise of reconstructing
by side, Agamben may be doing more than the subjective environments of the small
drawing a contrast between the division of animals he works with. Indeed, the subtitle to
human from animal as enacted in the laboratory, the original German Streifzüge durch die
and the new conjunctions he imagines at the Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen (retained
messianic table. The experiments that in Claire Schiller’s original translation “A
Agamben describes in The Open belong to the Stroll through the Worlds of Animals and
unconventional biologist Jakob von Uexküll, Men,” but missing in Joseph D. O’Neil’s
who broke with the scientific paradigm of the newer translation A Foray into the Worlds of
time by refusing to study animals as a series of Animals and Humans) is Ein Bilderbuch
isolated behavioural traits. Drawing on careful unsichtbarer Welten [A Picture Book of Invis-
observations of animals interacting with their ible Worlds].4 In so doing, Uexküll imagines
environments, Uexküll set out to intuit the the co-effecting relations between different
lived worlds of the small creatures he worked animal environments in ways that are not fully
with. For Uexkü ll, genuine biological investi- captured by the two conventional readings. By
gation entails a certain willingness, on the part attending to the Picture Book as a technic for
of the scientist, to evoke in the “mind’s eye” ecological thought and imagination, we intend
what is forever inaccessible to our physical to revisit the conjunctions between humans,
senses – the radically different spatial, percep- animals, the laboratory experiment and the fes-
tual, temporal and affective worlds of other tivities of music and eating, and consider
animals. Uexkü ll, as we will argue, can be under- whether the small creatures that Uexküll
stood as a pioneer of ecological thinking, describes may in some way enable the emer-
because the observational and imaginative tech- gence of new ethical sensibilities and relations.
niques he develops in the laboratory for attend-
ing to insects and other invertebrates have the
the laboratory experiment
potential to reconfigure traditional hierarchical
divisions towards new conjunctions between The field of animal studies has critiqued the lab-
animals, humans and environments. oratory experiment for its reductive picture of

46
loo & sellbach

the animal. Through the tools, techniques and names this “the anthropological machine,”
spaces of the laboratory the scientist is estab- because in the absence of any clear trait
lished as distant, dispassionate observer; the capable of defining human beings it continu-
animal is separated from its environment for ously enacts the distinction, with the animal
the purposes of isolating its behavioural traits, produced as the excluded by-product of
instincts or physiology, and the suffering human self-definition. In order to “oppose
inflicted by these experiments is ignored or man to other living things,” Agamben thinks
deemed secondary to human-centred outcomes. that the divide must first pass within the
Most research in animal ethics has focused on human, isolating the animal in the human
human obligations to the larger animals via being, so to speak (15). His aim in The Open
shared attributes such as the capacity to suffer is to better understand how this mechanism
and feel pleasure, self-awareness, the face-to- works, in the hope of countering the damaging
face encounter, or the social bonds such as effects of its continuously shifting decision
love or care.5 These studies challenge the between life that matters and life outside all
reduction of varied animal behaviours to fixed ethical consideration.
mechanical drives and affirm a complex web of Reflecting on this, it is possible to see why
differences and affinities between humans and insects and other invertebrates are so productive
other animals.6 On this basis, ethical codes for Agamben in his analysis of the anthropologi-
have been gradually devised to regulate the cal machine. The double otherness of insects in
ways in which mammals and other larger the laboratory – animals are other than human,
animals are used in laboratory experiments. insects are other than animals – draws attention
Insects, however, are not included. Tiny, multi- to the mobility of the mechanism by which we
tudinous and almost machine-like, seemingly define the human, and the fact that this is a stra-
with limited recognizable emotion or self-con- tegic rather than a natural divide. Insects are sim-
sciousness, they do not register easily as ultaneously distant and proximate to us – we use
objects of moral consideration or agents of their external behaviours to identify the base
ethical change. In his landmark anthology animal instincts inside us – and in this way a
Insect Poetics, Eric C. Brown argues that “the line is drawn inside and outside the human
insect has become a kind of Other, not only being. Building on Agamben, we can say that
for human beings but for […] animals studies when qualities pertinent to human ethics, such
as well, best left underfoot or in footnotes” (6). as “self-awareness” or “sentience,” are extended
What happens when we consider that insects to other animals, the anthropological machine
are also present in the laboratory? In The Open, may not necessarily be disenabled; rather, the
Agamben uses experiments on invertebrates to divide between ethical and instinctual life is
identify a general conceptual apparatus he redrawn in a new way. As Agamben observes,
calls the anthropological machine, which iso- often in the case of “higher” mammals as with
lates biological life as an object of management human beings, we imagine that two modes of
and study within and outside the human (33). existence seem to inhabit the one body – an
According to Agamben, the development of organic life and a life that consciously negotiates
modern science was made possible, in part, its relation to an outside. The “lower” animals,
because of the creation of a strategic divide on the other hand, seem to exhibit only a set of
between biological life – life conceived as blind instinctual traits (14).
blind instinctual acts of assimilation and
excretion, and relational life – life capable of
perceiving and acting out the relation between
uexküll’s laboratory
self and other, interior and exterior, incorpor- In this context, Uexküll’s unconventional lab-
ation and exclusion. The mechanism for this oratory is of particular interest. He does not
divide is a tendency to presuppose the human extend subjective concepts and feelings from a
every time biological life is defined. Agamben human-centred world to these small creatures,

47
invisible worlds

but nor does he interpret them in terms of fixed form, composition and meaning, depending on
drives and external traits. Instead, he posits that how it is perceived, used or ignored by each
every small animal has an Umwelt – a unique animal. “In this human environment, matter is
“foreign” subjectivity of its own. By provoking the rocher de bronze on which the universe
his readers to consider the lived worlds of seems to rest, yet this very matter volatizes
simple instinctual organisms – the grasshopper, from one [animal] environment to another”
the tick, the hermit crab, the jellyfish, the (Theory of Meaning 198).
housefly and the snail – Uexküll confounds the In spite of the potentially volatizing effects
divide between subjective relational life and of the radically different subjective worlds of
blind organic existence that is drawn by the the small animals in his experiments, we also
anthropological machine. As Sagan writes in see that the conception of Umwelt is affected
his “Introduction” to A Foray into the Worlds back by the tools that are used in its laboratory
of Animals and Humans, re-creations. As Geoffrey Winthrop-Young
observes in his “Afterword” to A Foray into
the phenomenon might be described as the the Worlds of Animals and Humans, the role
return of the scientifically repressed: what is
of tools in the evocation of animal Umwelt is
excluded for the sake of experimental simpli-
often a blind spot for Uexküll. “Uexküll con-
city eventually shows itself to be relevant
after all […] With Uexküll the inner real stantly denounces machines but then resorts to
comes back in the realization that not only do a Helmholtz world of cycles, coupling and feed-
we sense and feel, but so do other sentient back routines to describe the subject’s Umwelt
organisms; and that our interactions and signal- wiring” (238). Here, the observational tech-
ling perceptions have consequences beyond the niques, categorizations, and metricization of
deterministic oversimplifications of a modern the laboratory are so powerful in their tending
science that has bracketed off all causes that towards a complete and measured picture of
are not immediate and mechanical. (8) the animal that they seem to foreclose what
humans can observe and think.
For Uexküll, not only do different animals
So, for example, reflecting on his re-creations
experience the world in different ways but some-
of the life-worlds of the invertebrates he works
times there are even multiple subjectivities in
with, Uexküll concludes that it is a general
the one animal. So, for example, the sea
characteristic of the concept Umwelt that
urchin has no central organization, and on this
every animal exhibits a close functional unity
basis Uexküll speculates that skin, spines, legs
with its environment (“A Stroll” 6). In his
and claws must each possess their own percep-
most famous re-creation, the subjective environ-
tual universe (Foray 77).
ment of the tick is reduced to three carriers of
As Agamben points out, Uexküll’s re-creations
significance, which are highly selective
of the different worlds inhabited by non-human
samples taken from our more complex human
animals have a deeply disorienting effect on the
environment: butyric acid – the odour of
world of the reader, “who is suddenly obliged
sweat common to all mammals, hairy skin
to look at the most familiar places with non-
covered in blood vessels and liquid at the temp-
human eyes.”7 But Uexküll goes a step further,
erature of 37 degrees.8 The job of the researcher
insisting that in the subjective environments of
is to identify these markers.9 As Agamben
other animals the whole milieu of the laboratory
writes:
experiment is reconfigured. Although he uses
many of the classic devices of his time –
Everything happens as if the external carrier
clamps, wheels, bell jars, trolleys, partitioned of significance and its receiver in the animal’s
spaces, recording devices, diagrams, artificial body constituted two elements in a single
membranes, grafts and dissections – he insists musical score, almost like two notes on the
that no laboratory tool can ever function as a con- “keyboard on which nature performs the
stant in animal experiments. Matter changes its supratemporal and extraspatial symphony

48
loo & sellbach

of signification,” though it is impossible to Now if we look closely at “A Stroll through


say how two such heterogeneous elements the Worlds of Animals and Men” and Joseph
could ever have been so intimately con- D. O’Neil’s more recent translation, we can
nected. (The Open 41) see that both versions of Uexküll’s essay are
quite literally Picture Books, with illustrations
Again, the humble naturalist is also the biol- (in black and white and colour) and chapters
ogist-shaman. As Agamben speculates, if we titles that invite the reader to experiment with
re-imagine the world with the tick at its shape, colour, form, space, counting, time and
centre, then it must be movement. In the drier titled A Theory of
Meaning, the devices of the Picture Book are
immediately united to these three elements
equally present: there is a spider that is
in an intense and passionate relationship the
likened to a blind tailor (158), household
like of which we might never find in the
relations that bind man to his apparently knives and forks are made strange through
much richer world. The tick is this relation- the eyes of a dog (142), and a carnivorous
ship; she lives only in it and for it. (Ibid. triton that receives a “great surprise” when
46–47)10 sinking “its sharp teeth” into “its writhing
prey,” only to discover that it has grown veg-
At once dedicated naturalist and biologist- etarian gums (153).
sharman, Uexküll identifies the “task” of the The Picture Book quality of Uexkü ll’s
ecologist to reach the “limits” of animal worlds. writing is perhaps what helps it sustain so
But what techniques does he use to attend to many contrary possibilities – the de-centring
these limits? In the preface to “A Stroll Umwelt and the closed Umwelt,11 the “humble
through the Worlds of Animals and Men,” naturalist” and the “biologist-shaman.”
Uexküll describes his method: “This little mono- Uexkü ll invites his readers to give over to a set
graph does not claim to point the way to a new of self-evident instructions about animals and
science. Perhaps it should be called a stroll into their relationship to the natural world, in a
unfamiliar worlds; worlds strange to us but manner suggestive of the child’s passage from
known to other creatures, manifold and varied a fairytale world into an unfolding science.
as the animals themselves” (5). His investigations But at the same time, like any good storyteller,
of the limits of the “dwelling-worlds” of other he diverges from the idyll, only to enter more
animals will take the form of a collection of ima- strangely and deeply into it. What happens,
ginative forays, a reading that is affirmed by the then, if we consider the technique of Uexkü ll’s
original subtitle of his book: “A Picture Book of Picture Book more carefully by imaginatively
Invisible Worlds.” engaging with it?

THE GRASSHOPPER CABARET

49
invisible worlds

50
loo & sellbach

51
invisible worlds

technics in the laboratory told technical objects become records of transform-


through a picture book ations in human experience. Technics is the
process of the “exteriorization” of human
“The Grasshopper Cabaret” is a story we made beings, whose experience is preserved in exter-
up as part of a series of children’s writing exper- nal technical objects in what Stiegler calls ter-
iments based on Uexküll’s laboratory.12 The tiary memory. Understood in Stieglerian terms
story is a response to a picture of an experiment as an exteriorized technics, the human being is
that Uexküll conducted on grasshoppers (illus- at once the centre in human–tool relationships,
trated by G. Kriszat) in order to demonstrate but also always already de-centred, where some-
how the actions of these small animals are not thing like a scientific laboratory becomes, as
goal oriented but follow the “plan of nature” Nathan van Camp would argue, “living
inherent in their Umwelt (Foray 88). memory grafted onto non-living matter.” Van
Read as a conventional experiment one might Camp continues by saying that by focusing on
say that here Uexkü ll is demonstrating, in a pic- co-evolution of humans and exterior organized
torial manner, the closed loop of relations matter such as tools, Stiegler does not address
between animal and environment. In order to the complications posed by the presence of
investigate the limits of the grasshoppers’ other animals in the laboratory setting.14 Never-
world, he uses the tools of his laboratory to theless, his concept of technics provides us with
break their functional cycles. By retelling this a way to begin to see how Uexküll’s unorthodox
as a story in a Picture Book, we notice the pres- methodology eschews the complete and
ence of tools and technologies in the scene, measured picture of the animal that forecloses
which were there all along as techniques of what humans can observe and think about,
seeing, but which need to remain in the back- and with, animals.15
ground in order for the effect of the closed Let us now consider how technics, as a way of
loop to be demonstrated. understanding the laboratory, can be related to
In this context, Bernard Stiegler has pro- the Picture Book technique that Uexkü ll uses
vided us with a way to look upon the actual to make these tools visible. The Picture Book
strategies and technologies of the laboratory for children is a literary genre with specific his-
that is not merely reductive. To Stiegler it is dif- tories and audiences that differs between cul-
ficult, if not impossible, to fathom the evolution tures and social contexts, which entails highly
of what is the human from the evolution of specific imaginative devices for organizing the
“technics,” which he defines as the exterior fluid relationships between image and text,
organized realm of inorganic matter (Technics narrative and instruction, fiction and reality.
and Time, 1 17). In Stieglerian terms, both If we see the Picture Book as part of an assem-
the anthropological machine as a conceptual blage of techniques and technologies, including
mechanism and the scientific laboratory as an image making, written language and the print-
actual one, upon which human self-definition ing press, then it becomes possible to place it
rely, would be two technics amongst many in alongside the scientific laboratory, and the
a larger technical consciousness at the “origin” anthropological machine which we outlined
of the human being.13 above, within a Stieglerian framework, as
Technics allows us to see how external a technical means by which social and
realms of scientific experimentation – tools, psychic expressions are inherited through
diagrams, equipment, data, languages, codes, externalizations.
epistemologies – are folded into the internal According to Stiegler’s argument on tertiary
definition of the human. Stiegler posits that memory, technical externalities retain not only
these externalities or artificial technical appar- human experiences but also regimes of “atten-
atus make possible, or in fact are, the retention tion.” The “internalization” of attention is not
of human experience and memory. It follows, something that is lived in a naturalistic sense
for Stiegler, that variations in the evolution of but an intergenerational inheritance that

52
loo & sellbach

arrives from the outside (Taking Care of between humans, animals and the tools of the
Youth 8). In the case of the Picture Book, laboratory?
the modes of attention and imagination it In Claire Schiller’s 1957 translation of
enables require the concentration of adult Uexkü ll’s “A Stroll through the Worlds of
attention on the juvenility of the child, some- Animals and Men” the picture of the grasshop-
thing that can either be actively cultivated or per experiment is accompanied by a lyrical
discouraged.16 description in which the scientific milieu of
Reflecting on this, we can say that the Picture the laboratory becomes overwhelmed by
Book is a distinctive technics in that, as a mode another fantastical reading. The year is 1934,
of tertiary memory, it tends to be doubly and we can imagine Uexküll’s laboratory trans-
forgotten in the world of adults. On the one formed into a grand inter-war cabaret club. In
hand, like other tertiary memory, it retains a closed booth, in front of a majestic radio
experiences which are inherited and not directly microphone, a diva grasshopper is lost in the
lived; but on the other, the experiences retained, revelry of her own performance. In a neighbour-
and the kind of attention it requires, are not ing concert hall, well-comported suitors gather,
taken seriously by the dominant paradigms of their wings glistening multi-coloured, capti-
scientific and philosophical thinking. Filled vated in the acoustic world of female song ema-
with aporias, mythologies, and hybrid objects, nating from a large loudspeaker. Behind them is
the childhood Picture Book is not rational in another singer, caught in an actual glass bubble,
cognition but is constantly expanding with a forlorn that her cries remain unheard.
sense of its horizons (Taking Care of Youth The combination of singular image with lyrical
108). narration is a classic Picture Book technique. The
Understanding, in biology and in other fields use of everyday human objects and tools in an
that proceed from a techno-scientific paradigm, unfamiliar setting is another. And the exacer-
arrives from the construction of a knowable and bated anthropomorphism is a third.
“whole” object or individual. As we have seen, In this strange musical concert, sound and
the laboratory retains experiences that are image have fallen out of sync. The grasshopper
replete with the desire for reaching the complete that sings into a microphone is heard but not
object or individual. The Picture Book, seen by her suitors, the grasshopper that sings
however, is arguably one of the most powerful under a glass bell is unheard and invisible. The
practices since the advent of writing that words and pictures that convey the scene to a
resists whole-object relations.17 In fact, the human audience are also at odds. In the written
Picture Book, in its requisite attentiveness, accompaniment Uexküll provides, the two grass-
exploits the dissonance between celebrating hopper singers are female, while the grasshop-
the incompleteness or the gap between knowl- pers listening at the speaker are male. But as
edge at hand and objects that are yet-to-come; Joseph O’Neil, points out in his 2010 English
and over-determining the ideal of whole object translation, female grasshoppers do not chirp
based on familiar forms and knowledge.18 (88). It seems that in the process of telling, the
For us, this suggests that the Picture Book story of the concert overrides scientific accuracy.
can enable a thinking that feels (for) the type O’Neil’s attempt to correct this error by rever-
of grammar that produces partial images, sing the sex of the grasshoppers is further con-
rather than complete objects. This attentiveness founded by the fact that all the grasshoppers
is corporeal and affectual, for it is only through appear to be illustrated as anatomically male.
the performance and re-performance of the Here we see at once the weakness and the
Picture Book that the illusions of the partial power of the Picture Book as a strategy for
objects it creates become real and concrete thinking about animals in the laboratory. On
instantiations. If the Picture Book is under- the one hand the narrative logic of the scene
stood as a technics that tends towards incom- is at risk of eclipsing the scientist’s commit-
plete imaginings, what new relations emerge ment to empirical observation. On the other

53
invisible worlds

the stories that biology is capable of telling us picturing the technique of nature
can turn out to be even stranger than fairytales.
By entering the world of the scientific exper- Not only does Uexküll use the Picture Book as a
iment through the Picture Book frame we are technic for imagining animal Umwelts in his lab-
invited to imagine the unknowable worlds of oratory, he also believes that nature has pictur-
the grasshoppers through over-determined ing strategies of its own. Uexküll calls these
anthropomorphic frameworks that collapse “techniques of nature,” where animals enter con-
logical sense to perform an alternative logic of trapuntally into a web of co-affectual relations
sensation and affect. This technique de- with each other and with inorganic elements of
centres the human being in the laboratory, their environments. Uexküll’s favourite meta-
allowing other kinds of relations to become phor for expressing this is a vast “symphony”
visible. Here, we no longer see a “complete” of nature, where the perceptual worlds of differ-
picture of the animal Umwelt; instead, the ent animals interact in a way that is absolutely
Picture Book frame assembles, in partially rea- unknowing but perfectly in tune, like two
lized ways, different grasshopper life-worlds, notes harmonizing in a “musical score.”19
each effected in its own way by the presence What is less remarked upon is that Uexküll
of human tools and out of phase with one believes that ecologists can attempt to “write
another. These imaginings take the form of the score of Nature” only because animals are
expressions, which are speculative and incom- already making pictures of their affectual
plete, because one folds into the next. relations with each other (Theory of Meaning
Performed through the Picture Book, we can 186). In order to consider this technique of co-
see that the limits of the Umwelt are not fixed picturing further, we have invented another
but drawn and redrawn in these partial expres- story. It combines two flies described by
sive ways, through the uncanny picturing of Uexküll – the fly in a village street, from “A
different configurations of insect, technology, Stroll through the Worlds of Animals and
human relations. Here, the tools of the labora- Men,” and the fly and the spider in A
tory are also “volatized,” opening up the specu- Theory of Meaning. Our story puts the fly and
lation that small laboratory animals may also in the spider, which Uexküll takes as exemplary
some way be de-centred by their comportment of the technique of nature in A Theory of
to human technologies. Meaning, directly into the Picture Book frame.

54
loo & sellbach

THE SPIDER & THE FLY

55
invisible worlds

A Conversation Arising from the Story of


The Spider & the Fly
The final picture still needs to be made. What to draw?

Uexkü ll says that spiders are good at making pictures of flies. The
threads of a spider web are perfectly measured to fit the flying fly.

But the spider in the story is young and has never met a fly before.
So how does the picture of the fly appear?

The spider is so affected by the missing fly, that its web becomes
“fly-like.” Imagine! The young spider is making a picture of
something it feels but has not yet lived.

What happens next?

Imagine the fly flying down the village street.

Does it see the web?

The web is so fine the fly cannot make it out.


“It is indeed a refined picture of the fly which the spider produces
in its web,” says Uexküll. (158)

But what does the spider’s invisible picture show?

The fly of course!
It is so not (like) the fly even the fly cannot see it.

It shows the limits of the fly’s world.


But it is also a picture of the fly at the limits of its world.

The fly flies into the web.


And gets caught in its own picture?

56
loo & sellbach

To begin with, the scientist Uexküll tries to with the spider’s web at the limits of its
reconstruct the fly’s Umwelt with the aid of a Umwelt. It is with the aid of the Picture Book
camera, an enlarger and a screen combined that we as humans can imagine the life-world
with careful laboratory observations about the of the spider through the externality of its
fly’s compound eye and the markers of web, and the life-world of the fly through the
significance in its environment. Unfortunately, spider via what its web is not.
these classic scientific devices result in a The Picture Book does not show us the com-
picture that is “disturbing” to the human eye, plete picture of the spider or the fly but provides
so he decides to retouch the scene with us with what Brian Massumi would call “sem-
“watercolours” (A Stroll 21). With the help of blances”21 (as opposed to re-semblances) of the
Stiegler we can say that, by explicitly making fly and spider. That is, the Picture Book
the Picture Book his technic, Uexküll allows makes a virtual fly and a virtual spider appear.
for an intensification of tertiary memories of Furthermore, the Picture Book frame swerves
childhood aesthetic experience, which differ the scopic regime away from the thinking
from the technics of the lab. human eye to the respective life-worlds of the
Entering the world of the Picture Book more spider and the fly, to give us a feeling for a
fully does two things. First, a different type of spider that “knows” from birth a fly it has not
comportment or attention towards nature is yet met; and for a fly that meets its counterpoint
called for: a performance of the Picture Book, in the web only at its death.
rather than distanced scientific observation of On the occasion of entering the Picture Book,
the animals. Second, inside the book, humans the spider, the web and the fly assume abstract
are placed out of the frame (even their tools forms, which have real effects on one another.
are gone and they are no longer making the “pic- Likewise, the grasshoppers, the chirps coming
tures”). Instead, there are two others – the through the loudspeaker, the radio microphone
spider and the fly – co-picturing. and the glass bell can all be viewed as abstracted
Like the tool in hand for humans, the web may pictures of animals and technologies that never-
be considered an exteriorization of the spider – a theless enter into actual relations.
technique that co-evolves with the spider.20 For These abstract forms are “something” not
Stiegler, human tools and techniques are reposi- fully determinate; they are not sensed in the con-
tories of experiences that have not been lived. In ventional sense, they are “non-sensed” percep-
the Picture Book story the young spider remem- tion, almost like a passing thought that is felt
bers the fly that it has not yet met in its web. So rather than understood.
the web is co-evolving with the fly as well as the In the Picture Book frame, it seems that all enti-
spider. Affected by the fly, the spider intuits a ties, whether human, animal or technical, reach
picture of the fly at the limits of its world. And over to another to build relations in partial but
the fly then inherits the picture in the spider’s concrete ways, as if they were, to use Alfred
web, an image that it does not see, but North Whitehead’s concept, “prehending”
“suffers” (Theory of Meaning 182). (rather than apprehending) each other. Prehen-
sion is not completely a human category; it con-
cerns relations of casual connectedness between
semblances of animality in the actual entities not determined by human tele-
ology. It is a feeling that emerges when connecting
picture book perceptions and cognitions are transported from
Picture this. In the Picture Book there is a one actual occasion to another (18).22 The feeling
spider, whose web is an extension of its body. of transport imposes limits on or enables potential
The web is a negative picture of the fly, a coun- in the apparatus of actualization (Massumi,
terpoint to the fly’s bodily capacities, dimen- “Autonomy of Affect” 43). As Whitehead says,
sions and movements. The fly cannot “see” this movement of prehension from one occasion
itself in the web, but it enters into a relation to another is life itself: “a living person [or any

57
invisible worlds

organic life] is some definite type of prehension as foreign subjectivities of animals and their
transmitted from occasion to occasion of its exist- mutual prehendings are imagined away from
ence” (18). As Uexküll’s animal, human and human technologies; closed by the inherited ter-
environmental entities differentially prehend tiary memory in the technicity of the tools of the
each other, we can imagine the stretching and lab tending towards the whole or complete
deforming of the limits of their life-worlds, entity; and reopened through the performative
towards overlapping and involuting Umwelts. dimension of the Picture Book with its infantile
So, the Picture Book is a Whiteheadean technics of language and image. In the anthro-
occasion whereby individual entities, whether pological machine, if it continues in some
human, animal or technical, partially concretize form, the drawn lines themselves are partial,
as their life-worlds enmesh. The becoming of perforated.25
individuals is never stable but “metastable,”23 The Picture Book dramatizes the grey area
as resultant forms of the individual ontologically between the seemingly closed functional cycles of
contain the tendency to reconfigure themselves, animals. It pictorially abstracts the interstices of
based on a constantly shifting conjunction of closed functional cycles, where the edges of the
actual and affectual internal forces struck by Umwelt are given expression as semblances.
external forces as organized technics. In the Because we can only think-feel these grey areas
case of our argument, the technicity of the through the performance of the Picture Book
Picture Book, in performing the foreign subjec- frame, the animal cannot completely be the
tivities of other animals as abstractions, enables excluded by-product of human self-
a form of thought and feeling where animality definition because it is always already caught up
and humanity take on partially concrete shapes in co-effectual relations of co-picturing. This
that are not fixed. Each time the Picture Book abstraction of the foreign subjectivities of
is performed, the individuation of entities also animals in the Picture Book laboratory is actual
shifts.24 Herein lies the great difference in com- experience – a performance of life – a “lived
portment between the distanced scientific obser- abstraction.”26
ver of animals, and the ecologist imaginatively A paradox appears between Stiegler’s idea of
engaging with Picture Books! As Uexküll tertiary memory in human technics as inherited
writes, from the conventional viewpoint of and therefore “not lived,” and the Picture
science, “there is no mammal in itself as intuit- Book technic which invites the expression of
able object, only as a notional abstraction, as a tertiary retentions as “lived” abstractions in
concept which we use as a means of analysis the unique forms of pictures, words, and
but never encounter in life. With the tick, this imaginings that are phenomenologically per-
is completely different” (Theory of Meaning formed.27 By “living” the “not lived” tertiary
179). The tick encounters the mammal as a memories through abstracting exteriorizations,
living abstraction, and we the readers of the which to Stiegler are ontological to the process
Picture Book, Uexküll goes on to imply, may of individuation of the human, we suggest that
also use our concepts in ways that think-feel the Picture Book enables a radically different
(Massumi, Semblance and Event 39) the comportment to animal and technical others
strange partial concretization of our human and the human-self. It increases a feeling for
being that the tick’s intuition entails. and between one another that reaches over to
The shifting lines drawn between animal and configure new ecological relations in partially
human mediated by the technicity of the Picture concrete ways.
Book may seem to re-engage the anthropological
machine as a “mobile mechanism” (as Agamben the picture book as a technic for
has pointed out) in ways that are not so different
ecological thinking
from the scientific laboratory. But as the process
of individuation is only always partial, Umwelts Uexkü ll’s contribution to ecology is tradition-
fibrillate between being open and closed: open ally read in two contrasting ways. On the one

58
loo & sellbach

hand, Uexküll the “humble naturalist” refuses of a real orchestra demonstrate a contrapun-
to bracket off for the sake of experimental con- tal behaviour already in their structure.
venience the ways in which other animals also (189)
sense, feel and interpret the world. On the It seems that we have made the symphony
other, Uexküll the “biologist-shaman” conjures Uexkü ll hears in his laboratory into a “cacoph-
forth the radically different worlds of these ony,” an assemblage of makeshift instruments
animals to reveal a web of co-effectual relations played by a Picture Book clown. But we must
between animals and their environments that not forget that the grasshoppers are also
he likens to the harmonies of a musical “making music.” For Uexkü ll, the grasshop-
score. As we have shown, these possibilities per’s chirps are techniques of nature, exterior-
co-exist in post-humanist readings of Uexkü ll, izations of its capacity to form contrapuntal
which emphasize the de-centring effects of relations between its organs of perception and
animal Umwelten, and in conventional scienti- its environment.28 To conduct this experiment,
fic readings where the animal Umwelt is a Uexkü ll uses recording and amplification tech-
closed functional loop. nology and this causes the grasshopper’s song
What might the Picture Book do to an to be at once enhanced and displaced via the
ecology that oscillates between the careful obser- loudspeaker. If we imagine the concert that is
vations of a naturalist and a vast “symphony of performed by the grasshopper in the labora-
nature”? At the end of A Theory of Meaning, tory, then there may no longer be a preor-
Uexkü ll reflects on the analogy he has drawn dained melody but a discordant harmony
between the co-effecting relations that the biol- interrupted by a strange silence. By “living”
ogist observes between organisms and environ- through the Picture Book’s performance, the
ments, and the “natural score” played by the “not lived” tertiary memories retained in the
instruments of an orchestra. laboratory in its abstractions, we may speculate
a memorization and further extension of the
If we take a glance at an orchestra, we see in
Umwelt of small animals through technical
each individual rostrum in musical notation
the voice leading, for the instrument to means.29
which it belongs, while the whole score is
on the conductor’s rostrum. But we also see
the instruments themselves and wonder if epilogue
these are possibly adapted to each other not
just in their respective tonalities, but in One way of imagining the coming community
their entire structure, i.e., if they form a that Agamben anticipates in The Open would
unit not just musically but also technically. be that in the end human beings learn to
Since most instruments in the orchestra are accept their (base) animality, and animals
capable of producing music by themselves, come to be accepted for their human-like
this question cannot be answered in the affir- qualities (their intelligence, emotions, self-
mative as simply as that. awareness). But if through the Picture Book
Whoever has listened to the production
we attend to the invertebrates that are with
of musical clowns, who work with instru-
us in the laboratory and at the table, then it
ments that otherwise serve for making
noise, such as hair combs, cow bells, and no longer seems to be a matter of transposing
other such things, will have been convinced existing qualities between human and animal
that one can very well play a cacophony, but but of creating an aesthetic medium in
not a symphony, with such an orchestra. which new and unforeseen sensibilities might
Upon closer examination, the instruments emerge.

59
invisible worlds

THE STARLING & THE FLY

The following story is told by the scientist Uexkü ll.

A researcher who is a friend […] raised a young starling in a room,


and the bird had no opportunity ever to see a fly, much less to catch
one. Then he observed that the bird suddenly started after an
unseen object, snapped it up in midair, brought it back to its perch
and began to hack away at it with its beak, as all the starlings do
with the flies they catch, and then swallowed the unseen thing.
(Foray 120–21)

For Uexküll it is obvious – the starling is so overcome by a feeding


mood that it magically conjures up a fly, even though there is no fly
in the room.

How remarkable, a room without flies!

And more too, the starling eats an invisible fly! Magical and invis-
ible, the fly must be in a Picture Book.

Of course, the Picture Book belongs to Uexküll, but wasn’t it the


starling that first made up the fly?

Imagine the Picture Book fly.

What becomes of the invisible fly as it is being swallowed? What


picture might it make?

notes Humans with A Theory of Meaning, trans. Joseph


D. O’Neil (Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2010);
The figures reproduced in this paper are from Jakob copyright 2010 by the Regents of the University of
von Uexküll, A Foray into the Worlds of Animals and Minnesota. Originally published in Streifzüge durch

60
loo & sellbach

die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen; copyright The always present danger, of course, is that
1934 Verlag von Julius Springer. this may entail a reification of other Umwel-
ten. The question How can we in our world
1 Agamben observes that the animal figures
see how animals see their world? may easily
representing humanity in the miniature correspond
turn into the more self-interested inquiry
allegorically to different parts of the human body:
How can we see how animals see their world
bones, nerves, veins, flesh and skin (The Open 2).
in such a way that it will change and enrich the
2 Both the laboratory and the table are key way in which we see ours? (235)
contested sites for animal studies. As Peter
Singer and others have argued, when we bring 8 Biosemioticians would call these “markers of sig-
other animals to our table as food we disregard nificance” signs.
the terrible suffering incurred through factory 9 It is important to remember, however, that
farming and its environmental impacts. In this Uexküll understands these markers to be indi-
context, it is a provocation to consider cations of what matters to the animal, rather
whether, by bringing insects to the table, we than the human being. It is precisely because the
are in fact including them in some way in our animal decodes its environment according to a
ethical consideration. series of markers (or signs in biosemiotics) that
3 While we are cognizant that the animal worlds he likens the animal to a “machine operator” but
of Jakob von Uexküll are thoroughly opened up not a “machine,” which reacts to stimuli from the
by the field of contemporary biosemiotics, in this outside world without selectively interpreting
paper we are concerned with the technical them (“A Stroll” 7–9).
ontology rather than a semiotic one of scientific 10 Agamben argues in The Open that Uexküll may
experimentation when it meets the children’s end up re-articulating the anthropological machine
Picture Book, and how this may provide a re- in a new way that lends itself to two disturbing alterna-
reading of Uexküll’s animal perceptual worlds, tives. Either the hierarchical division between human
and the relationship of humans with these and animal is re-established – Heidegger, for example,
worlds. We would like to thank our anonymous uses Uexküll too in order to contrast the instinctive
reviewer, who reminds us that the kind of captivation he believes is proper to all animal behav-
aesthetic “knowing” which the Picture Book iour, with a human openness to the world – or the
exhibits can be read through semiotics as a rec- divide between human and animal collapses entirely,
ognition on Uexküll’s part of the importance of in a way that aligns with Friedrich Ratzel’s politically
iconic and indexical signs for both animals and frightening notion of Lebensraum, whereby “all
humans. people are intimately linked to their vital space as
4 The figure of the child and the picture storybook their essential dimension” (42).
are also devices that Agamben uses to imagine new 11 If we attend more carefully to the Picture Book
relations opening between human and animal that frame then both the previous readings of Uexküll
do not serve the project of human self-definition. we have outlined are affected: Uexküll the post-
But what Agamben does not consider is that humanist uses a very human, child-like technique
Uexküll’s laboratory also draws on the imaginative to evoke non-human worlds. But for Uexküll the
realm of childhood, through its Picture Book ecologist who researches the limits of the animal,
frame. his task is imagined or performed in ways that
5 For example, Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation and suggest that its precise outcome is open.
more recently Marc Bekoff’s The Emotional Lives of 12 “The Grasshopper Cabaret” was performed as a
Animals. children’s book reading as part of the symposium
6 For example, Cary Wolfe’s Zoontologies. presentation “Ecological Thinking through the
Picture Book of Jakob von Uexküll’s Laboratory” in
7 The Open 45. Here, Uexküll aligns with the artis- Rethinking Behaviour and Conservation: The
tic avant-garde of his day, and with recent post- History, and Philosophy and Future of Ethology II,
humanist work on non-human agencies. But as Centre for Social Inclusion, Macquarie University,
Geoffrey Winthrop-Young warns in his “After- Sydney, 26–28 November 2011; and as a short per-
word” to A Foray and Theory of Meaning: formance at the Architecture-Writing: Experimental

61
invisible worlds

Approaches symposium, Critical Studies in Architec- “transitional spaces”; spaces that “form the basis
ture, KTH Stockholm, Stockholm, 24–25 May 2012. of all systems of care and nurturance: a transitional
space is first and foremost a system of caring” (ibid.
13 Stiegler, in Technics and Time, 1, in an effort to 15). So we might also say here that the Picture Book
postulate the origins of the human, explains the augurs human attention that proceeds from a per-
originary “default” in the constitution of the formativity that involves transitional objects and
human through the myth of Epimetheus who spaces whereby humans are struck by the infancy
“forgot” to confer upon humans any special gifts, of inherited technics.
and that the current power of the human being
and its ability to know, think and exteriorize is 17 It is important to note that the Picture Book
the “fire” stolen from the gods by Prometheus. relies on the concerted use of the mode of “pictur-
ing” that significantly pre-dates writing.
14 Although, as Nathan van Camp has pointed out,
by recognizing the tertiary memories of human 18 Building on this, we can see that what is
life deposited in externalities, the human is de- expressed in the Picture Book, in its content, struc-
centred in ways that may disrupt the anthropologi- ture and framing, is organized by a unique gramma-
cal machine, we have also argued that tertiary mem- tization related to infancy. Here, infancy is not a
ories deposited in the tools of the laboratory tend nascent version of the rules of language that
back towards a picture of the centrality of the “matures” into adulthood, or a pre-linguistic ineffa-
human which covers over this destabilizing effect. ble state. Rather, according to Agamben, “infancy”
marks the threshold between wordlessness and
15 Of all the animals, insects appear to have the speech: “where language stops is not where the
highest technicity, so one way to adapt the conven- unsayable occurs, but the other where the
tional reading of Stiegler to human animal relations is matter of words begins” (Idea of Prose 27). At
to say that these small creatures also operate, like this threshold, which we are arguing can be
the tools of the laboratory, as tertiary memories found in children’s Picture Books, humans are
of the human being. Along these lines, Jussi Parikka’s struck and overwhelmed by language. This affect
recent book Insect Media investigates how insect stems from the fact that the Real of language – its
modes of organization – swarms, webs and distrib- grammar, words, and image-objects – are there
uted agencies – provide new ways of understanding at their limits of sense and existence.
media technology and its relationship to biology,
which do not rest on the notion of individual 19 Theory of Meaning 188–89. Deleuze, Parikka
agents or a deterministic account of technology. and Agamben have developed different readings
By reading insects via media formations, his book of Uexküll’s musical metaphors.
opens up a new and rich account of the ways in 20 Making a similar point, in more general terms
which digital culture helps to form and de-centre about animal Umwelt, Elizabeth Grosz has argued
human beings. This is a productive approach to that the bubble world is the projection of an
pursue. However, we would like to avoid a animal’s bodily capacities (183).
reading that reduces insects to externalizations of
the human, because this potentially misses the 21 Massumi defines semblance as “the
otherness of insect life that Uexküll emphasizes, experience of a virtual reality,” the manner in
and the difficult question of their place in our which the virtual actually appears (Semblance and
ethical thought and consideration. Event 15–16).

16 For Stiegler, the capturing and formation of 22 As Whitehead says, prehensions “define the
attention in the young by technical and media indus- real individual facts of relatedness, a kind of trans-
tries threatens processes of what he calls human portable perception or cognition extracted from
“maturity,” and global social and cultural develop- other actual occasions, or prehensions are trans-
ment (see Stiegler, Taking Care of Youth 7–8). By ported by perception or cognition” (18).
contrast, we are suggesting that the Picture Book 23 This “process of ‘individuation’” as metastable
is part of the formation of nascent attention as comes from Gilbert Simondon (300).
imagination. For Stiegler, the partial or “transitional
objects” opened through childhood play are the first 24 As Grosz says, the limit space of the Umwelt is
forms of tertiary retention that can only appear in always in construction: “Space is built up, sense by

62
loo & sellbach

sense, perceptual organs upon organs, forming the Agamben, Giorgio. The Open: Man and Animal.
soap bubble, its limits, its contents” (180). Trans. Kevin Attell. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2004.
Print.
25 We appropriate here a description of the line
drawn by the anthropological machine which is Bekoff, Marc. The Emotional Lives of Animals.
also metonymic of the stretched boundaries of Novato, CA: New World Library, 2007. Print.
Uexküll’s bubble Umwelts:
Brown, Eric C. Insect Poetics. Minnesota: U of
Minnesota P, 2006. Print.
What I have really drawn there is an oval line,
for this white chalk mark is not a line, it is a Buchanan, Brett. Onto-Ethologies: The Animal
plane figure, in Euclid’s-sense a surface, and Environments of Uexküll, Heidegger, Merleau-Ponty
the only line that is there is the line which and Deleuze. New York: State U of New York P,
forms the limit between the black surface 2008. Print.
and the white surface. This discontinuity can
only be produced upon that blackboard by Grosz, Elizabeth. Becoming Undone: Darwinian
the reaction between two continuous sur- Reflections on Life, Politics and Art. Durham, NC
faces into which it is separated, the white and London: Duke UP, 2011. Print.
surface and the black surface. (Massumi, Sem- Massumi, Brian. “The Autonomy of Affect.” Parables
blance and Event 89) for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation. Durham,
NC and London: Duke UP, 2002. 23–45. Print.
26 Massumi, Semblance and Event 15. Massumi
derives “lived abstraction” from a Deleuzian Massumi, Brian. Semblance and Event: Activist
concept, where abstraction is nothing more or Philosophy and the Occurrent Arts. Cambridge, MA:
less than the performative/lived dimension of that MIT P, 2011. Print.
abstraction. The act of abstraction configures the
Parikka, Jussi. Insect Media: An Archaeology of
potential in that abstraction, and that potential is
Animals and Technology. Minneapolis: U of
relayed from one abstraction to another.
Minnesota P, 2010. Print.
27 The theoretical argumentation on the impli-
Simondon, Gilbert. “The Genesis of the Individual.”
cations of this paradox for Stiegler’s contention
Incorporations, Zone 6. Ed. Jonathan Crary and
with Simondon that the process of individuation is
Sanford Kwinter. New York: Zone, 1992. 297–319.
ontologically technical as the process of psychic indi-
Print.
viduation is already a collective one (Stiegler,
“Theatre of Individuation”), warrants another paper. Singer, Peter. Animal Liberation. London: Pimlico,
1995. Print.
28 The chirping sounds – for Deleuze, the
exterior territory – of the animal are related to Stiegler, Bernard. Taking Care of Youth and the
its morphology; for example, the evolution of the Generation. Trans. Stephen Barker. Stanford:
development of sound-making techniques is Stanford UP, 2010. Print.
related to the distance of mates.
Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of
29 To perform the foreign subjectivity of insects and Epimetheus. Trans. Richard Beardsworth and
other small animals through the Picture Book frame George Collins. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998. Print.
opens up the radical possibility of insect exterioriza-
Stiegler, Bernard. “The Theater of Individuation:
tions – not just insects as human exteriorizations
Phase-Shift and Resolution in Simondon and
but insects with their own tools, insects reconfiguring
Heidegger.” Trans. Kristina Lebedeva. Parrhesia 7
human tools and insects displaced by tools and tech-
(2009): 46–57. Print.
niques (human and animal) that surround them.
Uexküll, Jakob von. A Foray into the Worlds of
Animals and Humans and A Theory of Meaning.
bibliography Trans. Joseph D. O’Neil. Minnesota: U of
Minnesota P, 2010. Print.
Agamben, Giorgio. Idea of Prose. Trans. Michael
Sullivan and Sam Whitsitt. New York: State U of Uexküll, Jakob von. “A Stroll through the Worlds
New York P, 1995. Print. of Animals and Men: A Picture Book of Invisible

63
invisible worlds

Worlds.” Instinctive Behavior: The Development of a


Modern Concept. Trans. Claire H. Schiller.
New York: International Universities P, 1957. 5–
80. Print.
Uexküll, Jakob von, and G. Kriszat. Streifzüge durch
die Umwelten von Tieren und Menschen: Ein
Bilderbuch unsichtbarer Welten. Sammlung:
Verständliche Wissenschaft, Berlin, 1934.
Van Camp, Nathan. “Animality, Humanity and
Technicity.” Transformations: Journal of Media and
Culture 17 (2009). Web. <http://www.
transformationsjournal.org/journal/issue_17/
article_06.shtml>.
Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality: An
Essay in Cosmology. 1929. New York: Free, 1978.
Print.
Wolfe, Cary, ed. Zoontologies: The Question of the
Animal. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2003. Print.

Stephen Loo
School of Architecture & Design
University of Tasmania
Locked Bag 1323
Launceston 7250
Tasmania
Australia
E-mail: stephen.loo@utas.edu.au

Undine Sellbach
School of Philosophy and School of
Architecture & Design
University of Tasmania
Locked Bag 1323
Launceston 7250
Tasmania
Australia
E-mail: undine.sellbach@utas.edu.au
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

One thing about which fish know exactly


nothing is water, since they have no anti-
environment which would enable them to
perceive the element they live in.
McLuhan and Fiore, War and Peace in
the Global Village 175

I dog days

I n his 1970 collaboration with Wilfred


Watson, From Cliché to Archetype, Marshall
McLuhan characterizes the domestic dog as a
“primordial” technology which functioned as
an early extension of human sensory life, with
important survival benefits for human
society.1 Like the printing press and automobile
that came later, the authors argue, Canis lupus tom tyler
familiaris made possible for Homo sapiens a
new mode of living.2 McLuhan and Watson
suggest that earlier technologies remain
evident in modern times in the “verbal resi-
NEW TRICKS
dues” of well-known phrases and idioms: “His
bark is worse than his bite,” “Every dog has powers of attention by sheer pervasiveness.”4
its day,” “A bone of contention,” et al.3 Any Like the pencil or the telephone, the most revo-
technology will imprint such clichés on the lutionary innovations soon become ubiquitous
language, expressions that originally derived and commonplace. The social and psychological
from unique and innovative practices but environments which result, comprising the
which soon became hackneyed and stereotyped technological and perceptual media within
through their endless repetition. Today they which we exist, are overlooked, unacknow-
are employed through habit and convention, ledged and effectively invisible. “[O]ur percep-
their origins largely unnoticed. McLuhan and tions themselves are clichés patterned by the
Watson are keen not to confine this notion of many hidden environmental structures of
the cliché just to language, however, which, culture.”5
they argue, is but one technology amongst Throughout his work, McLuhan sought to
many. All technologies serve initially to focus on the far-reaching effects of technologies,
enlarge a culture’s scope of action and patterns and to highlight the invisible environments they
of association and awareness, only to produce created. In his writings and presentations he
environments which subsequently “numb our attempted always, by means of provocative

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010065-18 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783442

65
new tricks

prompts, probes and jokes, to draw to our atten- I’d love to stop and play ball with you, teach you
tion the perceptual and conceptual clichés we so a few tricks maybe, but my friend Daisy has just
often fail to notice. In this essay I would like to been dog-napped!”7 And so it begins. Players
explore the ways in which an unassuming are able to enter Jake’s world and to engage in
and seemingly frivolous digital game requires all manner of stereotypically canine behaviour,
its players to confront a longstanding and designed to appeal to the younger gamer:
deep-seated cliché, a distinct strain of anthropo- digging up bones, marking territory, farting,
normativity that quietly but persistently dis- defecating, swimming and then, inevitably,
courages perceptual identification with other shaking dry. As Jake himself says, “No school,
forms of animal life. I wish to look too at a par- no chores, no clothes! It’s great being a dog!”
ticular, innovative way in which this game Canine life is not just a matter of tug-of-war
engages its participants in the process of play, and chasing chickens, however. Players must
evoking modes of affinity and involvement keep Jake healthy and well fed, lest he become
that are unbound by questions of species iden- tired and listless, whilst avoiding at all times
tity. On this unlikely platform the technological the dog catcher and his Doberman. And, of
and the animal meet, and play together, to edu- course, there’s that matter of rescuing Daisy.
cative, enlightening effect. It is often said – it is Jake must track her down, searching first
a cliché, in fact – that you can’t teach an old dog through the quiet corners of rural Clarksville,
new tricks, and so I would like to suggest that then on to Lake Minniwahwah ski resort, and
we can best understand the game, and learn arriving, finally, at the perilous streets of
from its creative coupling of techne and animal- Boom City. Ultimately, he must face the
ity, by boning up instead on a pair of established elusive Miss Peaches, purveyor of the suspi-
but largely forgotten conceptual ploys which ciously sourced Crunchy Cat Food.8
remain, nonetheless, profitably challenging. In The narrative of Dog’s Life, though engaging
revisiting, and, perhaps, teaching to a new audi- enough, is far less interesting than a central,
ence these old tricks, it is my intention to novel element of its gameplay. When the game
pursue thereby the essay’s twin themes of alter- begins, it is a bright, sunny day, and Jake
ity and identity. Like many others, our digital finds himself at the edge of a flowering
game depicts varied modes of interaction meadow, buzzing with insects and fluttering
between members of different species, but it with butterflies (Fig. 1). As he enters, bounding
also extends to its players an invitation both to after a young human companion, players are
appreciate a certain, striking form of animal invited to switch to “Smellovision” and truly
otherness and to engage, at the same time, in step into Jake’s world. Smellovision has two
interspecific identification. key features. Firstly, play shifts from a third-
person perspective which follows Jake from
some distance, to a subjective, first-person per-
II a shaggy dog story spective that permits gamers to “see the world
Dog’s Life for the PlayStation 2, created by through Jake’s eyes.”9 The environment is
Frontier Developments and published by Sony depicted as if through a wide-angle, fisheye
Computer Entertainment Europe in 2003, is a lens, and colours become noticeably muted,
digital game aimed principally at a children’s simulating a canine point of view. Secondly,
market.6 Players control Jake, a young, care- players are now able to “see smells,” which are
free, mixed-breed mutt, who, clearly without represented as brightly coloured clouds of
owner or primary care-giver, gets along by scent, free-floating or billowing around the
means of his winning ways, and by scavenging humans, parrots, pigeons, fox, and other
from trashcans and pilfering unattended food. animals whom Jake encounters, and who leave
At the beginning of the game, roguish Jake odorous wisps in their wake. Footprints glow
immediately finds himself called to adventure: and can be tracked, and the locations of
“Hi, I’m Jake. Welcome to my world! Normally buried bones are revealed by shafts of celestial

66
tyler

Fig. 1. Third-person perspective. Players see Jake as he interacts with his environment.

Fig. 2. Smellovision. Players can “see the world through Jake’s eyes,” including clouds of scent, glowing
footprints, and the location of buried bones.

light (Fig. 2). The game becomes, in effect, an players are invited to step into the digital soap
interactive manifestation of Jakob von bubble that represents Jake’s Umwelt (self-
Uexkü ll’s much-discussed monograph A Foray world). Just as Uexkü ll describes, the familiar
into the Worlds of Animals and Humans, as meadow is transformed, and a new world

67
new tricks

comes into being.10 I would like, initially, to Smellovision, which provides the player with a
focus on this playful simulation, and to reduced range of colours, in dull shades.12
examine the variety of ways in which Smello- As a full simulation of the alterity of canine
vision seeks to reproduce a canine phenomenal vision, however, Dog’s Life ultimately falls
world.11 short. The game does not attempt to demon-
strate dogs’ limited depth perception, for
instance. Precisely because their eyes are set
III how does your dog smell? further to the sides, affording a wider field of
Smellovision effectively captures something of view, dogs have a smaller area of overlap in
the greater field of view of canine vision. The the middle, and thus less three-dimensional
visual field varies from breed to breed, and vision, which amounts to no more than 60°,
indeed from individual to individual, depending and often much less, compared to a full 140°
on the placement of the eyes in the skull. Typi- in humans. Dogs’ visual acuity is similarly
cally, a dog’s eyes deviate approximately 20° poor. In a canine eye, multiple photoreceptors
lateral to the midline, with each eye providing are attached to a single ganglion, the nerve cell
a monocular field of view between 135° and that transmits signals from eye to brain, increas-
150°, combining to create a total field of view ing overall sensitivity to light but decreasing the
of approximately 240° or 250°, allowing for degree of detail that can be conveyed. Canine
overlap. A human’s eyes, by contrast, both visual acuity has been estimated to be equivalent
oriented straight ahead, provide a smaller field to 20/75 human vision, which is to say that Jake
of view of approximately 180°. The fisheye would need to be just twenty feet away in order
lens of Dog’s Life is thus a means of communi- to distinguish the detail of an object that one of
cating Jake’s greater visual field within the his human companions could see at seventy-five
constraints of a conventional television screen. feet. Perhaps unsurprisingly, this aspect of
Similarly, the significantly lower visual perspec- canine vision is not explored in Dog’s Life.
tive that dogs normally experience is replicated Nor, indeed, is dogs’ relatively poor accommo-
by the game. In shifting to Smellovision, players dation, the ability to focus on objects situated
find themselves just inches from the virtual at different distances, which renders as a blur
ground, confronted in the first instance by car anything closer than thirty centimetres or so
wheels, trash cans and the legs of humans: you from their faces. A human adult, by contrast,
must actively look up in order to see the faces can on average accommodate objects as close
that now tower above you. Further, although it as ten centimetres away, and a young child can
was believed for a long time that dogs lacked usually see clearly at just five centimetres
all colour vision, this is not, in fact, the case. away. (This is most likely why dogs often
The retina of a human eye ordinarily has three seem not to notice objects that are right in
kinds of photoreceptor cells that detect colour, front of them.) Finally, nothing is made
called cones, each of which is especially sensitive during the course of the game of dogs’ impress-
to a different wavelength of light: red, green and ive crepuscular vision. A range of physiological
blue. In combination, these three types of cone factors provide dogs with sight which is ideally
make possible trichromatic colour vision, the suited to the dim light to be found at dusk
detection of a vast range of colours. A dog’s and dawn. Whilst the central 25° of a human
eye, on the other hand, contains just two kinds retina is devoted principally to cones, providing
of cone, which respond most to violet and that glorious trichromatic colour vision, in dogs
yellow-green wavelengths. As dichromats, dogs this area is largely given over to rods, photo-
thus detect a much smaller spectrum of receptors sensitive to low levels of light. In
colours than most humans, and cannot dis- addition, a canine eye contains a layer of cells
tinguish, for instance, red from green, or blue at the back of the retina, called the tapetum
from violet. This colour blindness is carefully lucidum, which reflects back light that has
simulated by the subdued palette of already passed through the retina, effectively

68
tyler

providing the photoreceptors with a second Life, trails of bright yellow shoe prints, includ-
opportunity to capture each photon of ing those left by a masked robber you must hunt
light. Further, tapetal riboflavin may even down, clearly indicate direction by their distinct
absorb light in the shorter blue wavelengths, heel-and-sole shapes. Finally, Dog’s Life cap-
shifting it to a longer wavelength more easily tures not just the passive reception but also
detected by rods, and thereby enhancing the the active pursuit of scents. Dogs’ enthusiastic,
contrast between dark objects in the environ- noisy sniffing, significantly more effective than
ment and the brighter night sky behind.13 The the paltry human equivalent, is a complex
ability to see in the dark, when swapping to process that simultaneously draws new air into
Smellovision, might perhaps have opened up the nose whilst expelling the old, and which in
interesting gameplay opportunities, but Jake’s turn causes a slight wind current that facilitates
adventures take place entirely during daylight further inhalation. Jake can’t help but stumble
hours.14 into a mass of floating odours when in Smello-
Dogs, famously, have highly sensitive noses, vision, but, by pressing the appropriate control-
and Dog’s Life works hard to explore the experi- ler button, players can also have him sniff at
ence of living in a richly odoriferous world. In will, which causes him to turn towards the
the first instance, with the change over to Smel- nearest scent.15
lovision, aspects of the environment that are Effective as these many simulations of canine
entirely invisible to humans become apparent. olfaction are, however, they do not begin to
Though the hues of the visible world are now capture the astonishing extent to which a dog
muted and dull, representations of scents and is sensitive to the slightest of smells, and
smells are brightly, vividly coloured: objects as capable of discriminating between near identical
diverse as misplaced axes and wind-snatched odours. Each nostril of a dog’s nose draws in a
sheet music emit swirls of vibrant scent; distinct sample of odour, providing differential
varied puffs of inviting odour float around information, and research indicates that the
every part of the environment, to be “collected” canine sense of smell works with the exhalation
by the player; and humans and other creatures as well as with the inhalation of air. The inside
are surrounded always by a warm cloud of of a human nose contains approximately six
their own scent, a conspicuous current of oils million receptor sites, each with hairs capable
and dead skin cells, evaporating sweat and bac- of catching chemicals of a particular molecular
teria. Dogs’ ability to locate hidden objects is shape. A canine nose, by contrast, contains
similarly integrated into the gameplay, with per- two or three hundred million such receptor
iodic digging necessary to unearth coveted sites, and sensitivity increases exponentially.
bones, whose location is disclosed by spectacu- Dogs, as a result, are receptive to minute quan-
lar, unmissable pillars of light. Urine marking, tities of odour, the equivalent, for instance, of
the placement of canine calling cards, is ordina- being able to detect a single teaspoon of sugar
rily undertaken to indicate a dog’s identity, diluted in a million gallons of water. In one
interest in mating, etc. Jake can be made to series of tests, dogs were able to identify a
pee at any time, but in the special “pee glass slide by the scent from a solitary human
marking” mini-game, initiated after collecting fingerprint with which it had been marked
yellow scents, you must capture areas by three weeks earlier. Other research indicates
peeing over your opponent’s marks, in a that dogs can even smell the chemicals produced
contest for territory. The capacity to track by cancerous cells: from tissue or urine samples,
other creatures, long employed to human advan- or the patients’ exhalations, dogs have accu-
tage, depends on a dog’s being able to detect rately detected skin, breast, bladder and lung
when individual footprints were laid down: the cancers, in one case when melanoma was
odour of any given print will be fractionally present in only a fraction of cells and had been
stronger than its immediate predecessor, missed by pathological examination. Although
thereby revealing direction of travel. In Dog’s Smellovision makes present odours that are

69
new tricks

entirely imperceptible to humans, represented although new technologies may at first be start-
as distinct, unambiguous clouds, it does not lingly innovative and invigorating, they soon
explore the extent to which dogs can detect become, through repetition and ubiquity,
the faintest traces of scent. Similarly, the game numbingly environmental. These encompass-
does not address dogs’ celebrated powers of dis- ing, involving environments, he argues, are
crimination. Presented with T-shirts that had not passive wrappings but active processes
been worn by identical twins, dogs were able that structure our actions and awareness
to ascertain the garments’ owners, provided without our noticing them. The ground rules,
the shirts were placed in close proximity the configurations, the pervasive patterns of
during the test, thereby allowing them to be these active environments elude easy percep-
sniffed simultaneously. Although different tion; they are, for the most part, invisible.18
species of creature within Dog’s Life give off We are oblivious to our surroundings,
distinctive odours – synaesthetic consistency immersed, like fish in water, in a medium
within Smellovision ensures that humans are whose significance remains unknown and unac-
always purple, other dogs are orange or blue, knowledged. In order to discern the environ-
parrots are green, etc. – individuals of the ments in which we habitually exist, to become
same species or breed are identical in terms of aware of the enveloping “climates of thought
their scent.16 and feeling,”19 we need to be exposed,
Dog’s Life, then, is an engaging and very McLuhan suggests, to what he calls anti-
effective simulation of canine perception, but environments.
it is certainly not comprehensive.17 Gameplay Anti-environments, according to McLuhan,
necessarily comes first, and the demands of can promote awareness and pattern recog-
the medium, genre and market prevent a more nition.20 They can provide new strategies of
detailed or exhaustive re-creation of contempor- attention that train perception onto the unno-
ary research into dogs’ visual and olfactory ticed environment. McLuhan was fond of Hans
capacities. Shortcomings in terms of verisimili- Christian Andersen’s tale of the emperor’s
tude, however, by no means detract from new clothes as a means of illustrating this
Dog’s Life’s unrivalled capacity to highlight process by which environmental norms are dis-
and bring to the fore the alterity of this particu- rupted and thereby brought to our attention.
lar, non-human mode of awareness and appre- The “well-adjusted” ministers and officials,
hension. Despite its inevitable limitations, immersed in court culture, saw the emperor as
Smellovision embodies, as we will see, the beautifully appointed, he suggests, whilst it
digital game’s anti-environmental potential. took an “antisocial” brat, unaccustomed to
this environment, to alert everyone to what
was going on.21 It is, McLuhan argues, most
IV dogged determination often the ill-adjusted individual, the outsider,
In welcoming us to his world, Jake expressed even the criminal or enemy of society, who is
the desire to teach us some tricks. Caught up best placed to draw attention to the environ-
in his rescue mission to save Daisy, this activity ment. Beyond the delinquent child,22 it is to
seems to be postponed indefinitely, but in fact, the artist, for instance, that McLuhan most
over the course of the game, Jake is a very effec- often turns for anti-environmental observations.
tive instructor. In this section and the next, I Pop Art, he argues, takes banal objects from our
would like to explore two such tricks, two con- daily lives and reminds us that we are sur-
ceptual ploys, neither entirely new but both rounded by a world of images and artefacts
largely forgotten today, which Jake ably demon- that are intended not to train perception and
strates if we take up his challenge and play awareness but to produce effects for the
Dog’s Life. The first of these is one of McLu- economy.23 Such art can elicit a “sting of per-
han’s lesser-known probes. As we saw, ception” or “shock of recognition.”24 Similarly,
McLuhan argues that, like verbal clichés, McLuhan suggests, whilst the professional will

70
tyler

tend to classify and specialize, adopting the features of the old environment, before it
ground rules provided by the mass response of becomes, inevitably, environmental itself.37
his colleagues, the amateur, who works alone Anti-environmental means of perception
and can afford to lose, seeks instead a total, criti- “must constantly be renewed in order to be effi-
cal, anti-environmental awareness of the indi- cacious,”38 as the soup cans that are appro-
vidual and of society.25 The sleuth or gumshoe priated for the gallery swiftly become
of popular fiction, such as C. Auguste Dupin postcards and tea-towels, before being rede-
and Sherlock Holmes, Mike Hammer and ployed, newly formatted, to sell soup once
Philip Marlowe, turns a self-conscious attentive- more.39 Environment and anti-environment
ness on the big city, “detecting the social alternate their roles “with all the dash and
environment by probing and transgression.”26 vigour of Tweedledum and Tweedledee,”40 per-
And, like the wisecracks and witticisms of forming an endless, cyclic, “technological
Chandler’s private investigator, McLuhan fugue.”41 Even the most popular arts,
argues that jokes more generally can be our McLuhan suggests, can serve to increase aware-
most appealing anti-environmental tool, as the ness, at least until they become entirely environ-
funny man, an outsider with a grievance, mental.42 Games, in fact, by transforming the
probes into the cultural matrix that plagues customary, working environment into model,
him, providing as he does so a guide to changing paradigm form, can provide that anti-environ-
perceptions.27 mentalism indispensable to any culture
In addition to these inquisitive, unconven- seeking to avoid “complete somnambulism.”43
tional individuals, amongst whom McLuhan In the first instance, Dog’s Life engages its
himself might well be included, all manner of players in a typically environmental form of
processes and products, many of them more play. The third-person perspective is the
mainstream, can function anti-environmentally. default point of view: it is the outlook from
McLuhan recounts how Ovid’s multiple plots which players start when the game is first
and subplots, or succinct Japanese haiku, or suc- launched, and to which they always return
cessive literary movements from realism to the after having saved their progress, or following
romantics to the modernists, can produce anti- the occasional cinematic cut scenes. The
environmental effects.28 Schools, in turn, have virtual camera follows Jake from above, captur-
traditionally been designed as anti-environ- ing his actions and immediate environment as
ments, “to develop perception and judgement players guide him through Clarksville, the ski
of the printed word,”29 though they are increas- resort, and beyond. This third-person perspec-
ingly ineffectual, McLuhan argues, in today’s tive seems dispassionate and impartial, observ-
electronically mediated milieu, which turns the ing the characters and events from an
whole world into a “classroom without abstracted, disembodied vantage point at some
walls.”30 Liberal studies have long been con- remove from Jake’s interactions on the
sidered a means of providing orientation and ground. But the game’s third-person point of
perception, but when the arts and sciences view is by no means detached or neutral, as
themselves become environmental, new controls the shift to first-person Smellovision retrospec-
must be found.31 Diverse events and artefacts – tively demonstrates. The explicitly subjective
from participatory happenings32 to the hard viewpoint of Smellovision is, as we saw, that of
drugs of Burroughs’ anti-Utopian novels,33 a dog. This canine perspective serves to
from the jolt of bad news34 to the very Earth remind us, however, that the ostensibly objec-
itself when experienced from a post-sputnik per- tive third-person outlook is nothing of the
spective35 – can produce anti-environmental sort. When playing in third person, the lack of
effects in the right environmental context.36 a fisheye lens means that we have a smaller
Even a new technology can itself enjoy a “brief field of view, the broader palette of on-screen
reign” as an anti-environment, highlighting colours allows us to experience the world as
through sheer novelty and innovation some does a trichromat, and, of course, the absence

71
new tricks

of colour-coded clouds, glowing footprints, and human perceptual norms. Smellovision’s per-
spectacular bone-markers ensures that scents ceptible odours and fisheye lens draw attention
and smells are entirely unrepresented. Jake to the water in which we fish swim.45
does not even take a swift, involuntary sniff as
he passes through those areas that we discover,
V working like a dog
if we swap back to Smellovision, in fact
contain rich deposits of appealing odours. Smel- By means of these alternate perspectives, then,
lovision shows us, in short, that the default, see- the anti-environment that is Dog’s Life invites
mingly impartial third-person perspective is, in us to appreciate something of the overlooked
fact, a human perspective.44 alterity of canine perception. Jake is the
Alignment of the detached, dispassionate game’s outsider, its alter, and, despite the
observer with an implicitly human mode of necessary limitations of execution and inevitable
apprehension effectively normalizes the latter. concessions to playability, Smellovision under-
This unacknowledged perceptual anthroponor- scores the fact that dogs and humans experience
mativity functions as a McLuhanesque environ- the world in radically different ways. The
ment, an encompassing milieu that we fail to promise was to demonstrate two tricks,
notice, but which nonetheless actively struc- however, and the second, though it starts expli-
tures our actions and awareness. Whilst citly from this position of alterity, speaks at the
playing in third person, we do not recognize, same time to the identity that Dog’s Life
or remember, that this apparently natural, manages to cultivate between player and
normal point of view is but one amongst protagonist.
many. Indeed, when we switch to Smellovision, Building on Erving Goffman’s dramaturgical
the zoom from an unremarked third-person per- analyses of social interaction,46 in 1963 Eugene
spective, which is human, to an entertainingly Weinstein and Paul Deutschberger published
odd first-person perspective, which is canine, their essay “Some Dimensions of Altercast-
quietly normalizes the former by drawing atten- ing.”47 They open with the observation that
tion only to the latter. In shifting to Smello- “Among the most venerable notions in social
vision, however, we are obliged at the same psychology is the assumption that human
time to concede that the so-called third-person behavior is goal directed.”48 Consciously or
perspective with which we started is just as otherwise, an individual will pursue these
partial and particular as first. We are reminded, goals during the course of interactions with
and compelled to confront the fact, that there is others, both by presenting themselves in a par-
no single, standard mode of apprehension: fields ticular manner, and also by projecting roles or
of view and orientation are simply different, tri- identities onto interlocutors. Such altercasting
chromacy is as contingent as dichromacy, and is a technique, Weinstein and Deutschberger
the presence or absence of detectable odours is argue, of interpersonal control: if an alter can
a function of one’s olfactory apparatus. be manipulated or cast into a particular role,
Neither species-perception need be preferred the responses one desires of them are more
to the other, or conceived as any kind of likely to be elicited. Modes of altercasting can
paradigm. Smellovision serves, in effect, as an be explicit or they can guide the alter by more
anti-environment to pervasive assumptions subtle gestures of approval and disapproval,
regarding the pre-eminence of human modes and the literature distinguishes between
of perception. By first modelling this anthropo- manded and tact altercasts. A manded altercast
normative outlook, and then providing a canine- specifies more or less directly the role that is to
centric alternative, Dog’s Life, even whilst nor- be adopted by the alter: they will be told unam-
malizing the human perspective, works to biguously that they are a “good friend,”
undermine it. Jake, the roguish outsider, wel- perhaps, and thus expected to act accordingly.49
comes us to his world, and in so doing provides A tact altercast, on the other hand, solicits a role
a counterpoint, a counterenvironment, to from the alter by adopting a complementary

72
tyler

identity. One might ostentatiously demonstrate dream.” He encourages Jake with gestures and
the qualities of close friendship in the hope of exclamations of approval – “Sit, Jake … good
evoking these in another; or, alternatively, one dog” – and presents him with a bone when he
might adopt the role of needy neighbour in performs correctly. The interaction is effec-
order that the alter step up to the complemen- tively a tact altercast, with Grandpa adopting
tary role of good Samaritan.50 Of course, the the role of pedagogue whilst Jake takes up that
alter may well resist these attempts to of dutiful student. In each of these cases, and
manoeuvre him or her into a particular role, throughout the game, Jake is frequently alter-
whether it be submissive and helpful, dominant cast as the obedient and helpful pooch, man’s
and decisive, or something else again. They may best friend perhaps, a role or identity he is
endeavour to engage in an altercast of their own, obliged to take on if the interaction is to
in fact, which is entirely at odds with the goals persist and gameplay continue.52
and objectives of their colleague. The successful Weinstein and Deutschberger’s account of
continuance of the social interaction depends, altercasting addresses a key aspect of interperso-
then, on individuals maintaining an ongoing, nal power relations. In his own discussions of
negotiated working consensus, “a tacit agree- such relations, Foucault emphasised always
ment as to the roles the several participants that, properly considered, the alter is never
will play out in the encounter.”51 This merely a malleable, brute object:
working consensus does not entail the roles
being equal, of course, but only that at some a power relationship can only be articulated
level all parties are complicit in the interchange on the basis […] that “the other” (the one
over whom power is exercised) be thoroughly
that results.
recognized and maintained to the very end as
Weinstein and Deutschberger do not
a person who acts; and that […] a whole field
examine the question of interspecific altercast- of responses, reactions, results, and possible
ing, but it is by no means precluded by their inventions may open up.53
account. The narrative that plays out during
the course of Dog’s Life illustrates a good Interpersonal control requires precisely that the
many instances of altercasting, and although it alter be a person, capable of independent action,
is humans projecting the identities, insistently and the altercast comprises, in Foucauldian
pursuing their goal-directed behaviours, it is terms, a “complicated interplay” of interactions:
the dog Jake who is altercast. Throughout the
game, Jake is repeatedly cast as an itinerant, In this game freedom may well appear as the
condition for the exercise of power (at the
Lassie-like assistant, enjoined to complete a
same time its precondition, since freedom
range of tasks and errands for polite but consist-
must exist for power to be exerted, and also
ently inept humans. Submitting to entreaties or its permanent support, since without the
the promise of a juicy bone, Jake provides possibility of recalcitrance, power would be
varied but characteristically canine support. In equivalent to a physical determination).54
Clarksville’s rustic environs, a drill sergeant
turned crop farmer has difficulty protecting Those occasions on which a party is subject to
his seeds: “Every time I try to repair the scare- bare, physical determination evince the appli-
crow I get attacked by birds. Well, this means cation of what Foucault designates not
war.” He addresses Jake as “Private Dog” in a “power” but “capacity,” a means of direct
direct manded altercast that effectively enlists control that “stems from aptitudes directly
him to scare off the crows by barking. Early in inherent in the body or relayed by external
the game, Jake meets a benign, flatulent instruments” and which is “exerted over
“Grandpa,” Daisy’s doting primary care-giver, things and gives the ability to modify, use,
who teaches him to sit and to lie down: “Say, consume, or destroy them.”55 Although he is
Jakey, let’s see what tricks you can do besides engaged by a succession of demanding
waking up a poor old man out of a lovely humans, Jake, the ownerless, uninhibited

73
new tricks

canid, is never constrained or compelled by such Grandpa endeavour to shape their subject’s
capacities, and, within the power relations of conduct, where, as Foucault points out, both
which he is a part, a field of reactions and meanings of that equivocal term should res-
responses remain open to him throughout, onate: a variety of behaviours are open to
including the option to curtail the interactions. Jake, even whilst he is led in a particular
As a canine alter, he is free, we might say, to direction.57
the extent that he is at liberty to subject It is not just the human characters in Dog’s
himself to the roles and controls of the Life who can altercast others, however. Grand-
human-initiated altercasts, or not. pa’s instruction provides just the first of a
Grandpa’s interaction with Jake exemplifies series of moves that Jake picks up during the
one of the most common forms of interspecific course of his adventure. In every area of the
altercast, that of training. Jake learns how to game he meets a local dog, each of a different
sit and to lie down, manoeuvres that will be breed, many of whom teach him new tricks.
useful to him later in the game. Techniques of These increasingly impressive (and unlikely)
the most brutal and violent kinds are undeni- manoeuvres can be used to coax and cajole
ably employed in the course of much animal treats from nearby humans. Adopting the role
training,56 but Grandpa is a benevolent of adorable performer, by sitting and begging
teacher, using in his own programme only posi- or executing a hand stand, Jake can, without a
tive, linguistic reinforcement and feedback, and word being spoken, tact altercast a passing
the final reward of a bone. There is more to the human into the position of provider. Some
training session than simply teaching Jake these prove immune to his charms, especially the
basic tricks, however. Grandpa’s objective, the jaded citizens of Boom City, and will send him
goal he is ultimately pursuing, is to induce on his way (“Get a job!”). But, provided that
Jake into seeking out his beloved Daisy. he is not too dirty, many will provide Jake
Encouraging though he is, Grandpa cannot with a choice morsel (“Ha ha, way to go there,
help making unfavourable comparisons: “Nice little guy”). Interspecific altercasting can work
moves, Jake, but nobody moves like my both ways. The fact that Jake is able to
Daisy. Say, Jake, I don’t suppose you could assume the part of caster as well as that of
track her down? I don’t know what I’d do alter demonstrates the intricate and fluid
without her.” The training session is a means nature of the interplay of power relations here.
to an end, that of communicating Grandpa’s To suppose that it is the caster who “holds”
desire and making clear the role he would like the power would be to fall into precisely the
Jake to adopt: canine assistant and rescuer of trap of reification, from which Foucault consist-
the doggy damsel in distress. Interspecific alter- ently recoiled.58 The power relation between
casting, like that between humans, engenders a Jake and his benefactors is asymmetric in
working consensus to which the parties more- varied ways. Although Jake successfully
or-less freely subscribe, but such a consensus, pursues his goals by directing the behaviour of
as Foucault argues, is the precondition for the others and casting them as donors, his position
exercise of power. The issue of interpersonal is, at the same time, subservient. Not unlike
control, of attempting to realize one’s goals the bones that Jake must collect by completing
for, or by means of, the other, lies at the heart chores in order to progress through the game,
of the animal training process, and even in the “treats” he manages to wheedle from
those regimes where physical determination is those around him are in fact one source of the
lacking, and where direct violence plays no food he needs to maintain his health: they are
part, the non-human individual who is subject necessary nutrition as much as indulgent
to the altercast will find the range of his or her titbits. Just as Jake spends a good deal of his
actions channelled and directed. In seeking “to time in the game helping others, so too he in
structure the possible field of action of turn finds himself dependent on the kindness
others,” animal training altercasters like of strangers.

74
tyler

With these interspecific altercasts, Jake take upon yourself – digging for bones,
demonstrates that Weinstein and Deutschber- marking territory, tracking scent trails,
ger’s approach need not be confined to the begging for treats, et al. – comprise, in part,
human realm, and that, in its application to the game’s altercast of you in the role of a
the give and take of interpersonal power dog. Beyond these somewhat formulaic activi-
relations, there is no reason to assume, vener- ties, though, your casting as a canid is facilitated
ably or otherwise, that it is only human behav- by two technological innovations within the
iour that is goal directed. Further, there is an game. The first is Smellovision. The option to
additional form of more-than-human altercast- press the triangular button on the game control-
ing that Dog’s Life begs us to consider. When- ler and move to Smellovision is always available,
ever a digital game player takes up a and you must choose when, or even if, you will
controller, or settles to their keyboard and allow yourself to be so induced, in order not
mouse, or turns on their mobile device, in simply to control the avatar of Jake but to be
acquiescing to the solicitation that they press confined to his perspective. Alexander Galloway
“Start,” or select a difficulty level, or undertake has argued that cinematic convention most often
their assigned mission, they can be considered uses the subjective shot to effect a sense of alien-
altercast by the game. Irrespective of the genre ation, detachment or unease.59 The first-person
or mode of play, gamers must yield to appropri- perspective breaks the spell of the authoritative
ate forms of behaviour if they wish to continue. and seemingly objective traditional camera shot,
The player’s actions within the game are never inhibiting audience identification: it is used
entirely determined, as if controlled directly most often to represent the vision of criminals,
by the capacities and external instruments of monsters, aliens, and “otherwise inhuman”
the technology, of course. Rather, a whole characters.60 Digital games that make use of
field of responses, reactions, and possible inven- the first-person perspective, on the other hand,
tions opens up, providing precisely the inter- are able to merge player and protagonist: the
action and participation to which digital games fact that you direct the virtual “camera” your-
lend themselves as a medium. The trajectory self ensures, in this case, a significant sense of
of a game, narrative or otherwise, may ulti- identification.61 With Smellovision, Dog’s Life
mately be as linear as any novel or film, con- utilizes this mode of subjective identification
straining players to work their way through a but adds to it a unique, other-than-human vari-
succession of predetermined areas or levels. ation. Not only is the weapon of the traditional
But, at the same time, players have a degree of first person shooter replaced by Jake’s nose
freedom to choose how they wish to negotiate (Fig. 2), but as we saw above, when you shift
the game’s challenges. The successful continu- from third-person perspective to Smellovision,
ance of the interaction depends on game and the wide-angle view and muted tones, together
player maintaining an ongoing, negotiated with the fact that you can “see smells,”
working consensus, a tacit agreement as to the imperfectly but effectively simulates canine
roles that the participants will play out in the perception. By means of this inhuman and
encounter. yet entirely enjoyable identification, players
In Dog’s Life, then, you are altercast as a dog. are altercast as harassed but homely Jake
The promotion and packaging take the form of the dog.
an explicit, verbal cast – “It’s great being a In addition to the distinctive visual dimen-
dog!” – and the gameplay itself is no less sion of the game, the PlayStation 2 also pro-
manded. Grandpa’s training session does not vides tactile feedback through the DualShock
simply teach Jake the first of his tricks but analogue controller. As Jake leaps over fences
begins to instruct you, the player, as to how and gates, or simply bounds around the
you must adopt this particular identity within game’s locations for the sheer pleasure of the
the confines of the game. The varied forms of experience, the controller provides an indica-
stereotypically canine behaviour that you must tive jolt when he launches and lands. Similarly,

75
new tricks

whenever he strays too close to a precipitous extension of human capacities and thereby
edge, on cliffs, ski slopes or in warehouses, made possible a whole new way of life. There
the controller will vibrate, cautioning the is, in McLuhan’s conception of all media and
player to step back. The warning feedback on technologies as “extensions of man,” an anthro-
these high ledges effectively constitutes an pocentric bias which pulls against the elements
instance of Weinstein and Deutschberger’s of his work that, with equal force, emphasize
“gestures of approval and disapproval,”62 the determining effects of the new environments
which serve as signposts for the route that the generated by those technologies. In this
game would prefer you to take. Players are free instance, however, his equivocally humanistic
to persist as they wish, but those who do so and probes hold the potential to highlight the
fall will feel the heavy impact of their landing, means by which the technological innovations
and Jake will become noticeably less healthy as of Dog’s Life complicate and interrogate habit-
a result, complaining about his sore head and ual understandings of animal experience. The
moving more slowly. Like the first-person per- medium, McLuhan insisted, is not just the
spective, the practice of providing indicative message, but also the massage. Technologies,
vibrations is by no means unique to Dog’s he argued, produce environments that “work
Life, and is widely supported by PlayStation us over,” that “leave no part of us untouched,
games. But, again, the technology here takes unaffected, unaltered,” a characterization that
a unique turn. Just as the shift to Smellovision lends itself to the tactile, immersive, participa-
alerts us, with hindsight, to visual and olfac- tive nature of digital games.63 Games, on McLu-
tory aspects of the third-person perspective han’s account, function as “live paradigms” of a
we had been employing, changes in our tactile society, encapsulating the cultural environment
experience now also prompt reassessment. in model form. By simulating one situation by
Players receive haptic feedback at appropriate means of another, and inviting participation in
moments whether they are employing a first- that re-creation, games make available a mode
or third-person perspective, but there is con- of revealing, anti-environmental perception.64
spicuously more vibration when playing the Participation in the particular technology at
game in subjective Smellovision than in dispas- which we have been looking, in the Smellovision
sionate third-person mode. Having experi- game mechanic that lies at the heart of Dog’s
enced both, the game world literally feels Life, can facilitate a greater awareness of and
more physical when playing in Smellovision: critical reflection on traditional, clichéd ways
it is more immediate, more “real,” when you of thinking about both animality and subjectiv-
are a dog. By this means of tactile feedback, ity, human or otherwise.
Dog’s Life privileges a player’s subjective In addressing the three senses of sight, smell
experience of the game as a dog over their and touch, Smellovision provides players with
time merely controlling Jake from a detached an inventive and surprisingly rigorous re-
but anthroponormative, third-person perspec- creation of key aspects of canine perception as
tive. In addition to the visual and olfactory they are currently understood, even if the simu-
dimensions of Smellovision, then, this lation as a whole remains necessarily simplified.
complementary form of technologically The limitations of this model are, I would
induced haptic altercasting helps affirm your suggest, less important than its educative
identity as a dog during your interaction with effect. During the course of his adventure,
the game. young Jake learns a number of impressive
moves from his fellows, and, in turn, this new
dog teaches us a pair of old tricks. On the one
hand, as a ludic altercast, the game requires
VI old tricks and new
players to recognize dogs as subjects. The
McLuhan suggests that the dog was, originally, a player of Dog’s Life may not get to experience
primordial technology that functioned as an life as a dog (as we have seen, the game’s

76
tyler

simulated Umwelt and conventional narrative point of view is but one immersed, subjective
are inevitably schematic and stereotyped), but perspective amongst many.65 Thus, by means
they are reminded that it is like something to of these two edifying tricks, altercasting and
be a dog. The key issue is not, pace McLuhan, anti-environments, this digital game’s simu-
that dogs should be conceived as technologies, lation of canine perception through its Smello-
augmenting human aptitudes and abilities and vision technology complicates our
thereby generating new modes of social exist- understanding both of animal and of human
ence. Rather, this digital technology helps us subjects.
to appreciate more fully the subjective dimen- In terms of its narrative and characterization,
sion inherent to the interpersonal relations Dog’s Life may be conventional and even
that pertain between the human and canine par- clichéd. Jake is both loveable rascal and faithful
ticipants in any such social order, and, indeed, hound, and over the course of the game he runs
the asymmetric nature of those subjective inter- the whole gamut of traditional canine conduct.
personal relations. The altercasts depicted and Jake is not just cast but typecast as everyone’s
enacted by the game work to educate players, best friend, and a universal everydog.66 In
directing (but never forcing) us to acknowledge terms of the Smellovision technology which
that such interspecific interactions, including sets this game apart from the pack, however,
training processes of all kinds, involve two Dog’s Life mounts a genuine challenge to cus-
more-or-less free subjects with their own percep- tomary thinking about the canine. Even whilst
tions and objectives who, at the same time, are insisting on the significant alterity of canine
engaged in an uneven, irregular, shifting experience, the game obliges players to identify
power relationship. with the subjective dog’s life of the title. Anti-
On the other hand, as a disruptive anti- environment and altercast here work together
environment, the game requires players to to emphasize that recognition of the otherness
reconsider the traditional, presumed primacy of different species does not preclude modes of
of the human subject. The player of Dog’s identification. In troubling a tacit, uniform
Life does not experience events from a single, anthroponormativity, Smellovision entails a
human perspective (as we have seen, our per- shift from an unquestioned, dogmatic identity
ception of the game’s settings and characters to a disruptive, reflective alterity. At the same
is not consistent or continuous), but switches time, in casting players as an extraordinary,
repeatedly between a human and a canine view- inhuman other, Smellovision involves the volun-
point. Contrary to first appearances, the game tary adoption of a projected, alien alter as an
does not set out to provide an impersonal, ongoing, relational identity. The anti-environ-
impartial, third-person perspective from mental altercast that is Dog’s Life, which is
which locations and interactions can be freely taken up by its players, invites and chal-
observed as if with dispassionate detachment. lenges us to rethink both
Rather, the engaged, subjective, first-person human and canine subjectivity.
perspective that belongs to Jake, the unruly Until, that is, the novelty of this
outsider, undercuts the pre-eminence of what innovative, inventive digital
now turns out to have been an implicitly game is exhausted, and new
anthropocentric outlook. In shifting from a tricks must be sought once more.
god’s-eye to a dog’s-eye view, the anti-environ-
ment established and enacted by the game
works to educate players, challenging privi-
leged, normalized notions of human percep- notes
tion, which is to say the perceptual Thanks to Ewan Kirkland for introducing me to
anthroponormativity that would conflate an Dog’s Life; to the Animals and Society Institute
ostensibly objective with an implicitly human and the fellows of the inaugural Human–Animal
outlook, and reminding us that a human Studies Fellowship Program at North Carolina

77
new tricks

State University for an unparalleled research Nietz, Geist, and Jacobs; for accessible accounts
environment; to Erica Fudge, Ron Broglio, Geor- of canine vision, see Budiansky 106–16; Horowitz
gina Montgomery, and Claire Molloy for providing 121–37; Bradshaw 224–30.
opportunities to present my ideas to a wider audi-
13 Miller and Murphy 1623–24, 1633.
ence; and to John Ensminger and Susan McHugh for
their helpful comments on earlier drafts. 14 Additionally, although neither is replicated in
Dog’s Life, dogs are probably more adept at
1 McLuhan and Watson 56–57.
motion detection, and can more easily discern
2 McLuhan and Watson provide no details; on the fast-changing images; see Miller and Murphy 1624.
contested question of the early collaboration, and The latter means that dogs have a higher threshold
even co-evolution, of human and canine, see for flicker fusion, the point at which fast changing
Wang and Tedford esp. chapter 8; Paxton; Brad- images blend into a constant image, which suggests
shaw 3–67 (chapters 1–2). that a digital game such as Dog’s Life would appear
to canine eyes as a series of distinct images, rather
3 McLuhan and Watson 56–57; the idioms they
than as a seamless animation. Interestingly, some
quote are taken from Smith 196 (5.vi). Most of
research has found that playing digital games actu-
the phrases listed are in fact of very recent
ally improves visual processing (in humans); see
origin, many deriving from blood sports that bear
Green and Bavelier and the literature cited therein.
little relation to the hunting practices in which pre-
historic humans and dogs might have engaged. 15 On canine olfaction, see Ensminger; Budiansky
118–23; Horowitz 67–88; Bradshaw 230–49. On
4 McLuhan and Watson 57.
urine marking, see Scott and Fuller 69–70; in fact,
5 Ibid. 54. “eliminative behaviour” does not seem to function
as territorial marking at all, as is popularly believed
6 Dog’s Life was released on 29 October 2003, to and represented in Dog’s Life.
mixed reviews. It was nominated for two
BAFTAs (“Best Adventure Game” and “Best Chil- 16 In fact, several species give off a green scent,
dren’s Game”). The game should not be confused including parrots, sheep and (sometimes) pigeons.
with the Macintosh “interactive storybook” pub- Not all creatures are visibly odorous in Smellovi-
lished by Sanctuary Woods in 1994, titled It’s a sion, presumably in order to simplify gameplay.
Dog’s Life (aka Digby the Dog and Digby’s Adventures). On cancer detection, see Horowitz 81–82; Pickel
et al.
7 Dog’s Life booklet, p. 1.
17 Dog’s Life does not tackle the alterity of canine
8 Incredible as Jake’s feats and adventures are, I hearing, for instance the ability to detect ultrasonic
would caution against suggesting that either he or frequencies; see Budiansky 116–18; Horowitz
they are “anthropomorphic”; see Tyler, “If 92–98.
Horses.”
18 McLuhan and Fiore, Medium is the Massage 68.
9 Dog’s Life game case, reverse.
19 McLuhan and Watson 57.
10 Uexküll 43.
20 McLuhan, “Art as Anti-environment” 57.
11 Other attempts to represent smells within
McLuhan also uses the terms counterenvironment
digital games have included the “cat senses” of
(e.g., McLuhan and Watson 77; McLuhan and
the critically panned Catwoman (Electronic Arts,
Parker 2; McLuhan, “Emperor’s New Clothes”
2004) and the derivative “ScentView” of WolfQuest
342), countersitutation (e.g., McLuhan and Fiore,
(Eduweb, 2007). Various devices have been devel-
Medium is the Massage 68; McLuhan, “Emperor’s
oped to integrate actual smells into digital games,
New Clothes” 342), and countergradient (e.g.,
for instance Ruetz Scnet Systems’ Sniffman,
McLuhan and Parker 2).
BIOPAC’s Scent Delivery System, and Scent
Sciences’ forthcoming ScentScape Gaming Suite. 21 McLuhan and Fiore, Medium is the Massage 88;
See Steffen; Bingham; Scent Sciences. McLuhan, “Emperor’s Old Clothes” 4.
12 An excellent overview of canine vision is pro- 22 McLuhan, “Address at Vision 65” 226; McLuhan
vided by Miller and Murphy; on colour vision, see and Fiore, Medium is the Massage 93.

78
tyler

23 McLuhan, “Relation of Environment to Anti- colorful designs of the Warhol labels.” See Camp-
environment” 112. See also idem, “Emperor’s bell Soup Company.
New Clothes” 342, 344–45 on Picasso.
40 McLuhan, “Emperor’s New Clothes” 344.
24 McLuhan and Watson 59.
41 Idem, “Art as Anti-environment” 57.
25 McLuhan and Fiore, Medium is the Massage
42 McLuhan and Parker 2.
92–93; McLuhan, “Relation of Environment to
Anti-environment” 112. 43 McLuhan and Fiore, War and Peace 168–69; see
also McLuhan, Understanding Media 234–45
26 McLuhan, “Emperor’s Old Clothes” 5; idem,
(chapter 24).
“Address at Vision 65” 226; idem, “Relation of
Environment to Anti-environment” 114; idem, 44 In her essay “Situated Knowledges,” Donna
“Emperor’s New Clothes” 354–56. Haraway discusses the problem of objectivity,
“the god-trick of seeing everything from
27 McLuhan and Fiore, Medium is the Massage 92;
nowhere” (189), and the particularity and embodi-
McLuhan and Watson 131–33; McLuhan, Letters
ment of all vision. One prompt to her own account
315.
of situated knowledges was imagining how the
28 McLuhan, Letters 316; idem, “Relation of world looks to her dogs, which is to say “without
Environment to Anti-environment” 113–14. a fovea and very few retinal cells for colour
vision, but with a huge neural processing and
29 McLuhan, “Relation of Environment to Anti-
sensory area for smells” (190).
environment” 111–12.
45 On representations of the ambiguous, mixed-
30 Idem, “Classroom without Walls” 1–3.
breed mutt as a means of social critique, see
31 Idem, “Relation of Environment to Anti- McHugh 127–70. On the ways in which another
environment” 111. species’ Umwelt can prompt reassessment of
one’s own, which he relates to the Russian Form-
32 McLuhan and Watson 198–99. alist notion of ostranenie (defamiliarization), see
33 McLuhan, Letters 312. Winthrop-Young 230–35.

34 Idem, “Emperor’s Old Clothes” 4–5; idem, 46 Goffman.


“Address at Vision 65” 226. 47 Weinstein and Deutschberger.
35 Idem, “Emperor’s Old Clothes” 10. 48 Ibid. 454.
36 In a letter to Jonathan Miller dated 8 January 49 Ibid. 456.
1965, McLuhan pushes his anti-environmental
probe still further, applying it to dreams, cosmetics, 50 For a number of common role-pairs, see Prat-
perfume, whiskers, speech, clothing, the market kanis 216–22. The terms manded and tact come
and prices, and more; see McLuhan, Letters 315. from Skinner 35–51 (chapter 3) and 81–146
For an excellent overview and discussion of anti- (chapter 5).
environments, see Rae. 51 Weinstein and Deutschberger 456.
37 McLuhan, Letters 315; idem, “Art as Anti- 52 This is not the only role that Jake plays within
environment” 57. the game, however. On several occasions he
becomes, instead, a mischievous mutt, sometimes
38 Idem, “Relation of Environment to Anti-
at the urging of others (for instance, the children
environment” 119.
who egg the butcher in Clarkesville Centre), and
39 In 2004, Campbell’s released a limited edition sometimes on his own initiative (as when a Dober-
tomato soup with “Warhol-inspired labels.” Shop- man under his control solicits a bone from a terri-
pers who purchased the special four-pack could fied shopkeeper by growling).
also “take advantage of an offer for a limited
53 Foucault, “Subject and Power” 220.
edition Campbell’s Andy Warhol magnet set, fea-
turing a collection of four die-cut magnets in the 54 Ibid. 221.

79
new tricks

55 Ibid. 217. 12.1 (2006): 120–28. Web. 30 Mar. 2012. <http://


www.cyberchimp.co.uk/research/manifesto.htm>.
56 On methods of training captive animals, see
Mellen and Ellis. Bingham, Matthew. “Computer Scientists Add Smell
to Games.” The Sunday Times 26 Apr. 2009. Web. 29
57 On the term “conduct” (conduire), see Fou-
July 2011. <http://technology.timesonline.co.uk/tol/
cault, “Subject and Power” 220–21. Cary Wolfe
news/tech_and_web/article6162217.ece>.
has criticized Vicki Hearne precisely for her
failure to reconcile the symmetry of relation that Bradshaw, John. In Defence of Dogs. London: Lane,
she supposes to pertain between trainer and 2011. Print.
animal, and the radical asymmetry expressed in Budiansky, Stephen. The Truth about Dogs: An Inquiry
her characterization of those animals’ rights in into the Ancestry, Social Conventions, Mental Habits
terms of property ownership; Wolfe 44–54. In and Moral Fiber of Canis familiaris. London:
similar vein, Carol J. Adams has taken Donna Phoenix, 2002. Print.
Haraway to task for her defence of circus trainers,
particularly her euphemistic description of per- Campbell Soup Company. “Campbell’s Celebrates
forming animals as “the animals they work with,” Andy Warhol with Limited Edition Tomato Soup
which overlooks the radically uneven nature of Cans.” PR Newswire 14 Apr. 2004. Web. 30
such a working consensus; see Adams. For Mar. 2012. <http://www.prnewswire.com/news-
further discussion of animal training as an instance releases/campbells-celebrates-andy-warhol-with-li
of Foucauldian power relationship, see Palmer. mited-edition-tomato-soup-cans-giant-eagle-super
markets-to-unveil-special-labels-and-warhol-muse
58 See, for instance, Foucault, “Subject and um-offer-72471872.html>.
Power” 219, or idem, Will to Knowledge 93. On
Foucault’s nominalism regarding power, see Ensminger, John J. Police and Military Dogs: Criminal
Spivak 26–37. Detection, Forensic Evidence, and Judicial
Admissibility. Boca Raton, FL: CRC, 2011. Print.
59 Galloway.
Foucault, Michel. “The Subject and Power.” Trans.
60 Ibid. 50. Leslie Sawyer. Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism
61 See Morris 89–90. and Hermeneutics. Ed. Hubert L. Dreyfus and Paul
Rabinow. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1982. 208–26.
62 Weinstein and Deutschberger 456. Print.
63 McLuhan and Fiore, Medium is the Massage 26. Foucault, Michel. The Will to Knowledge: The History
64 McLuhan and Fiore, War and Peace 168–69; I of Sexuality, Volume 1. Trans. Robert Hurley.
have addressed the particular ways in which London: Penguin, 1998. Print.
digital games can be considered participative else- Galloway, Alexander R. “Origins of the First
where; see Tyler, “Procrustean Probe,” especially Person Shooter.” Gaming: Essays on Algorithmic
the section “Retrieving Participation.” Culture. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2006.
65 For illuminating discussions of literary, science fic- 39–69. Print.
tional representations of animal otherness, see Vint. Goffman, Erving. The Presentation of Self in Everyday
66 It is perhaps instructive to imagine an alterna- Life. Garden City: Doubleday, 1959. Print.
tive Dog’s Life that was not motivated by the Green, C.S., and D. Bavelier. “Action-Video-Game
imperative of heteronormative coupling, but Experience Alters the Spatial Resolution of Vision.”
instead invited players to follow canine standards Psychological Science 18.1 (2007): 88–94. Print.
of sociality and sexuality.
Haraway, Donna J. “Situated Knowledges: The
Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege
of Partial Perspective.” Simians, Cyborgs, and
bibliography Women: The Reinvention of Nature. New York:
Routledge, 1991. 183–201. Print.
Adams, Carol J. “An Animal Manifesto: Gender,
Identity, and Vegan-Feminism in the Twenty-First Horowitz, Alexandra. Inside of a Dog: What Dogs
Century.” Animal Beings. Spec. issue of Parallax See, Smell and Know. London: Simon, 2009. Print.

80
tyler

McHugh, Susan. Dog. London: Reaktion, 2004. Miller, Paul E., and Christopher J. Murphy. “Vision
Print. in Dogs.” Journal of the American Veterinary
Medical Association 207.12 (1995): 1623–34. Print.
McLuhan, Marshall. “Address at Vision 65.”
Essential McLuhan. Ed. Eric McLuhan and Frank Morris, Sue. “First-Person Shooters – A Game
Zingrone. New York: Basic, 1995. 219–32. Print. Apparatus.” ScreenPlay: Cinema/Videogames/
Interfaces. Ed. Geoff King and Tanya Krzywinska.
McLuhan, Marshall. “Art as Anti-environment.” Art
London: Wallflower, 2002. 81–97. Print.
News Annual 36 (1966): 54–57. Print.
Nietz, J., T. Geist, and G.H. Jacobs. “Color Vision in
McLuhan, Marshall. “Classroom without Walls.”
the Dog.” Visual Neuroscience 3 (1989): 119–25.
Explorations in Communication. Ed. Edmund
Print.
Carpenter and Marshall McLuhan. Boston:
Beacon, 1960. 1–3. Print. Palmer, Clare. “‘Taming the Wild Profusion of
Existing Things’? A Study of Foucault, Power and
McLuhan, Marshall. “The Emperor’s New
Human/Animal Relationships.” Environmental
Clothes.” 1968. Essential McLuhan. Ed. Eric
Ethics 23.4 (2001): 339–58. Print.
McLuhan and Frank Zingrone. New York: Basic,
1995. 339–56. Print. Paxton, David. Why it’s OK to Talk to Your Dog:
Co-evolution of People and Dogs. Brisbane:
McLuhan, Marshall. “The Emperor’s Old Clothes.”
Boolarong, 2011. Print.
1966. Unbound, #20. Ed. Eric McLuhan and
W. Terrence Gordon. Corte Madera, CA: Pickel, D., G.P. Manucy, D.B. Walker, S.B. Hall, and
Gingko, 2005. 3–14. Print. J.C. Walker. “Evidence for Canine Olfactory
Detection of Melanoma.” Applied Animal Behaviour
McLuhan, Marshall. Letters of Marshall McLuhan. Ed.
Science 89 (2004): 107–16. Print.
Matie Molinaro, Corinne McLuhan, and William
Toye. Toronto: Oxford UP, 1987. Print. Pratkanis, Anthony. “Altercasting as an Influence
Tactic.” Attitudes, Behavior, and Social Context: The
McLuhan, Marshall. “The Relation of Environment
Role of Norms and Group Membership. Ed.
to Anti-environment.” 1966. Media Research:
Deborah J. Terry and Michael A. Hogg. Mahwah,
Technology, Art, Communication. Ed. Michel
NJ: Erlbaum, 2000. 201–26. Print.
A. Moos. Amsterdam: G+B, 1997. 110–20. Print.
Rae, Alice. “Art (Anti-environment).” Light through
McLuhan, Marshall. Understanding Media: The
McLuhan. Web. 30 Mar. 2012. <http://light-
Extensions of Man. 3rd printing. New York:
throughmcluhan.org/art.html>.
McGraw-Hill, 1964. Print.
Scent Sciences. “ScentScape Gaming Suite.” Web.
McLuhan, Marshall, and Quentin Fiore, with
30 Mar. 2012. <http://www.scentsciences.com/
Jerome Agel. The Medium is the Massage.
products/scent_scape_gaming_suite.html>.
New York: Random, 1967. Print.
Scott, John Paul, and John L. Fuller. Genetics and
McLuhan, Marshall, and Quentin Fiore, with
Social Behavior of the Dog. Chicago: U of Chicago
Jerome Agel. War and Peace in the Global Village.
P, 1965. Print.
New York: McGraw-Hill, 1968. Print.
Skinner, B.F. Verbal Behavior. New York: Appleton,
McLuhan, Marshall, and Harley Parker. Through the
1957. Print.
Vanishing Point: Space in Poetry and Painting.
New York: Harper, 1968. Print. Smith, Logan Pearsall. Words and Idioms: Studies in
the English Language. 5th ed. London: Constable,
McLuhan, Marshall, and Wilfred Watson. From
1943. Print.
Cliché to Archetype. New York: Viking, 1970. Print.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. “More on Power/
Mellen, Jill, and Sue Ellis. “Animal Learning and
Knowledge.” Outside in the Teaching Machine.
Husbandry Training.” Wild Mammals in Captivity:
New York: London, 1993. 25–52. Print.
Principles and Techniques. Ed. Devra G. Kleinman,
Mary E. Allen, Katerina V. Thompson, and Susan Steffen, Oliver. “High-Speed Meditation? Eine
Lumpkin. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1996. 88–99. religionsästhetische und ritualtheoretische
Print. Betrachtung des Computerspiels.” MA diss. U of

81
new tricks

Bern, 30 May 2008. Web. 30 Mar. 2012. <http://


www.god-mode.ch/assets/downloads/oliver-steff
en_high-speed_meditation-lizentiatsarbeit%20_mai-
2008.pdf>.
Tyler, Tom. “If Horses had Hands …” Animal
Encounters. Ed. Tom Tyler and Manuela Rossini.
Leiden: Brill, 2009. 13–26. Web. 30 Mar. 2012.
<http://www.cyberchimp.co.uk/research/horses
hands.htm>.
Tyler, Tom. ‘A Procrustean Probe.’ Game Studies 8.2
(2008). Web. 30 Mar. 2012. <http://gamestudies.
org/0802/articles/tyler>.
Uexküll, Jakob von. A Foray into the Worlds of
Animals and Humans. Trans. Joseph D. O’Neil.
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print.
Vint, Sherryl. Animal Alterity: Science Fiction and the
Question of the Animal. Liverpool: Liverpool UP,
2010. Print.
Wang, Xiaoming, and Richard H. Tedford. Dogs:
Their Fossil Relatives and Evolutionary History.
Illustrated by Mauricio Antón. New York:
Columbia UP, 2008. Print.
Weinstein, Eugene A., and Paul Deutschberger.
“Some Dimensions of Altercasting.” Sociometry
26.4 (1963): 454–66. Print.
Winthrop-Young, Geoffrey. “Afterword: Bubbles
and Webs: A Backdoor Stroll through the
Readings of Uexküll.” A Foray into the Worlds of
Animals and Humans. By Jakob von Uexküll.
Trans. Joseph D. O’Neil. Minneapolis: U of
Minnesota P, 2010. 209–43. Print.
Wolfe, Cary. Animal Rites: American Culture, the
Discourse of Species, and Posthumanist Theory.
Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2003. Print.

ludography
Catwoman. Electronic Arts, 2004.
Dog’s Life. Frontier Developments, 2003.
Tom Tyler
It’s a Dog’s Life aka Digby the Dog and Digby’s
Adventures. Sanctuary Woods, 1994.
Department of History, Philosophy and
Religion
WolfQuest. Eduweb, 2007. Oxford Brookes University
Harcourt Hill Campus
Oxford OX2 9AT
UK
E-mail: ttyler@brookes.ac.uk
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

book of beasts

I n 1868, a slim, anonymously published book


entitled Les Chants de Maldoror appeared in
Parisian bookshops. It contained only the first
Chant or Canto, and its purported author was
the “Comte de Lautréamont” – much in line
with the fin-de-siècle vogue for the gothic, the
decadent, and a turn towards a literary, aesthetic
aristocratism. In its posthumous life, the book
would have a decisive impact on the countercul- eugene thacker
ture, from Surrealism to Situationism. But at
the time of its publication Les Chants de Mal-
doror (hereafter Maldoror) was completely
ignored, even when Canto I was re-published
APOPHATIC
in the anthology Parfumes de l’Ame a year ANIMALITY
later, and even when the full Maldoror appeared
in book form. lautr éamont, bachelard,
It is not difficult to see why this book was
largely ignored. It was neither prose nor poem,
and the bliss of
neither fiction nor non-fiction – it did not metamorphosis
even fit into the popular genre of the roman
noir, or the then-emerging genre of the prose
poem. The following passage – from Canto II squids (at a distance resembling crows) float
– is representative of much of the text’s above the clouds and scud stiffly toward the
idiosyncrasies: cities of the humans, their mission to warn
men to change their ways – the gloomy-
There are times in life when verminous- eyed pebble perceives amid flashes of light-
scalped man trains his wild and staring gaze ning two beings pass by, one behind the
upon the green membranes of space, for other, and, wiping away a furtive tear of com-
ahead of him he seems to hear the ironic passion that trickles from its frozen eye,
jeers of a phantom. He reels and bows his cries: “Certainly he deserves it; it’s only
head: what he has heard is the voice of con- justice.” Having spoken thus it reverts to
science. Then quick as a madman he rushes its timid pose and trembling nervously,
in amazement from the house, taking the continues to watch the manhunt and the
first route available, and tears along vast lips of the vagina of darkness whence
the rugose plains of the countryside. But flow incessantly, like a river, immense
the yellow phantom does not lose sight of shadowy spermatozoa that take flight into
him and just as rapidly pursues. Sometimes the dismal aether, the vast spread of their
on a stormy night while legions of winged bat’s wings obscuring the whole of nature

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010083-16 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783443

83
apophatic animality

and the lonely legions of squids – grown image – pages on pages of thick, block text
downcast viewing these ineffable and with dense, phantasmagoric creatures following
muffled fulgurations. (Lautréamont, Mal- one after the other. At some points the text
doror 101–02) addresses the reader directly, almost confronta-
tionally; at other points the text digresses into
Animals abound in Maldoror, but their func-
long, quasi-scientific descriptions of flora and
tions vary, from the symbolic, to the scientific,
fauna; at still other points the text suddenly
to the absurd. The passage that opens Chant
breaks into pulp horror or gothic romance.
IV extends this litany of animalization across
Maldoror breaks nearly every rule of poetics,
the spectrum of beings, from the human to
though it does this less as avant-garde posturing
the mineral, culminating in one of the text’s
and more because the text cannot help itself.
many incantations against the human:
There seems to be no end to what the text can
A man or a stone or a tree is about to begin do or is capable of – in a way, its length and div-
this fourth canto. When the foot slithers on ision into six Cantos seems almost arbitrary.
a frog one feels a sensation of disgust, but The one review that did appear upon the orig-
one’s hand has barely to stroke the human inal publication of Maldoror expressed mostly a
body before the skin of the fingers cracks puzzled astonishment: “the hyperbolic bombast
like flakes from a block of mica being of the style, the savage strangeness, the despe-
smashed by hammer blows; and even as the rate vigour of conception, the contrast of this
heart of a shark an hour dead still palpitates impassioned language with the dullest lucubra-
on the deck with dogged vitality, so are we
tions of our time, at first cast the mind into a
stirred to our very depths long after the
deep amazement” (Lautréamont 276).1 The
contact. Such is the horror man inspires in
his own neighbour! Perhaps I am mistaken reviewer’s reaction echoes subsequent mentions
to propose this, but perhaps too I am of Maldoror in literary criticism and literary
telling the truth. I know of, conceive, a sick- histories. Such comments have always been
ness more terrible than the eyes swollen from brief and astonished, as if happening upon a
long meditations upon the strange nature of strange but menacing beast. Antonin Artaud
man: but I am seeking it still […] and have sums up the general attitude of nineteenth-
been unable to find it! I do not consider and early twentieth-century criticism towards
myself less intelligent than anyone else, and the likes of Lautréamont, Nerval, and Baude-
yet who would dare assert that I have suc- laire: “they were afraid that their poetry might
ceeded in my investigations? What a lie
leap out of the books and turn reality upside
would escape his lips! The ancient temple
down” (Artaud 125). In fact, such comments
of Denderah lies an hour and a half away
from the left bank of the Nile. Today count- on Maldoror are interesting for precisely this
less phalanxes of wasps have taken possession reason – they inadvertently treat the text as
of its gutters and cornices. They swarm alive, the text as animal. For many readers,
round the columns like dense waves of Maldoror not only confronted one in an
black hair. Sole inhabitants of the cold abject, monstrous way, but the text itself
porch, they guard entrance to antechambers seemed like an animal, a teratological anomaly
as a hereditary right. I liken the humming composed of bits and pieces, a corpus left unfin-
of their metallic wings to the incessant clash ished or untended. In contrast to the textuality
of ice-floes flung against one another during of the animal so frequently found in literary rep-
the breaking-up of the polar seas. But if I
resentation, Maldoror seems to put forth the
ponder the conduct of him on whom provi-
animality of the text – composed of multiple
dence has conferred this earth’s throne, the
three pinions of my grief give vent to a tendrils, leaping off the page, devouring the
louder murmur! (131–32) reader. In The Romantic Agony, published in
the 1930s, literary critic Mario Praz includes
Much of Maldoror displays this sense of a only a few paragraphs on Lautréamont. But
prodigious outpouring of word, sound, and even in these few lines he echoes this tendency

84
thacker

to treat Maldoror as an unnatural creature, Latréaumont, a gothic novel by Eugène Sue


referring to Maldoror as a “late but extreme published in the 1830s. As for the title, Mal-
case of cannibalistic Byronism” (163). doror has often been compared to the French
When Maldoror was “discovered” by the phrase mal d’aurore or “evil dawn,” something
Surrealists, another shift occurred in the recep- that seems to be supported in one of the few sur-
tion of the text: the animality of Maldoror sud- viving letters of Ducasse: “Let me explain my
denly gave way to an almost mystical quality. situation to you. I have sung of evil as did Mis-
André Breton noted that Maldoror was “the ckiéwickz, Byron, Milton, Southey, A. de
expression of a revelation so complete it seems Musset, Baudelaire, etc.” (Lautréamont 258).2
to exceed human potential.” Philippe Soupault Further detective work has highlighted the
edited several editions of Maldoror, and Louis many textual appropriations that find their
Aragon wrote the essay Lautréamont et nous. way into Maldoror, from literary appropriations
No doubt Breton, Soupault, and Aragon were of Homer, the Bible, Shakespeare, Dante, Bau-
taken by the often surprising juxtapositions in delaire, Maturin, to extended passages from
the text, the most famous of which is the textbooks on mathematics and the natural
phrase “beautiful as the chance meeting on a sciences – foremost among them Jean-Charles
dissecting table of a sewing machine and an Chenu’s Encyclopédie d’histoire naturelle
umbrella.” But Breton’s comments point to (1850–61). All of the “facts” surrounding Mal-
another aspect of Maldoror, one that extends doror seem to point to a text that, at all levels,
the animality of the text, and that is its vigorous attempts to unhumanize itself, divesting itself
and persistent anti-humanism. While the Surre- of authorship, authentic voice, and even signifi-
alists were unwavering critics of religion, they cance. The text of Maldoror is predatory in its
notoriously imported a whole host of mystical extensive borrowings, and, true to Praz’s
and occult themes into their works. Little sur- words, ultimately becomes an autophage,
prise, then, that Maldoror – a text that would devouring itself in the process. As we will see,
become part of the Surrealist canon – is fre- this tendency towards a self-abnegation at once
quently described in mystical terms: Breton corporeal and textual allows Maldoror to effec-
evoked Lautréamont as “that dazzling figure of tively collapse the distance separating the
black light”; Artaud lauded Maldoror for its bestial and the spiritual.
almost mystical, “perfect lucidity,” an “orgy
of the collective unconscious trespassing on
individual consciousness”; René Daumal
tooth and claw, flesh and blood
asserted that Maldoror was nothing less than a Among the modern studies of Maldoror, there
“holy war” on humanity. is a significant body of work that deals with
These two views of Maldoror – as animality the role of animals and animality in the text.
and as spirituality – often dovetail into each But the critical work on Maldoror differs on
other, becoming nearly indistinguishable from how exactly to approach the topic. Some advo-
each other, resulting in what Gaston Bachelard cate an understanding of the animals in Mal-
referred to as “the bliss of metamorphosis.” doror through language and linguistic tropes.
Much of this is borne out by modern literary For instance, in his analysis of “animal
scholarship on Maldoror. There is the question similes” in Maldoror, Peter Nesselroth argues
of authorship – the real person Isidore Ducasse, that the animals in the text must be understood
who uses the pen name Comte de Lautréamont, within the context of the cultural represen-
and about whom very little is known, except tations of animals, a context that allows
that he was born in Montevideo, Uruguay in Lautréamont to play with the many strange
1846, and that, in 1870, he died under myster- comparisons between humans and animals
ious circumstances in his Parisian hotel room. (including the many insertions of scientific
Literary detectives have noted the similarity descriptions of animals). The result of such dis-
between the name Lautréamont and ruptions in the conventions of poetic language is

85
apophatic animality

that the reader “finds that Lautréamont is they allegorical stand-ins for human beings. In
revealing to him a new mode of perception, a a text like Maldoror the message is clear: ani-
vision which is not restricted by the artificial mality is no way reducible to animals.
limits imposed through culture, since the The critical work to have comprehended this
boundaries between the objective and subjective is Gaston Bachelard’s 1939 study Lautréamont.
have vanished” (Nesselroth 69).3 In his analysis of the “animal life complex” in
Other approaches suggest that the strange Maldoror, Bachelard suggests we understand
and anomalous creatures of Maldoror should animality on a phenomenological plane, as a
be understood in terms of dream, phantasm, “vigorous poetry of aggression” (2). For Bache-
and the archetypes of nightmares. This is what lard this means understanding animals less as
Alex de Jonge proposes, in his analysis of Mal- scientific species or cultural symbols, and
doror as an extended “anatomy of a nightmare.” more in terms of their affectivity. As he notes,
Animals in Maldoror are often portrayed in off- “Lautréamont grasps animals not as forms but
kilter ways, either through an inversion of the as direct functions – that is, their aggressive
natural order (talking spiders or frogs), or functions” (3). Animals never are, they always
through exaggerations in scale (the glow-worm do – moving, growing, pouncing, and devour-
as big as a house). For de Jonge, “Lautréamont ing. In this sense Maldoror is an inventory of
distorts and destroys the essential matrices affects: “A complete classification of animal
through which we decode reality. His distor- phobias and philias would yield a sort of affec-
tions threaten our sense of space, of what is tive animal kingdom that would be interesting
‘up’ and what is ‘down,’ our ability to judge to compare with the animal kingdom described
the relative size of images formed on the in the bestiaries of antiquity and the Middle
retina” (82). The particular types of animals Ages” (79).
that frequent the pages of Maldoror – insects, One of Bachelard’s most instructive analyses
reptiles, amphibians – stand out in their comes in his contrast between Lautréamont and
radical difference from the human animal. “So La Fontaine. The latter, well known as the
foreign are they that they represent a devastat- author of a number of beast fables, tends to
ing threat, a rich source of nightmare” (84). portray humans in the guise of animals. The
Finally, there are those approaches that animals in La Fontaine’s Fables only appear to
suggest we understand the innumerable be animals; underneath they are simply exem-
animals, creatures, and monsters in Maldoror plars of human types and characters. For
in relation to the concept of “nature” in the Lautréamont, nearly the reverse is true –
history of science, in which natural philosophy, humans, when they are present in the text,
logic and classification, and even theology go tend to look like animals, or are rapidly animal-
hand-in-hand. In an admirable account of ized in their actions. If La Fontaine is really
animals in Maldoror, Alain Paris suggests interested in the human in the animal, then
that, in its excessive proliferation of life forms Lautréamont is interested in the animal in the
both real and fantastical, Maldoror borrows human. Furthermore, in Maldoror humans
the model of the bestiary. For Paris, don’t just resemble animals, they frequently
Lautréamont “is an explorer, an explorer of undergo metamorphosis and become animals
the human. An explorer of the inhuman, also, as well. Bachelard stresses this active,
and particularly of the animal kingdom. From dynamic, “aggressive” animality in Maldoror,
there the bestiary is born, like a diversion in which animality is equivalent to function.
recorded in a log book” (6; translation mine). This stands in contrast to La Fontaine, for
Though one can annotate each and every whom animality is physiognomy, represen-
instance of this or that animal in the text, such tation, and form. In the innumerable hybrids,
tabulations will bring one no closer to the ani- teratologies and metamorphoses that constitute
mality of Maldoror. In Maldoror, animals are Maldoror, Lautréamont asserts a concept of ani-
neither exemplars of the natural world, nor are mality that is constantly producing life, life as

86
thacker

presentation. By contrast, in the characteriz- In one scene described by Bachelard, the dis-
ation and caricature of the human animals in embodied “spirit” of Maldoror is transformed,
the Fables, La Fontaine portrays life, life under- first into an eagle, then into an entire flock,
stood as representation. Whereas Lautréamont and finally into a strange, phantom, “lost
understands animality as an explosion of body” composed of a detached pair of albatross
affects, La Fontaine understands animality as a wings co-mingled with a fish tail, which then
set of behaviors. Bachelard summarizes these takes angry flight in defiance of “the Creator.”
points, letting loose a hint of the romanticism For Bachelard, such moments reveal less about
that runs throughout his study: “La Fontaine animals and more about the abstract process
has written of human psychology in the form of animalization, signaling “a sort of vertigo of
of an animal fable, but Lautréamont has the animalizing faculty, which at this point
written an inhuman fable by reviving those will animalize anything. In its very inadequacy
brutal impulses that are still potent in men’s this instant biological synthesis shows clearly a
hearts” (3).4 need to animalize that is at the origins of
Comparisons such as these allow Bachelard to imagination” (27). Thus, while there are numer-
draw out his major analytical contribution to the ous animals in Maldoror, for Bachelard they are
study of Maldoror, and to pinpoint more largely subsumed within the affective physi-
specifically the animality in and of the text. A ology of tearing and sucking, claw and tooth,
catalog of the major appearances of animals flesh and blood.
and their actions reveals for Bachelard two In Maldoror animality is in no way identical
major aspects that constitute the animality of with animals per se, and yet the text is replete
Maldoror. There is the action of tearing, and with animals, animals that come to us straight
its association with the physiology of the claw, out of natural history books, but also out of
the beak, the horn, and then there is the the fantastical worlds of literature, the bestiary,
action of sucking, and its physiological associ- and myth. This type of layering – animals in the
ation with the sucker, the fang, the mouth. text and animals as text – is something that can
For Bachelard these constitute the twin poles only be achieved in the “anti-generic” poetics of
of Maldoror’s animality: “In fact I believe text like Maldoror, with its many references,
Lautréamontism is almost exclusively con- borrowings, appropriations, and modes of pas-
cerned with two themes: the claw and the tiche. A proposition, then: animality is that
sucker, which correspond to the twin attractions point where the animals in the text and the
of flesh and blood” (16). text as animal converge. 5 That point of conver-
Furthermore, the actions of sucking and gence is, as Bachelard has already intimated, on
tearing are not exclusive to their corresponding, the issue of form.
anatomical organs. The action of tearing (or
sucking) may be passed laterally, from a claw
to a tusk, a beak, or a stinger. Similarly, the
the bliss of metamorphosis
object of tearing (or sucking) may also be trans- Maldoror is a text where the wild metamor-
ferred, from the flesh of amphibian skin to the phoses of creatures in the text are matched
smooth marble of a statue. This lateral transfer- only by the equally wild metamorphosis of the
ence is so fecund in Maldoror that it almost text itself. So great is this animality of forms
becomes arbitrary, obtaining an almost animis- in Maldoror that production and destruction,
tic propensity for the formation and defor- generation and decay, forming and de-forming
mation of forms. As Bachelard notes, in tend to overlap. As Bachelard notes, in Mal-
Maldoror “the beautiful can no longer be doror “a living being has an appetite for forms
simply reproduced. First of all it must be pro- at least as great as his appetite for matter”
duced. It borrows from life – from matter (84). This emphasis not just on form but on
itself – elementary energies that are first trans- life forms places Lautréamont in relation to
formed, then transfigured” (60). Aristotle. While Aristotle’s works in natural

87
apophatic animality

philosophy contain detailed descriptions of re-forming and de-forming as well. Maldoror


animals, it is in the treatise known as De is not exactly against Aristotelianism; if any-
anima that Aristotle talks about life in itself, thing, it is Aristotelianism run amok, a feral
apart from any particular manifestation. The Aristotelianism.
question that guides Aristotle’s inquiry has to This “appetite for forms” has a teleology that
do not just with understanding this or that life is ostensibly spiritual. The appetite for forms is
form but with understanding the life of every not arbitrary or happenstance, in spite of its
life form. For Aristotle, there must be some- aggressive, instinctual connotations. Bachelard
thing substantial to each and every form of suggests that the appetite for forms in Maldoror
life, such that we can say that a bird, a human, often passes through successive stages, culmi-
a tree and an octopus are all alive. It is here nating in an ecstatic, almost mystical state.
that Aristotle proposes the term psukhē (often The animality of Maldoror “would proceed
translated in English as “soul,” but more accu- through a world of living forms executed in
rately as “life-principle”). This soul or life-prin- well-defined bestiaries, then through a zone of
ciple is, for Aristotle, directly connected to the trial forms to end finally in a more or less
form of any living being. As Aristotle notes, clear awareness of the almost anarchic freedom
“the soul [psukhē] must be substance in the of spiritualization” (83). The comment is brief,
sense of being the form of a natural body, and Bachelard does not follow it up. But the
which potentially has life” (69). Furthermore, suggestion is an interesting one – that at the
this principle of life forms is always form-ing, core of Maldoror’s animality is really a spiritual-
in the sense that it is an actualization of this ity. The “spiritual anarchy” of Maldoror is a
potential for life: “The soul may therefore be direct result of its aggressive, vitalistic, animal-
defined as the first actuality of a natural body ity of forms. At another point in his study,
possessing life” (69). The capacity for form is, Bachelard briefly mentions an even more impor-
for a thinker like Aristotle, tantamount to the tant phrase – “the bliss of metamorphosis” – to
potential for life; there is no life without a describe this intersection of animality and mys-
form of life. ticism: “[…] there are passages that give clear
Against Aristotle, form in Maldoror is evidence of the frenzy and especially of the
neither that which holds matter nor that which bliss of metamorphosis […] for Lautréamont
is abstractly shaped as an empty container. metamorphosis is a means of executing an ener-
Form is not an end in itself, nor does form getic act all at once” (6). Again, Bachelard does
give way to the ontological priority of matter not elaborate or develop this mystical motif. But
(even if this matter is viewed in terms of its vita- it is arguably central to an understanding of the
listic, emergent properties). Form does not lead animality of Maldoror. The “bliss of metamor-
to that which is well-formed, or in-formed. It is, phosis” not only describes an animality that is
to use Bachelard’s terms, the dynamics of inseparable from a mystical tendency but it
tearing and sucking, flesh and blood, claw and also attempts to conceive of form in a way that
tooth; but these are themselves a manifestation is at once the lowest and the highest, the
of a more general animality, which is driven bestial and the spiritual, the deformed and the
by an aggressive, generative, “appetite for informed.
forms.” Instead, in Maldoror there is a sense Bachelard is not the only reader of Maldoror
in which everything is devoured by form, at to have pointed to this spiritual aspect – and in
the same time that form devours everything, particular, the defiant, anarchic spirituality of
including itself. In Maldoror, form is never the text. Such a reading is implicitly a part of
formed, but instead devoured, metabolized, the Surrealist fascination with Lautréamont,
broken down and reconstituted again in a new and it forms an important part of Maurice Blan-
guise. The animality of Maldoror is, in a chot’s study Lautréamont and Sade. More
sense, the extension of Aristotelianism to its recently, it has been extended in Liliane
logical conclusion, in which the forming is also Durand-Dessert’s study La Guerre Sainte:

88
thacker

Lautréamont et Isidore Ducasse, where, contra that they can only refer to as “evil” or
existing interpretations, Durand-Dessert “cruelty.” In Canto II the discovery of a
argues for a “religious war” at the heart of Mal- corpse in the Seine prompts a reflection on the
doror: “This revolution in consciousness of arbitrariness of death; this directly correlates
which Maldoror is […] the legible trace, is not to an earlier section where the narrator imagines
in itself a new phenomenon, since it constitutes the corpse of God, composed of a multitude of
the foundation of all religions, and is something fish and amphibians. Apprehension and dread
one finds is the basis of all initiatory traditions” predominate, as if the apparent order of the
(3; translation mine). all-too-human world were suddenly thrown
In fact, we can draw out the implications of into abeyance. All human actions seem arbi-
Bachelard’s brief comments by re-casting Mal- trary, a pervasive sense of dread can suddenly
doror as a text on animality that is structured come over the safest and most secure of
along the lines of a mystical itinerary. The text situations.
begins from a normative state of the human, Another stage occurs in which we see the ani-
structured along the division of life forms malization of the human – and the divine. Here,
(human, animal, plant, mineral) which corre- Maldoror moves beyond the confrontation of
spond to the division of life faculties (reason, human and animal and moves into the terrain
motion, nutrition, change). We see all the exem- of hybridity, effected through Bachelard’s two-
plars of nineteenth-century European culture – fold activators of tearing and sucking. The
the bourgeois family, the innocent youth, relations of human–animal, animal–animal,
lovers and adventurers, men of science, and of and, importantly, animal–God are each played
course priests. But we also see criminals, the out through successive metamorphoses and
insane, grave-diggers, and the sick on their transformations. Not only are there human–
death-beds. In short, the life and world of animal hybrids, we also see: a reincarnated,
humanity. In Maldoror this is the human vampiric spider; a glow-worm’s soliloquy on
world of science and religion, especially prostitution; a long elegy for a sleeping her-
natural history and natural theology. Here, ani- maphrodite-seer; a decapitated octopus rebel-
mality is always reduced to the animal, either in ling against God; and a giant dung-beetle
the form of religious iconography (e.g., sheep, playing out its sorrowful, excremental, Sisy-
goats, black dogs) or in terms of scientific phean drama. Perhaps the most notorious
rationality (e.g., the numerous appropriations example of this type of animality comes in
of the Encyclopédie d’histoire naturelle found Canto II, where, amidst a stormy shipwreck
in Maldoror). scene off a rocky shore, the narrator has a pas-
Into this world Maldoror depicts the invasion sionate sexual encounter with a giant shark.
of animality, the invasion of the human by the The final stage of Maldoror’s mystical itiner-
unhuman. Sometimes this occurs via actual ary is the stage where the immediacy of animal-
animals, chosen for their stark difference to ity leads to a pure openness of form in unceasing
the human (the various amphibians and reptile metamorphosis. The text departs from the ani-
hybrids that populate the text), and at other mality in the text and moves out to the animality
times this occurs via animal assemblages of the text itself; the scenes and events por-
(flocks, swarms, or packs of animals). At one trayed in the book – themselves appropriations
point in Canto I this type of animality is from other sources – gradually give way to an
depicted as a predatory, miasmatic force haunt- almost purely arbitrary production of forms
ing both family and domestic space; this miasma (an “anarchic spiritualization”). Vampiric fin-
turns into a pack of rabid dogs, which somehow gernails grow over a few weeks, along with a
telepathically connect to a frightened, young craving for infant blood, there is a soliloquy
boy in the safety of his bed, as he realizes his by a hair found in a brothel bed, each of the
fate. In such scenes the human characters are body’s organs turn into rodents or reptiles,
confronted with something radically unhuman God is transformed into a toad and then a

89
apophatic animality

giant hog, we see the world from the perspective of metamorphosis? Bachelard gives us a clue,
of a python, a basilisk, and an oak tree, and though it is ultimately the weakest point in his
mathematics becomes at once the most revered analysis. There is undoubtedly a strong anti-
and most horrific of all things, the unhuman humanist thread that runs through Maldoror,
in its ultimate form. evidenced not only by the violence done to
Thus, insofar as Maldoror thinks animality nearly all human characters but also by the
through the lens of mysticism, we can discern bestiary of animals, animal parts, and animal
a mystical itinerary, driven by “the bliss of transformations. While human beings usually
metamorphosis,” an animality of forms that undergo monstrous transformations in Mal-
has its telos in the dual negation of human and doror, and while the author constantly rallies
divine, man and God. In the final stages of against the human (including the human-made
this itinerary, the text moves from reproduction God), Bachelard suggests that the anti-human-
to production, from representation to presen- ism of Maldoror is actually an attempt to
tation, signaling a shift from the animality in re-imagine a renewed human, within the frame-
the text to the animality of the text. All of this work of animality. As Bachelard notes provoca-
proceeds from the premise that the animality tively, “the bestiary of our dreams animates a
of Maldoror is not reducible to animals. This life that returns to biological depths […] All
in turn means a focus on the form-giving and the functions can create symbols; all biological
form-generating process in life forms, taken to heresies can produce phantasms” (86).
its extreme in the many cases of monstrous Ultimately, for Bachelard the animality of
metamorphoses. Here animality is that form- Maldoror comes to be regarded as a testament
generating principle of life (Aristotle’s psukhē) to a kind of super-human capacity for imagin-
that conditions the very possibility of form ation and the poetics of form – even at the
and forming, the very capacity for form. Philo- moment when the text so violently revolts
sophically speaking, such a notion implies a against the human. For Bachelard the animality
metaphysics of generosity, a commitment to a of Maldoror is really about poiesis, the creation
first principle of generation, fecundity, and affir- of new forms, what Bachelard terms a “poetry of
mation – a first principle of a philosophy that, the project” or simply the “open imagination.”
by definition, cannot be examined in philos- The successive, incessant, and aggressive trans-
ophy. It is, perhaps, precisely for this reason formations in Maldoror come to be seen as an
that this type of animality takes on the tone of indicator of the human passing beyond the
mysticism. animal, and finally passing beyond itself. Bache-
lard again: “At that point, man appears as the
sum of vital possibilities, as a super-animal.
devouring the human All of animality is at his disposal” (11).
We have moved, then, from a consideration of Bachelard’s emphasis on the imagination is
animality in Maldoror to a consideration of its not an attempt to re-install the human at the
strange conflux of animality and spirituality, top of the Great Chain of Being. Lurking
its spiritual anarchy of life forms, driven by a behind his proposals for a poiesis of the open
vitalist metaphysics of generosity and prodigal- imagination is a further investment in a vitalist
ity. Readers of Maldoror such as Bachelard metaphysics of fecundity, generosity, and meta-
already hint at this “bliss of metamorphosis,” morphosis. Maldoror is not so much a testa-
in which animality is in no way reducible to ment to the human capacity to imagine
animals. any- and everything; rather, Maldoror is the
But in our shift from animality to spirituality manifestation of an anonymous, generative,
we have, as it were, jumped over the human – creative principle that animates the world –
the target of some of the most vitriolic phrases and especially the natural world. There is a
in Maldoror. What is the status of the human sense in which, for Bachelard, “imagination”
in relation to this mystical animality, this bliss is simply another name for poiesis, producing,

90
thacker

creating. This comes through in the closing perpetual transformation and metamorphosis.
pages of his book: In this way, the open imagination is not exclu-
sive to human beings or the products of
The way of direct human exertion is only a human culture. Bachelard comes very close to
poor extension of animal exertion. It is in
making a “realist” assertion for this generalized
the dream of action that the truly human joy
poiesis as a property of the world as such.
of action resides. To cause to act without
acting; to leave bound time for liberated Yet, even if we take Bachelard to mean
time, performance time for decision time “imagination” in a broadly non-human sense,
[…] to replace a philosophy of action, too it is unclear why an explicitly poetic text,
often a philosophy of agitation, with a philos- belonging explicitly to human culture, would
ophy of repose and then a philosophy of the be the avatar of this open imagination. Why
consciousness of reposing […] Next, this not, for instance, make the claim that the gen-
repose of the imagination must be taken as erative metamorphoses and morphologies of
the point of departure for a discovery of nature itself are the true exemplars of the
firmly deanimalized thought-motifs, free open imagination? Problems like these are com-
from all allurement, cut off from the hypno-
pounded when one considers the strong, anti-
tism of images, clearly separated from the cat-
humanist thread that runs throughout Mal-
egories of understanding that are concretized
forms of intellectual prudence, “fossilized doror. For a text that so virulently poises itself
states of intellectual repression.” (90) against humanity, it would seem strange to
hold up Maldoror as the pinnacle of imaginative
While we may agree with Bachelard’s attempts achievement, human or otherwise.
to move animality beyond “the animal,” it For Bachelard, anti-humanism and animality
remains unclear how such a “firmly deanima- co-exist in an uneasy relationship. Anti-human-
lized thought” avoids simply re-instating the ism ultimately leads to a renewed humanism of
human at the top of the pyramid (all the more the imagination, an elevation of the human
so in that Bachelard mentions, at one point, a above the animal. Hence Bachelard manages to
“psychoanalysis of life” as part of his project). take what is perhaps the most extreme state-
Part of the confusion comes from the jump ment of anti-humanism and transform it into a
that Bachelard makes, from a discussion of the call for a renewed humanism of the imagination.
animality in the text to a discussion of the ani- For Bachelard, the animality of Maldoror is the
mality of the text of Maldoror itself. While vehicle by which humanity renews itself – less in
much of Bachelard’s analysis operates at the terms of reason and more in terms of imagin-
level of the animality in the text (as per his ation. Hence animality is subsumed within
analysis of tearing and sucking motifs), the humanity (though a humanity of imagination
larger, more philosophical claims made by rather than reason). Maldoror is, in Bachelard’s
Bachelard rely on an identity between the two reading, a poetic sacrifice of animality for a new
types of animality (in the text and of the text). humanity.
Put another way, Bachelard’s arguments con-
cerning the open imagination and the vitalist
poetics of Maldoror actually rely on the collapse
apophatic animality
of the distinction between the animality in the As we have noted, Maldoror suggests to us a
text and the animality of the text. relationship between animality and spirituality.
In his discussion of the open imagination, But this spirituality need not be of an anthropo-
Bachelard wants to make a claim for a general- centric type, in which the human is the endpoint
ized poiesis, one that extends beyond modes of and culmination of animality, immediacy the
literary representation, and, ultimately, even highest bliss, metamorphosis the highest form.
beyond modes of textual production. This Might there be another type of animality at
poiesis is, for Bachelard, thoroughly vitalist, play in Maldoror, an animality that still
generative, and fecund; it is an animality of retains this link to spirituality, but that does

91
apophatic animality

not simply culminate in the raising up of the and more its inverse: an animality of the nega-
human animal as its highest form? Is there an tion of life, of the withdrawal of form, of the
anti-humanist animality at play in Maldoror? liquidation and dissipation of form, of the emp-
The traditional view of animals in philosophy tying of all form – in short, an animality that,
is often split: it tends either to reduce animals to while retaining the link to mysticism, also con-
their naturalistic substrate or elevate them into ceives of mysticism precisely as the dissipation
an abstract realm of flows and forces. Ironically, of form. Is there an animality of absence, of dis-
in the philosophy of animals, animals them- tance, of opacity – an oblique animality? This
selves disappear behind the mists of empirical would mean looking to those moments in Mal-
observation, epistemological classification, and doror when animality ceases simply to be
the hermeneutic demand for myth, symbol, immediate, while not being absent – moments
and psychological depth. Either animality is when animality avails itself in its inaccessibility.
reducible to animals or animality is raised up Animality in Maldoror is not the continual pro-
to and includes human life; either animality liferation of forms; animality constantly slips
excludes the human or it includes the human. away, a single animal losing its form and becom-
In the former view – a lateral version of animal- ing a swarm of animals, which in turn disaggre-
ity – all life forms are arrayed on a plane as part gate and become indistinguishable from the
of the animal kingdom, each with differing elements and the atmosphere itself, all of this
characteristics. In the latter view – a vertical just as easily dissipated into the oblique and
version of animality – all life forms are arranged opaque ideas that inhabit the text of Maldoror.
in a hierarchy of capacities and functions. Perhaps, then, there is less a mystical itiner-
However, what both of these views have in ary in Maldoror and more a mystical anomaly,
common is a philosophical commitment to a an interruption of divine beatitude, a mysticism
metaphysics of generosity and prodigality, a that ends not with the fullness of the bliss of
vitalist ontology of fecund forms that constantly metamorphosis but with a different type of
proliferate, generate, and change. The animality bliss, a gothic bliss of the loss of all form.
of animals is this commitment to the idea of a Such a gothic bliss would require an ontology
primordial, vitalist generosity of creation and based not in affirmation and generosity, but
form. Hence the philosophy of animals must instead in negation and dissipation – in short,
presume something prior to the animal called it would require a negative theology. In this
“life,” that is connected, in some basic way, to sense, Maldoror is less a vigorous bliss of meta-
the generation and proliferation of forms that morphosis, and more an incessant poetry of
constitutes this traditionalist view of animality. negation. The fifth- to sixth-century mystic Dio-
This metaphysics of generosity is, in short, the a nysius the Areopagite articulates this contrast
priori of animality. between affirmative (cataphatic) and negative
At the crux of the bliss of metamorphosis and (apophatic) forms of mysticism:
its mystical itinerary there is a philosophical
commitment to a notion of life as generative, Now it seems to me that we should praise the
fecund, and proliferating of life forms. There denials quite differently than we do the asser-
is a metaphysics of generosity that determines tions. When we made assertions we began
and conditions the bliss of metamorphosis, with the first things, moved down through
intermediate terms until we reached the last
and it is this vitalist metaphysics that also
things. But now as we climb from the last
plays into the glorification of the human in
things up to the most primary we deny all
terms of its creative capacity and the “open things so that we may unhiddenly know
imagination.” In short, everything is generous, that unknowing which itself is hidden from
and it is generous for the benefit of the human. all those possessed of knowing amid beings,
If this is the case, then we can ask whether so that we may see above being that darkness
there is in Maldoror an animality that is less a concealed from all the light among
vitalistic, generous, bliss of metamorphosis, beings. (138)

92
thacker

The negation of this type of mysticism is not a only I could have defended myself with my
negation of privation or subtraction but paralysed arms – but I rather think they
instead a contradictory negation that is actually have turned into logs. Be that as it may, it
superlative, precisely because it forms the is vital to note that in them blood no longer
horizon of human knowledge. It is a negation pulses redly. Two small hedgehogs, that
grow no more, have flung to a dog – which
that involves an erasure, an effacement, a
did not decline them – the contents of my tes-
denial (apo-) of rational discourse and thinking ticles; inside the scrupulously scrubbed
(phanai). Borrowing from the apophatic tra- scrotal sac they lodged. My anus has been
dition of negation in mysticism, we might call blocked by a crab. Encouraged by my
this an apophatic animality. inertia, it guards the entrance with its
In Maldoror, apophatic animality has two pincers and cause me considerable pain!
aspects, both of which have to do with the nega- Two jellyfish crossed the seas, at once
tion of form. On the one hand there is anamor- enticed by a hope which did not prove mista-
phosis, exemplified by the many chimeras, ken. They closely inspected the two plump
monsters, and hybrids that populate Maldoror.6 portions which comprise the human rump
A passage from Canto IV illustrates the dual and, fastening on to these convex contours,
so squashed them by constant pressure that
process of building up and breaking down of
the two lumps of flesh disappeared while
form that is part of the apophaticism of the two monsters which issued from the
Maldoror: kingdom of viscosity remained, alike in
colour, form, and ferocity. Speak not of my
I am filthy. Lice gnaw me. Swine, when they
spinal column, since it is a sword. (142–43)
look at me, vomit. The scabs and sores of
leprosy have scaled my skin, which is
coated with yellowish pus. I know not river In this non-narrative section we are given a mon-
water nor the clouds’ dew. From my nape, strous version not only of the body natural but
as from a dungheap, sprouts an enormous the body politic as well. The body depicted is
toadstool with unbelliferous peduncles. at once decaying and, one senses, about to
Seated on a shapeless chunk of furniture, I crumble and fall apart – and yet it is also
have not moved a limb for four centuries. fixed, frozen, and petrified in its place. In ana-
My feet have taken root in the soil forming morphosis one sees the breakdown of part–
a sort of perennial vegetation – not yet
whole relationships, in favor of the play
quite plant-life though no longer flesh – as
between part and part, but also between whole
far as my belly, and filled with vile parasites.
My heart, however, is still beating. But how and whole. Anamorphosis can take place in
could it beat if the decay and effluvia of my space – as in the above citation – or it can take
carcass (I dare not say body) did not abun- place in time, as in the final Canto, where an
dantly feed it? In my left armpit a family of archangel is turned into a giant edible crab,
toads has taken up residence, and whenever then into a fishtail with bird wings, and so
one of them moves it tickles me. Take care forth. Anamorphosis functions on the axis of
lest one escape and come scratching with its humanity/animality; its operator is that of
mouth at the interior of your ear: it could decay and decomposition.
next penetrate into your brain. In my right In addition to anamorphosis, there is also
armpit there is a chameleon which endlessly
amorphosis, exemplified by the numerous
chases the toads so as not to die of hunger:
instances of formlessness in Maldoror. Here,
everyone has to live. But when one side com-
pletely foils the tricks of the other, they like the animality of formlessness need not have to
nothing better than to make themselves at do with actual animals. Whereas anamorphosis
home and suck the dainty grease that covers is predominantly metamorphic, amorphosis is
my sides: I am used to it. A spiteful viper predominantly morphological, dealing with the
has devoured my prick and taken its place. limits of form and formlessness. An example
This villain made a eunuch of me. Oh! If is given in Canto V of Maldoror, which,

93
apophatic animality

interestingly, becomes a meditation on the amorphosis form is pushed to its limit, becom-
poetics of the text itself: ing either the absence of all form (the evacuation
of all form) or absolute form (the devouring of
Let not the reader lose his temper with me if
all possible form). In Maldoror, these instances
my prose has not the felicity to please him.
You maintain my ideas are at least singular. of formlessness can exist within a single body (as
What you say, respectable man, is the in the morphologies of the Maldoror character
truth, but a half-truth. And what an abun- as a pack of dogs and then a miasma), or it
dant source of errors and misapprehensions can exist pervasively throughout multiple
every half-truth is! Flights of starlings have bodies (e.g. flocks of birds, a horde of rats, a
a way of flying which is theirs alone and swarm of flying squids). Amorphosis functions
seems governed by uniform and regular along the axis of humanity/divinity; its operator
tactics as a disciplined regiment would be, is that of dissipation and dissolution.
obeying a single leader’s voice with precision. Maldoror is an anomalous text replete with
The starlings obey the voice of instinct, and
animals of all kinds. It is also a text that is
their instinct leads them to bunch into the
equally concerned with animality, an animality
centre of the squad, while the speed of their
flight bears them constantly beyond it; so not reducible to animals, an assertion made in
that this multitude of birds thus united by the text’s frequent transgression of both natura-
a common tendency towards the same mag- listic and narrative form. But the question is
netic point, unceasingly coming and going, whether a text like Maldoror is about the pro-
circulating and crisscrossing in all directions, duction of forms or the loss of form, whether
forms a sort of highly agitated whirlpool the text points to an animality that is driven
whose whole mass, without following a fixed by a vitalist generosity of life or by an apophatic
course seems to have a general wheeling dissipation of life.
movement round itself resulting from the Hence we have two variants on a theme, a
particular circulatory motions appropriate
theme concerning the intersection of animality
to each of its parts, and whose centre, perpe-
and spirituality. On the one hand we have the
tually tending to expand but continually
compressed, pushed back by the contrary bliss of metamorphosis. This relies on a philoso-
stress of the surrounding lines bearing upon phical premise, in which a metaphysics of vital-
it, is constantly denser than any of these ist generosity provides the backdrop for a
lines, which are themselves the denser the fecund, proliferating, creation of life forms – a
nearer they are to the centre. Despite this bliss of metamorphosis that is ultimately recog-
strange way of swirling, the starlings cleave nized to be as spiritual as it is animal. With the
through the ambient air at no less rare a bliss of metamorphosis, we have both a lateral
speed and each second make precious, animality and vertical humanity, the former
appreciable headway towards the end of by virtue of the many life forms presented in
their hardships and the goal of their pilgrim-
the text, which reach their highest pitch in a
age. Likewise, reader, pay no attention to the
humanized capacity for poiesis. For the bliss
bizarre way in which I sing each of these
stanzas. (159–60) of metamorphosis, animality is immediate and
affirmative of life.
Unlike other instances of animality in Mal- By contrast, we have presented another vari-
doror, with their incessant biological admixtures ation, which highlights the unavoidable anti-
and hybrids, here we have a sustained passage humanism that energetically drives Maldoror’s
on a single phenomenon, that of swarming be- litany of assaults against both God and man.
havior that is at once tightly organized and yet In this view, Maldoror is a text that rails
formless and chaotic. It is also a passage that against the human – and also against “life”
is itself borrowed from the Encyclopédie d’his- (insofar as life is the privileged designation
toire naturelle, making the very act of reading made by humans on behalf of other beings).
the text ambiguous in its conflation of scientific While Lautréamont takes up the Aristotelian
description and figurative simile.7 In fascination with life forms, he is also positioned

94
thacker

against Aristotle on the need for a life-principle Maldoror is a tragic type of poetry because it
and the metaphysical necessity of its ability to asserts that there is too much form in the world.
cause form to take shape. With Lautréamont, This is because there is too much life (and there
we move from the well-formed life (the life of, is no form without life). Maldoror attempts an
say, biological classification), through the impossible task, which is to actively and conti-
form-ing life (the metaphysics of generosity, nually un-form all form, above all that most
the bliss of metamorphosis), to a more suspect tiring of forms, the human form. In spite of
and shadowy region, a gothic mode where its many invectives against God, and in spite
form and forming is inseparable from de- of its many absurdist descriptions of animals,
forming and un-forming. If it is still “mystical,” the challenge posed by Maldoror is not a chal-
it is in this apophatic register, summarized in lenge against religion or science. The real chal-
Alain Paris’ study: lenge posed by Maldoror is this: what is the
most adequate form of the unhuman? And yet
Lautréamont deplores the human form of
Maldoror can only accomplish this via some
conscience, which is duality and conscious-
form; hence its poetics of gothic misanthropy
ness of this duality – that is to say, the con-
sciousness of the separation of the self and must take on the abandoned shell or the
the world, and of the self with itself […] carcass of existing forms, both of literature
For Lautréamont, God frequently represents and of life.
this alterity that both founds consciousness
and the tearing of consciousness from itself
[…] It is in this way that one must under- coda: non-literature and non-life
stand the hatred of God, invoked from the
beginning of Maldoror, and not in the tra- Near the end of his study, Bachelard asks how
ditional sense of the problem of good and a text such as Maldoror might impact not only
evil […] There is a mysticism of hatred in literature or poetry but the entire field of
Lautréamont. Hatred is a propaedeutic of poetics itself. It leads him to coin a somewhat
the divine and that which is beyond the cumbersome yet evocative term, “non-
human. (115–16; translation mine) Lautréamontism”:
In Bachelard’s reading, the animality of Mal- Ducasse’s metamorphoses have had the
doror lies in the “bliss of metamorphosis,” a advantage of un-anchoring a type of poetry
concept of animality that is a conjunction of submerged in the job of describing. In my
the immediacy of life with a technics of form. opinion we must now take advantage of a
In his evocations of the “open imagination,” life given over to the metamorphosing
Bachelard therefore intimates a reading of powers in order to move on to a sort of
Maldoror as a heroic type of poetry, an non-Lautréamontism that will spill out of
example of the modernist imperative to discover Maldoror in all directions. I shall continue
to use the term “non-Lautréamontism”
the new.
while giving it the same function as that
However, this tends to downplay the central
non-Euclidianism which can generalize Eucli-
importance of the gothic in Maldoror, both in dean geometry. (90)
its style and in its literary context. In this
gothic mode, life exists only to the extent that Bachelard’s evocation of a non-Lautréamontism
it constantly ceases to exist; the prodigality of looks forward to the “non-philosophy” of Fran-
forms only exists in so far as they are decaying, çois Laruelle, who also makes the comparison
decomposing, or disintegrating. In the gothic to non-Euclidian geometry. For Laruelle, non-
mode, animality is a form of life that grows by philosophy is neither anti-philosophy nor meta-
decaying, that is built in ruins, and that is philosophy. It takes philosophy as its raw
prodigious in its nothingness. In short, material, illuminating the “philosophical
Maldoror is less a heroic and more a tragic decision” that structures the separation of phil-
type of poetry. osophy from theology, mathematics, or poetry,

95
apophatic animality

and that also internally distinguishes fundamen- It would seem that any non-Lautréamontism
tal philosophy (metaphysics and ontology) from or non-literature immediately raises the possi-
regional philosophy (the philosophy of religion, bility of a non-life, a life that cannot be lived,
political philosophy, the philosophy of science). or, better yet, the “lived-without-life.”8 Bache-
This philosophical decision is philosophy’s lard hints at this: “Maldoror can be taken as a
necessary self-positing and the basis of its expla- pretext for understanding what a work would
natory power. As Laruelle asserts, “philosophy is be if it were somehow to tear away from ordin-
regulated in accordance with a principle higher ary existence and welcome that other life
than that of Reason: the Principle of sufficient which must be designated by a contradictory
philosophy. The latter expresses philosophy’s neologism as an unlivable life” (55). Like
absolute autonomy, its essence as self-positing/ Deleuze, Bachelard also argues for a non-
donating/naming/deciding/grounding” (Lar- representational notion of literature, a notion
uelle 139). A non-philosophy would examine of literature that is itself a manifestation of
those aspects of philosophy that philosophy something immanent to both literature and
itself cannot examine, without its becoming life. But this also pulls both thinkers towards
something else (a logic, a science, a poetics). a metaphysics of generosity, a vitalist commit-
If we interpret Bachelard’s proposal for a ment to dynamic change and constant
non-Lautréamontism or a non-literature in this becoming.
way then the question would be whether Mal- Be that as it may, this relationship between
doror is a work of non-literature, in the sense literature and life is only given testament
that it complicates a poetics of balanced form within the exclusive provenance of humanity.
and content, a literature of representation and To whom is literature and its relation to life
hermeneutic depth. This returns us to our directed, if not to the specifically human life
opening comments about animality in Maldoror that is able to qualify both life and literature?
– the animality in the text and the text as ani- This is one of the central challenges put forth
mality. Maldoror is non-literature because in by Maldoror. The strange proposition of a
every phrase it questions the “literary decision” non-literature, a literature not intended for
that literature be at once apart from and yet humans, would seem also to necessitate a non-
engaged in that which it depicts. Maldoror life, or a life that is neither simply human
takes aim at the human per se, but also at the life-experience nor that of the life sciences. Mal-
cultural concept of the human as a literary crea- doror is in every way a text poised against the
ture, a form of life given over to reflection, rep- human, even in terms of its literary form:
resentation, and the production of meaning.
But as Gilles Deleuze reminds us, literature is Here in fact is a work born not from the
indelibly linked to life. However, this need not observation of others but not exactly from
be in the usual sense, in which literature rep- the observation of oneself either. Before
resents life, as form for matter. As Deleuze being observed it was created. It has no
asserts, “[t]o write is certainly not to impose a goal yet is an action. It has no plan yet is
coherent. Its language is not the expression
form (of expression) on the matter of lived
of a previous thought. It is the expression
experience” (225). This is because literature
of a psychic force that has suddenly become
not only transforms, but is transformed as a language. In short it is instant language.
well: “Literature rather moves in the direction (Bachelard 55)
of the ill-formed or the incomplete […] It is a
passage of Life that traverses both the livable But Bachelard’s study is ultimately compro-
and the lived” (ibid.). If this is the case, if litera- mised by its “heroic” turn towards the human.
ture and life are connected not as form to matter Not only does Bachelard recuperate animality
but as mutually deforming and unforming within a higher humanity (the “open imagin-
activities, then what is the corollary for a ation” with all of the animality at its disposal)
“non-Lautréamontism” or a “non-literature”? but nearly all of Bachelard’s discussion on

96
thacker

animality and the “bliss of metamorphosis” 5 Lautréamont is not the first to suggest this inter-
centers on the almost instinctual immediacy of section – arguably it can be found in early modern
animality – aggression, action, movement, cre- bestiaries and teratologies, where the language of
ation, spontaneity, and so on. For Bachelard, science and fable intermingle. More importantly,
animality is equivalent to immediacy. What is it is a point taken up in the contemporary theory,
in Deleuze and Guattari’s discussion of animality
more, Bachelard emphasizes the fact that Mal-
in Kafka, and in Akira Lippit’s notion of “animeta-
doror seems to itself – as a text – be equivalent phor,” developed in his book Electric Animal.
to this immediacy, as if the text itself spon-
taneously preceded its own conceptualization, 6 Although the term anamorphosis has a double
planning, and writing. Constantly changing, meaning – in art history to describe a visual illusion,
continually forming hybrids, incessantly and in biology to describe the development of
embryonic life forms – I am using the term to
pouring forth pages and pages of “the bliss of
describe a breaking-down of form and the
metamorphosis,” Maldoror seems to have forming capacity. Thus ana-morphosis is, in this
always existed, prior to any and all forms of case, a literal layering of negative form (ana-
mediation. The animality of Maldoror puts “back,” “reversion,” “again”) on top of existing
forth what is really a philosophical challenge – form (morphē, “shape,” “form”).
it is an immediacy that challenges all philosophi-
7 The appropriation of this passage is pointed out
cal decision, any metaphysical claim that would
in a still-useful 1952 article by Maurice Viroux,
begin by, for instance, dividing being from non- “Lautréamont et le Dr. Chenu” (published in the
being, thought from world, the living from the Mercure de France), where Viroux traces it to an
non-living, life from death. Everything is poss- almost verbatim passage in the volume Oiseaux of
ible in Maldoror, all hybrids are permitted, all Chenu’s Encyclopédie.
forms only exist to be deformed and reformed.
8 I borrow this phrase, with slight changes, from
Teratology in fact becomes the norm, with its
Laruelle. In his book Mystique non-philosophique à
propensity for the aggressive, spontaneous cre- l’usage des contemporains, Laruelle discusses the
ation of novel forms. In this sense Maldoror immanent type of mysticism represented in the
also poses a challenge to the prin- works of Eckhart, described as a “Vécu-sans-Vie”
ciple of sufficient reason, a moral (Lived-without-Life).
and theological principle that the
world is well formed, and that
the form of the world is necess-
ary to the world.

bibliography
notes Aristotle. On the Soul/Parva Naturalia/On Breath.
Trans. W.S. Hett. Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP/
1 The review was published in La Jeunesse 5 (Sept.
Loeb Classical Library, 2000. Print.
1868), and is reprinted in Maldoror: The Complete
Works of the Comte de Lautréamont. Artaud, Antonin. “Letter on Lautréamont.” Artaud
Anthology. San Francisco: City Lights, 1965. 123–27.
2 From a letter to Poulet-Malassis, 23 Oct. 1869,
Print.
reprinted in Maldoror: The Complete Works of the
Comte de Lautréamont. Bachelard, Gaston. Lautréamont. 1939. Trans.
James Hillman and Robert S. Dupree. Dallas:
3 This is also the approach adopted by works
Dallas Institute, 1986. Print.
associated with the journal Tel Quel, the most
notable example of which is Julia Kristeva’s Revolu- de Jonge, Alex. Nightmare Culture: Lautréamont and
tion in Poetic Language. “Les Chants de Maldoror.” New York: St. Martin’s,
1973. Print.
4 Bachelard also goes on to contrast Maldoror to
Kafka’s “Metamorphosis,” Kipling’s The Jungle Deleuze, Gilles. “Literature and Life.” Trans. Daniel
Book, and Wells’s The Island of Dr. Moreau. Smith. Critical Inquiry 23.2 (1997): 225–30. Print.

97
apophatic animality

Dionysius the Areopagite. Pseudo-Dionysius: The


Complete Works. Trans. Paul Rorem. New York:
Paulist, 1988. Print.
Durand-Dessert, Liliane. La Guerre Sainte:
Lautréamont et Isidore Ducasse. Nancy: Presses
Universitaires de Nancy, 1991. Print.
Laruelle, François. “A Summary of Non-philos-
ophy.” Trans. Ray Brassier. Pli: The Warwick
Journal of Philosophy 8 (1999): 138–48. Print.
Lautréamont, Comte de. Maldoror: The Complete
Works of the Comte de Lautréamont. Trans. Alexis
Lykiard. Cambridge: Exact Change, 1994. Print.
Nesselroth, Peter. Lautréamont’s Imagery: A Stylistic
Approach. Paris: Droz, 1969. Print.
Paris, Alain. “Le Bestiare des Chants de Maldoror.”
Quatre Lectures de Lautréamont. Paris: Nizet, 1972.
83–143. Print.
Praz, Mario. The Romantic Agony. 1933. Trans.
Angus Davidson. New York: Meridian, 1963. Print.

Eugene Thacker
School of Media Studies
The New School
66 West 12th Street
New York, NY 10011
USA
E-mail: thackere@newschool.edu
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

allison hunter

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010099-8 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783444

99
hunter

100
hunter

101
hunter

102
hunter

103
hunter

104
hunter

105
hunter

images
1. Allison Hunter, “Untitled (dragonfly),”
2009, 33 × 50 inches, digital c-print.
2. Allison Hunter, “Untitled #1 (from the
Honeycomb series),” 2011, 30 × 30
inches, digital c-print.
3. Allison Hunter, “Untitled #2 (from the
Honeycomb series),” 2011, 30 × 30
inches, digital c-print.
4. Allison Hunter, “Untitled #3 (from the
Honeycomb series),” 2011, 30 × 30
inches, digital c-print.
5. Allison Hunter, “Untitled #4 (from the
Honeycomb series),” 2011,
30 × 30 inches, digital c-
print.
6. Allison Hunter, “Untitled
#5 (from the Honeycomb
series),” 2011, 30 × 30
inches, digital c-print.

Allison Hunter
Humanities Artist in Residence
Rice University
Department of Visual and Dramatic Arts
6100 Main Street
Houston, TX 77005
USA
E-mail: amh10@rice.edu
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

I will end with an emphasis on the invisible,


but start with disappearance. The two ends
connect in this text, which concerns the inter-
twining of the ecological with the aesthetic;
not an aesthetics of nature, or ecology, or even
ecocrisis, but how such are themselves percepti-
ble through an intertwining with technological
epistemologies. Indeed, this deals with
capacities of bodies stretched across various
ecologies in the manner Guattari talked about,
and what recent techno-aesthetic theory con- jussi parikka
cerning sensation has been arguing (Parisi). In
short, what such a stance is saying is that the
capacities of human and animal bodies cannot INSECTS AND
be detached from considerations of their techno-
logical framings, which in this text is a question CANARIES
of ecology – a feedback loop of various levels
and scales. In this sense, this text focuses on
medianatures and
how to think the visual culture of disappearance aesthetics of the invisible
– more closely, disappearance of animals.
Hence, by way of a preface, let’s start with
Ernst Jünger’s novel The Glass Bees from emphasized the decisive role that war plays in
1957 – a science fiction story of an automata pro- technological modernity, and the idea of “total
ducer and industrialist Zapparoni and his minia- mobilization” as a form of tuning of the national
ture robotics that, according to Bruce Sterling’s economies, visual culture and personal readi-
introduction to the book, resemble more the ness for war, then what kind of alternative
high-tech creatures of recent years of MIT “master narrative” can we find in this slightly
design laboratories than the clunky robotics of different kind of Jünger novel that focuses on
typical 1950s science fiction. Indeed, Sterling’s microdesign of robotic worlds through
characterization echoes the German media the- animals? This addresses a different kind of
orist Friedrich Kittler, when the former writes readiness, and critique of progress, and still an
of The Glass Bees and Jünger of how he “under- intertwining of animal energies with technology.
stands that technology is pursued not to acceler- Without going into a fully fledged explication
ate progress but to intensify power” (x). If of the narrative – and the protagonist Captain
Jünger’s earlier novel The Storm of Steel Richard’s work application and introduction to
became a key reference point for a certain Zapparoni’s automata factory of entertainment
brand of (German) media theory that devices – we get a good sense of the slightly

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010107-13 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783445

107
insects and canaries

different emphasis than in Storm of Steel. ruthlessly sucked out the flowers and rav-
Through Captain Richard’s personal memories ished them. Wherever they crowded out the
and meditations of war – and the coming high- old colonies, a bad harvest, a failure of
tech war – which are familiar Jünger themes, crops, and ultimately a desert were bound
The Glass Bees addresses animal-like automata to follow. After a series of extensive raids,
there would no longer be flowers or honey,
and the immersive entertainment worlds of such
and the true bees would become extinct in
devices that are becoming embedded as part of the way of whales and horses. (Jünger 135)
everyday life. The novel, however, becomes an
observation of obsolescence – not only in the Extinction, replacement, disappearance, inno-
sense that we think of media device obsoles- vation coupled to obsolescence are themes that
cence in the culture of the “new” media but stand out from Jünger’s novel, and act also as
also replacement of another sort; for the prota- a trailer to this paper.
gonist, this observation becomes clear through Jünger’s science fiction world touches on this
his own personal history of war: displacing of the animal as part of the logic of
automation and relates to what I have called
Of course, differences existed between mili- “insect media”: the non-human qualities and
tary service under Henry IV, Louis XIII, or models for technology that animal worlds have
Louis XIV, but one always served on horse-
offered from nineteenth-century entomological
back. Today the magnificent creatures were
discourse to more recent software culture
doomed. They had disappeared from the
fields and streets, from the villages and (Parikka, Insect Media). In addition, The Glass
towns, and for years they had not been seen Bees nods towards the double-bind of modernity
in combat. Everywhere they had been in terms of technological obsolescence: the
replaced by automatons. (Jünger 29) paradox of technological society being that it
not only produces technology but also gets rid
The glass bees are one form of such displace- of it at an increasing pace, as well as getting rid
ment, replacement and introduction of auto- of and modulating the organic as part of that
mation. Described as a mix of a hive and “an process. It also produces obsolescence and non-
automatic telephone exchange,” Zapparoni’s use. In such a context of animals and technology,
miniature bee workers represent not only a new and insect media, we can refer to this as an anti-
form of automatized pseudo-animal labour but McLuhan take on media history where technology
a whole system of organization – like a switch- is not modelled on the human being but has a
board structure – which automates the carrying more complex entanglement with a variety of
of nectar to the hive. As such, as automated inde- animal bodies and nature. The approach might
pendent robots they fulfil Zapparoni’s dream of differ slightly from the emphasis that Friedrich
wireless communication networks of semi-auton- Kittler suggested in his own anti-McLuhan remin-
omous agents (hence, no wonder that Christoph der that before we are able to think media as
Rosol included a reference to Jünger’s novel in extensions of man they themselves include a
his media archaeology of the RFID), but also, range of other, very non-human processes
for the worried observer, Captain Richard anyway. Into this mix I want to throw in
summons the extinction of the organic bee – animals and the idea of how animal bodies are
work and love, in a much-too-perfect balance: themselves mediatic, and to be approached as aes-
thetic and material-epistemological figures in
Bees are not just workers in a honey factory.
order to understand bodies stretched across
Ignoring their self-sufficiency for a moment,
their work – far beyond its tangible utility various differing ecologies.
– plays an important part in the cosmic Indeed, we can claim that there is a wider
plan. As messengers of love, their duty is to mobilization of animals and natural resources
pollinate, to fertilize the flowers. But Zappar- as part of technological modernity and its
oni’s glass collectives, as far as I could see, forms of perception, related to political

108
parikka

economy of media (for instance, electronic waste through their archaeologies as scientific
as one central form of pollution) as well. Also measurement devices (see Ernst). The emerging
emblematic of the discourse of the posthuman, scientific epistemology concerning animal life
we are increasingly forced to think of worlds was feeding into aesthetics in the wider media
without the human – both for ethico-aesthetic and popular culture sense; the emerging media
and for empirical reasons. Guattari has been technologies such as screen media were instru-
the thinker perhaps most contributing to the mental both as producers and mediators of the
double notion of ethics combined essentially animal as a specific scientific question.
with new aesthetic paradigms, and the empirical Hence, this intertwining of animals and tech-
refers here to a possible future that, according to nology is not only metaphorical. Instead, the
various scientific modelizations, might be true; a disappearance of the animal is emblematic,
world without human life, and various forms of measuring impacts and affects of emergence of
animal life, if our climate change predictions are technicality and, in this case, visibility and
accurate (see Chun). invisibility. Indeed, in various contemporary
Without going into the detail of the various visual and scientific practices, the animal is
entanglements in which simulations concerning not only an object of concern but is itself a
the future of climate change are impacting on surface of registration, storage media and a
the epistemology of the crisis, we can observe signal of the processes concerning pollution
a parallel history concerning technology and and waste. We literally seem to learn through
animals. One way to make sense of this is to the “case studies” of animals, whether in news
take up Akira Mizuta Lippit’s argument con- media (as the case of bumblebee disappearance,
cerning modernity as intertwining trajectories to which we will return below), scientific data
of animals and technology – where the gradual (the discourse of the sixth mass extinction of
emergence of technical media during the nine- biodiversity) or other media, including fiction
teenth century was paralleled by a specific atti- (Coupland) and documentaries (Vanishing of
tude (and practices) concerning animals. The the Bees, 2009).
disappearance of animals from urban cultures Hence, in order for us to account for this idea
of technical media was paralleled by the appear- of “animal media” as an implicit ethico-aesthetic
ance of animals in various discourses, from and epistemological figure, we need to address
media (early cinematic discourses being a good the entanglement of technical media, animal
example) to modern subjectivity (e.g., psycho- bodies, and discourses of ecological crisis and
analysis). Disney’s mice can be seen as only waste. Hence the use of the title “insects and
part of the technological eradication of rodents canaries” refers to the use of (canary) birds in
from urbanity, and the appearance of various mining practices as well as the gas warfare of
animals in scientific films, literature discourses, the First World War to detect the presence of
and animations is part of various measures to dangerous air pollution. Hence, it was indeed
control the animal as a production force – and not only in mines but also in trench warfare
disturbance. The new regimes of media – where such ideas were used to detect the
which were to a large extent used as tools for impending danger to human lungs as well. In
scientific measurement such as chronophotogra- an early test, George A. Burrell of the United
phy and the various measuring instruments of States Bureau of Mines conducted tests on
physiology and experimental psychology labs – various animals, including himself, exposed to
were ones that tapped into the speed and slow- carbon monoxide. It took a minute for the can-
ness of animal bodies. Here, we should pay aries to start asphyxiating, eleven minutes for
attention to a genealogical understanding of pigeons, twenty minutes for himself, while
media that does not start from a current chickens took no notice (Harrington 259). The
bit-too-easy conflation of “media” with enter- canary became metaphoric as a way to transpose
tainment media, but acknowledges that our invisible, deadly toxins, which in this case I
mediatic devices should be approached transpose to another layer: to investigate

109
insects and canaries

notions of disappearance, obsolescence, the eco- in such a mobilization of animal bodies; that
logical crisis and animal organisms in relation to they embody and express a variety of temporal-
technological epistemologies. In this case, ities in which their material potentials are being
animals such as bees are early-warning systems consumed. Indeed, what is discussed in terms of
(with a nod towards the earlier use of the term technological obsolescence is a matter of forces
in media theory by Marshall McLuhan), epis- of production and consumption more widely
temological and aesthetic figures of a different too: I am referring here to the exhaustion of
kind that work as forms of animal aesthetics. energies of living matter, from people (labour)
Besides the concept there is another link too: to animals and natural resources. Much of this
the development of chemicals for gas warfare logic was well summarized in the idea of
led to a massive redeployment of such scientific planned obsolescence introduced in the midst
data and resources to pesticide production. of the Great Depression of the 1920s and
This, for its part, has been suspected as one 1930s: that products and devices should be
key cause of the bee colony disorders. legally declared “dead” after a certain period
Obviously we have had a fair number of of use, and hence be replaced through legal
theoretical accounts that establish links force. This did not make it onto the statute
between technical media culture and animal books but, as we know, it did as part of the
energies and intensities from cybernetics to mode of production of devices and desires of
Donna Haraway, to such materialist feminists capitalist consumer culture (Hertz and
as Rosi Braidotti and Elizabeth Grosz. The Parikka). And yet we need to establish the
various perspectives have paved the way for link between technology and where technologi-
the so-called wave of “new materialist” cal modes of production and consumption
thought.1 A thorough discussion of the various draw their resources from, and mobilize as
meanings of new materialism remains outside part of the drive for obsolescence, which
the scope of this text. Instead, I want to flag indeed, as we should realize, is a matter of obso-
the usefulness of such projects that aim to lescence of animals too.
think the entwining materiality of temporal
bodies – of animal and human – as a question
of the ethico-aesthetic. Indeed, of the recent dis-
II
cussions I believe it is Braidotti who has come Technology is one part of the wider story con-
closest to what I want to argue – that the cerning urbanization and modernization, which
animal energies, intensities, and productive play their role in what has been speculated
forces, which are in no way limited to the during recent years as the new mass extinction
human, are actually the motor, the energy of animal species, including insects. Insects
source, for so much of technological modernity are in this complex ecological pattern – and
and capitalism. Of course, this energetic per- ecological in the manner that includes various
spective that aims to develop a trans-species spheres from technology to political economy
ethics, outside an anthropocentric prejudice, is to nature as well as the ecology of subjectifica-
one that also accounts for what it most often tion in the manner that Fe´lix Guattari argued
means to mobilize animals as part of technologi- – in a crucial role because of their centrality
cal capitalism. Animals are living matter – and for pollination, decomposition and soil proces-
“material for scientific experiments. They are sing (Pickrell). The process of “co-extinction”
manipulated, mistreated, tortured and geneti- that follows from the loss of one species,
cally recombined in ways that are productive piling up as a chain of extinctions, is character-
for our bio-technological agriculture, the cos- istic of such ecological relations that define
metics industry, drugs and pharmaceutical a milieu approach to the world: no thing
industries, and other sectors of the economy” without another, i.e., relations define entities,
(Braidotti 98). Related to this, we are forced to co-evolution is shadowed by co-extinction, and
observe the necessary entropic quality inherent such processes of co-being and becoming

110
parikka

extend much outside the organic. Recent years tied together with aesthetics as a way to think
of Deleuzian-inspired theory of biopolitics and what could be called transversal subjectivities
art has picked up on Lynn Margulis’s idea of – the shared milieus of articulation for
symbiotic co-evolution as well as Bateson’s humans and non-humans, and what more
ecology (through Guattari), and now we can recently philosophers such as Braidotti have
extend such ideas of milieu-bound becomings developed into new forms of (Spinozian) ethics
to a grim side of “co-extinction” as well, which for an age of political economy and technologies
also addresses the ontogenetic and material of bios/zoë – life. To this already complex mix
sides of change. Indeed, if relations compose of various ecologies we can add media ecology
each other (Fuller, Media Ecologies 95), they as one specific field of practices, energies, epis-
might as well unfold, disperse, and recompose temologies and articulations of the ethico-aes-
in some other form. This approach also recog- thetic (Fuller, Media Ecologies). Through a
nizes the longer genealogy of ecological think- media ecological focus we are able to investigate
ing, pre-dating Guattari. For instance, Gregory how media technological energies contribute to
Bateson’s remarks in “Pathologies of Epistem- the patterns of replacement, displacement and
ology” are right to the point in their acknowl- disappearance of animal energies, and hence
edgement of how the ecological mode of hopefully avoid too-narrow “epistemological
questioning has opened a broader field of con- errors” (Bateson) in our investigation of the
sideration of what matters in terms of discourse aesthetico-epistemologies of disappearance.
of nature; from a hierarchical biological focus on Indeed, one of the characteristic features of
family lineages, species, sub-species down to “animal extinction” is the question of visibility.
individuals, the ecological as argued by Besides the obvious point about mediation in
Bateson is where we stop for a moment to con- popular culture narratives, such doomsday scen-
sider what exactly is the “unit of selection” (if arios are, of course, embedded in the larger
you want to use Darwinian vocabulary): this question of measurement, validation, compari-
makes us think of the couplings of genes with son and presentation of scientific facts so that
organisms, organisms in environments, ecosys- the radical complexity of such intertwining
tems and if we want to consistently continue, becomes understandable. This also refers to
and, as Guattari and the more recent wave of how we constantly discover new species, which
media ecology have done, we need to account is one part in the contemporary biology of
for a whole host of “extra-biological” ecologies species and populations (Heise, “Lost Dogs”),
in order to avoid the epistemological error of and emphasizes that despite the fact that it is
“choosing the wrong unit” (Bateson 459) most probably true that we are in a catastrophic
where we start our epistemological inquiry. situation concerning animal and natural life, we
Guattari argued in the 1980s that to under- need more complex ways to understand this
stand such forms of milieu, or ecology-bound situation as relational. Instead of a closed con-
thought, the only real option for the green tainer model of ecology we need to account for
movement is to extend its concept of nature natures that are more than objects for measur-
and animals to include a variety of other ing visualization, and think of more ontogenetic
spheres. Indeed, as a form of mixed semiotics, epistemologies – ecologies as constant creative
he was insisting on methodologies that take processes that are entangled with various scien-
into account the variety of ecologies and pro- tific practices of knowledge production across
cesses that contribute to processes of subjectifi- species and populations. As Ursula Heise in
cation, signification and a-signification. Guattari her “Unnatural Ecologies” article reminds us,
proposed three ecologies inclusive also of the the conceptualizations of nature and media
psyche and the social with their particular ecology work both ways, changing perceptions
“waste” and “pollution.” What still makes and aesthetics of understanding of nature and
Guattari’s idea refreshing is how it offers a technology. Indeed, one crucial question that
complex material epistemology, completely in a way echoes Lippit’s point mentioned

111
insects and canaries

above is how the perception of the ecological documented many insect and other species, we
crisis since the 1960s has been paralleled by are faced with the challenge of a possible mass
increasing media theoretical talk of media extinction underway, but which is difficult to
ecology (for instance Neil Postman), as if turn into an epistemology with, let’s say,
hinting that the disappearance of the natural policy impact. When dealing with populations
ecology has its counterpart in technological con- and species, biologists are faced again with
ceptualizations. In any case, we are safe to say similar problems of data collection from empiri-
that the two are very much intertwined, and cal and historical sources, and translating that
perhaps never were detached in the first place. into modes of perception that are convincing
In her usual perceptive manner, Wendy Hui from an aesthetic and epistemological point of
Kyong Chun argues that the whole epistem- view. Again, to emphasize, aesthetics refers
ology concerning scientific simulation is itself here not to ornamentality – or even science com-
a question of how we relate to data, software munication – when talking of visual communi-
and programming which involves a curious cation of scientific facts, but to a more
relation to the future: climate predictions are fundamental role that perception plays in all
not untrue because they are extrapolated from this.
a massive amount of data that speculates a poss- A widely media-reported environmental issue
ible future, and allows us a possibility to act on of recent years has been the mysterious bumble-
that one particular data epistemology – or even bee extinctions especially, in the United States
aesthetico-epistemology, as it involves various but also worldwide – reported probably
forms of visualization and aesthetics too as because not only of its catastrophic implications
part of its software-embedded knowledge but the cuteness of the subject topic. In the
production.2 same category of cuteness as pandas, puppies,
But mass extinction is not just something penguins and dolphins, and hence suitable for
directly observable, and includes the difficulty gentle discourses concerning preservation,
of detection (Heise, “Lost Dogs”; see also Pick- bees have been addressed as one of the most
rell). The massive scale of climate change that recent victims of climate change. What started
involves attempts to offer a convincing epistem- as a mysterious wave of mass deaths of anything
ology by tying up pasts (data collected over up to 60–70 per cent of the bee population in
decades) with futures (patterning data to offer certain parts of the United States spread to
a premediated scenario) is paralleled by the pro- become a worldwide phenomenon, the cause of
blems of detection that biologists have to face. which remains a mystery. Whereas estimates
This relates to the status of sub-disciplines in were of an apocalyptic scale for the bees them-
biology. Of these, molecular genetics enjoys a selves – that at this pace bumblebee species
prominent role in defining what a species is, would be wiped out in a few years’ time (“Bum-
and the re-emergence of taxonomy, as Heise blebees Could Face Extinction”) – this was
(“Lost Dogs” 55) notes. In short, we are faced registered as apocalyptic on another level too:
with questions not just of going out there and no bees, no pollination; no pollination, no
observing a situation but also having first to crops; no crops, no human beings.
address how we in the first case talk about Despite media hype tailing off in recent
animals, species, populations and extinction. years, in 2010 the United Nations Environment
This question ranges from disciplinary knowl- Programme released an alarming report entitled
edge and practices to a wider set of narratives, Global Honey Bee Colony Disorders and Other
technology and interests of knowledge (ibid.): Threats to Insect Pollinators that mapped the
a technologically embedded material episteme grim picture:
that is itself entangled (in Karen Barad’s way
of using the term to avoid a Kantian correlation- Current evidence demonstrates that a sixth
ism) with the objects of knowledge it produces. major extinction of biological diversity
In a situation in which we still have not even event is underway. The Earth is losing

112
parikka

between one and ten percent of biodiversity Such crises participate in a longer cultural
per decade, mostly due to habitat loss, pest history of narrativization of nature vs.
invasion, pollution, over-harvesting and humans/modernization (Heise, “Lost Dogs”),
disease. (1) but what I want to focus on is the entanglement
The data collated in the report not only regis- with technical media, and, as promised, the
tered a sudden slump in the honey-producing relation to aesthetics. In other words, a trans-
colony numbers but also, and perhaps more species ethics also needs to be a transmaterial
worryingly, a steady decline over a longer ethics, which takes into account technologies,
period. Indeed, what such diagrammatizations material epistemologies, scientific practices, aes-
have to deal with, in terms of the aesthetico-epis- thetic discourses concerning the entanglement
temological modes of perception, is to arrange of technical media and animals, etc. This does
time-scales; the past ten years of public dis- not always refer only to the established list of
course have produced and fed on narratives of what we count as “media” but also such scienti-
the catastrophe of the sudden decline in bee fic technologies as DNA fingerprinting too; in
populations, but the narrativization of a longer this curious case of the bees, such techniques
decline is still something that is not so easily were used to map information concerning colo-
or willingly picked up. Indeed, as Heise notes nies and their relations, and the suggested
of various earlier forms of media ecological the- causes most often took into account pollution
oretization, the notion of environment used in and other modernization-related effects,
media theory implied “a spatial perception or showing the further entanglement of the bee
experience” (“Unnatural Ecologies” 165). And question in the wider technological modernity.
yet, with the contemporary discourses and epis- This is where I want to nod towards the title
temological practices of climates, extinction and of the text again, namely “insects and canaries.”
relations between animals and technology, we The use of pesticides evinces the co-evolving
are increasingly faced with the question of how history of war and control of nature, as
to think/visualize/narrativize time in terms of Russell (2) argues: the entanglement of
non-human scales. Indeed, to quote Heise: techno-scientific development as well as organiz-
ational/industry arrangements between military
Questions of scale also matter for the stories and business, supporting the mobilization of
we tell about biodiversity in other ways. early gas warfare into insect pesticides, and
Human perception and cultural understand- back to human warfare. Identification of the
ing of species loss normally focus on the use of certain pesticides as contributing to the
orders of magnitude closest to us, whereas
recent bee colony disorders is one of the more
processes at other scales often do not make
their way into the public consciousness.
convincing causes, and also presents this
(“Lost Dogs 57) curious link back to discourses of ecocrisis –
across histories of war, animals, and techno-
This is where anthropocentric perspectives scientific developments.
fail to grasp the mixed ecological milieu, As to the various other causes suggested, one
across species, and humans and non-humans – often mentioned but that still lacks data has to
and a more transversal ethics of perception is do with electromagnetic radiation and the tech-
needed (Braidotti). One hundred crop species nical communication sphere of such devices. It’s
provide 90 per cent of human food worldwide. not just that bees are part of media history, but
Of these one hundred, seventy-one are bee polli- also that they are themselves mediatic. Their
nated, showing the curious way in which our body incorporates a crystal that contains lead,
survival is very much tied together with the and hence is receptive to electromagnetic com-
bees. Such narratives are of great use in rescal- munications – the regime of communications
ing issues of massive spatial and temporal that works through Hertzian vibrations. High-
scales to make sense, and hence create certain frequency mobile communications, including,
aesthetics of such a crisis too. for instance, RFID (Radio Frequency

113
insects and canaries

Identification Devices) have a level of resonance modern technological aesthetics – the intertwin-
with the communication of the bees – the ing of animal forms of perception and techno-
famous bee dance, discussed, for instance, by logical forms of perception both as non-human
Karl von Frisch in the middle of the twentieth worlds – is now also something that can help
century (see Parikka, Insect Media 121–44) – us think the various regimes of knowledge con-
that takes place at frequencies of 200 Hz and cerning the current ecocrisis, disappearance and
300 Hz; GSM (Global System for Mobile obsolescence. Indeed, again in the manner that
Communications), for example, has a very Chun argues in her “Crisis, Crisis, Crisis”
different carrier frequency (800–2200 MHz) article concerning the epistemology of climate
but the pulse frequency fits exactly into the change and technological simulations, and in
slot – 217 Hz. the manner of ongoing modern curiosity in
I am less interested here in the question of terms of the microworlds (or just alternative
whether or not this link is the true cause; worlds) of animals (why they communicate,
whether the little world of communication, the sense, perceive so differently), we are
anti-McLuhan global village of insects, is really confronted with the need to think through the
being disturbed by the parasitical human wire- animal and the non-human. In the context of
less communications. Instead, I am fascinated the ecocrisis and scientific knowledge, we are
by the sheer fact that this connection is being similarly engaged in this double bind of
suggested – not only in this context, of course, animal worlds of perception, and the radically
but also in the various studies that link that different aesthetics of animals, as well as the aes-
pulse frequency to disturbances in the brain thetics and modes of perception, afforded by
waves of people. The fact that people are complex technological forms – for instance the
making these links and exactly through a Geophysical Fluid Dynamics Laboratory
theme of pollution (of the electromagnetic spec- (Chun 107).
trum) is of significance in terms of understand- In this sense, Jünger’s “glass bees” are quite
ing continuums between nature and culture, or, an apt literary example that addresses the disap-
as I have called it recently, medianatures pearance of bees; the double bind of technologi-
(Parikka, Medianatures); the inherent link cal modernity as part of animal worlds is not,
that mediatic regimes and high-tech cultures, however, only a theme of obsolescence under-
by necessity, have to nature, the animals, and stood through the military metaphors of an
materiality of such regimes, also through waste arms race (even chemical), and the changing
and pollution. It is one way to investigate the face of the technological-scientific army, but
notion of media ecology, as well as the mediati- the wider media sphere. This point becomes
zation/aesthetics of “natural” ecology. Indeed, evident when analysing the material consti-
this demonstrates the further infiltration of tution of our screen technologies and their
technology in the epistemology and discourse e-waste load, as Sean Cubitt has been doing, as
concerning animals and mass extinction, part well as through an analysis of the aesthetics of
of the wider debates and research concerning the animal – both about, but also stemming
our large-scale ecocrisis. Such links elaborate from, the animal. The media and the natural
on the need to develop new methodologies to ecologies are also entangled on another level
track the continuum between animals and besides that of the metaphor and narrative.
humans, technology and ecology, political
economy to technology, aesthetics to ecocrisis.
Indeed, the curious question as to the scale
III
and causes of a variety of disturbances in As a way of investigating the link between
animal and “natural” life is constantly media, animals, bees, extinction and aesthetics
embedded in the frameworks of knowledge I want to turn to artistic methodologies.
needed to elaborate the not immediately percep- Indeed, an increasing amount of artistic work
tible. What has been a constant theme in has taken up the posthuman question. There

114
parikka

has been a wide range of responses to the “ques- – are the sounds, rhythms and vibrations that
tion of the animal” (Wolfe) in the contemporary Malen introduces as audiovisual elements. The
art sphere, picking up Jacques Derrida’s writ- installation surrounds you, through its envelop-
ings concerning the self and the non-human ing soundscapes and its compound images. As
animal (the famous example of the cat and Der- such an audiovisual ecology The Animal That
rida’s nude body). I want to use this aesthetic I Am is an implicit suggestion towards a slight
perspective to elaborate one further angle to variation: the Animal Media That I Am. Modu-
the aesthetico-epistemology of the knowledge lations of perception through media technol-
and disappearance of animals. In this context, ogies share much with the animal worlds, and
I am addressing Lenore Malen’s work and the event of cohabitation that the piece tries to
especially her 2009–10 piece The Animal offer is one where we are invited to hear,
That I Am. Through a three-screen video instal- sense, and tap to the rhythmic vibrations – the
lation, it articulates various aspects of the Hertzian world – of insects. As such, it opens
Colony Collapse Disorder discussed briefly to a slightly more radical non-human stance
above. In Malen’s video installation this is the when you close your eyes and embed yourself
case from the point of view of beekeepers, but in a rhythmic sonic ecology/epistemology.
also raising various aesthetico-ethical themes Also, the three screens (see Fig. 1) of The
concerning the relationship between bees and Animal That I Am are rhythmic elements
human cultures. As such, it is emblematic of that deterritorialize our vision. A slowly pro-
the technical media and artistic media responses gressing multiplication of viewpoints is the
to such developments as the mass extinction of becoming-animal of perception that the installa-
species, and articulates, in its own way, the tion aims to deliver. The immersive space is also
double bind of technology – including screen one of composed fragmentation into the com-
media – and disappearance of the animal. pound vision of insects. Slow disorientation is
Actually more interesting than the narrative one tactic of this mode of becoming; it points
of beekeepers about the universal harmony of both to the world of insects and to the media
the insect world – similar tropes were used at in which we are immersed. The early avant-
various times in history, even during Germany’s garde connection between the technical vision
1930s National Socialism when Maya the Bee machine and the insect compound machine –
was the ideal Nazi supporter due to her loyalty in the words of Jean Epstein, “the thousand

Fig. 1. From Lenore Malen’s video installation. Image reproduced by kind permission of the artist.

115
insects and canaries

Fig. 2. From Lenore Malen’s video installation. Image reproduced by kind permission of the artist.

faceted eyes of the insects” (115) – creates a can insects be our companion species? This is
sense of space as split; perspective is multiplied paradoxical in light of Derrida’s The Animal
into a variation. Malen’s The Animal That I That Therefore I Am, to which Malen’s title
Am is about such forms of multiplicity, but refers. Derrida starts with the gaze of the
transporting themes familiar from early twenti- animal – his cat, to be exact, lazily gazing at
eth-century aesthetics into the contemporary Derrida’s naked body. But catching the
context of bee disappearance. Hence, one insect’s compound eyes is more difficult. For
cannot avoid asking what is the double bind Malen, Derrida’s essay functions as a critique
implied in the installation; the theme of disap- of subjectivity but we need to account for
pearance addressed through the video visions. further levels on which the question of aes-
Lenore Malen’s The Animal That I Am thetics and perception features in our relation
intertwines the various histories, aesthetics, to animals and ecologies. Indeed, such key post-
and idealizations of the bee community as well human debates in philosophy have been addres-
as the bee’s relations with beekeepers. Donna sing the co-constituting nature of watching/
Haraway’s term for this – companion species – being watched as a cross-species mode of subjec-
comes to mind, but not without friction when tification for the human and its relation to the
you ask how one establishes relations with non-human. As a further question, we need to
such insect forms of life as bees. As flagged ask: what forms of aesthetics and “watching”
above, our relation to insects is reflected in do we need to carve out in order to understand
much more than the narrative aspect of the other scales of ecology in which we are
Malen’s work. The immersive environment of embedded, being co-constituted not only by
the installation envelops the spectator in trigger- cats and dogs but also by complex ecologies in
ing ways. The clips that Malen uses are mini- which we co-live, and might also co-extinguish?
thoughts, mini-brains, which are brought Such speculative, philosophical and aesthetic
together with her digital software tools; the questions might give insights into a more
clips are memes that Malen excavates from complex epistemology of technological aes-
online archives and audiovisual repositories, thetics too. This is exactly why we need to
and composes into a three-channel envelope. account for the wider framework in which the
The Animal That I Am poses the question: ecological is given to us, as technical media,

116
parikka

and ask how this link of technological, material relations than just an index of how good nature
epistemology is guiding a specific way of think- is destroyed by bad culture. The question con-
ing insects too as media. The disappearing cerning aesthetics and contemporary art – even
insect becomes a form of transmission as well visual arts – becomes more interesting when
as signal of wider ecological connections and you step out of the representational sphere to
chains of disappearances, in a manner in which tap into measurements and mediations of other
Douglas Coupland continued this line of sorts. More than art about animals, perhaps we
thought in his fiction novel Generation A: after should pay attention to art by and for animals –
the near future disappearance of bees, five to use Matthew Fuller’s ideas – where the non-
people in different parts of the world got stung human animal question is taken as an aesthetic
by a bee, and hence are themselves suddenly cue (Fuller, “Art for Animals”). Fuller identifies
transmitters, signals, or at least some kind of con- a two-fold danger in relation to art with/about
densation point for a whole range of measures of nature: that we succumb to a social construction-
scientific concern; what is it in these spatially dis- ism or that we embrace biological positivism.
persed people’s organisms that attracted the bee? And yet we need to be able to carve out the
What’s more, it points as if to a whole substrate art/aesthetic in and through nature and
of communication between animal and human animals in ways that involve the double move-
bodies, around which a whole scientific and ment back and forth between animality and
popular cultural (the bee-stung people become humanity. Art for animals is one way to achieve
media stars) world is summoned: that productive dynamics, to quote Fuller
(269): “Art for animals intends to address the
I began to imagine the lives of those bees that ecology of capacities for perceptions, sensation,
survived over the years just long enough to
thought and reflexivity of animals.” What’s
find us and sting us and send us their
more, this aesthetico-epistemological task is con-
message, to tell us their story. I began to
imagine small cells of them – not even hives nected to wider possibilities, that
– surviving from year to year, nesting under
make us imagine a nature in which nature
highway overpasses and the dusty eaves of
itself must be imagined, sensed and thought
failed shopping malls – foraging for pollen
through. At a time when human practices
in the weeds growing alongside highways,
are rendering the earth definitively unheim-
their wings freezing and falling off in the
lich for an increasing number of species,
winter and in the summers their wings
abandoning the human as the sole user or
rotting and leaving them crippled as they
producer of art is one perverse step towards
tried to keep their queens alive, finding little
doing so. (Ibid.)
comfort in each other, finding solace only in
the idea that their mission might one day What such a perspective raises is not a focus
succeed, that they would one day find us, merely on animals but the non-human energies
with our strange blood […]. (Coupland 297)
and potentials of/in aesthetics, including
media technological aesthetics.
This experimental connection between aes-
thetics and imagining natures picks up on non-
IV representational notions of art and animality
To conclude, let’s return to the original idea that, for instance, Elizabeth Grosz (Chaos,
about “canaries,” or how the question of the Territory, Art) has emphasized more recently.
animal is itself a measure of our situation con- Nature and animals already are aesthetic,
cerning technological modernity; from media vibrational, erotico-aesthetic milieus of
technologies (including electronic waste) to rhythms; and where aesthetics happens, much
urbanization, modern agriculture, pollution, beyond the human eye gets involved. In artistic
and so forth. This conceptualization is tied to practices, David Dunn’s bioacoustics can be
a much more complex ecology of things and seen elaborating on similar issues, and scaling

117
insects and canaries

the question of animals, nature and aesthetics to intertwining of invisibilities and the unrepre-
that very non-human level too. sentable complexity is the most
The signalling worlds of bees dancing, insect interesting and up to date in
worlds of acoustics, rhythm, and vibrations are trying to understand why and
in themselves already part of the world of eco- how ecocrisis is an aesthetic
aesthetics, which as a regime is primary to any crisis.
kind of mediations concerning the displace-
ment (or extinction) of the animal. Indeed, I notes
suggest that such themes should not be taken
to strengthen polarities of innocent nature 1 Despite the attachment to the discourse of new
materialism, Grosz, for instance, has wanted to
raped by bad technological modernity, as
specify her approach to prefer
Ursula Heise (“Lost Dogs”) argues so much
of environmentalist narrativization of extinc- to understand life and matter in terms of
tion has done during the past two hundred their temporal and durational entwinements.
years, but should help us to develop new Matter and life become, and become undone.
modes of understanding the media–nature con- They transform and are transformed. This is
tinuum as medianatures. This concept is one less a new kind of materialism than it is a
suggestion to think of the ecological entwinings new understanding of the forces, both
of epistemology and aesthetics in the context of material and immaterial, that direct us to
the future. (Becoming Undone 5)
the ecocrisis, and even, perhaps, one way to
address invisibility, disappearance and obsoles- 2 On climate change, data and simulations, see also
cence. I want to argue that disappearance does Edwards.
not merely flag a theme of “extinction” but also
such modalities that we need to struggle to per-
ceive – worlds of non-human perception. This
is not to downplay scientific research concern- bibliography
ing the de facto disappearance of animals
from the world, but to focus on such ecological Barad, Karen. Meeting the Universe Halfway:
Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter
intertwinings where aesthetics – making things
and Meaning. Durham, NC and London: Duke
visible – is something that needs to be
UP, 2007. Print.
addressed on a non-human level too. In other
words, this scientific level is also dealing with Bateson, Gregory. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. St
the difficulties of perception, of aesthetics, of Albans: Paladin Frogmore, 1973. Print.
addressing so many scales of interaction. Braidotti, Rosi. Transpositions: On Nomadic Ethics.
Such a multiscalar mapping would necessarily Cambridge: Polity, 2006. Print.
be an ecological project in the manner Guattari
“Bumblebees Could Face Extinction.” BBC News 5
proposed; transversal entanglement of techno-
May 2001. Web. 7 Feb. 2013. <http://news.bbc.
logical epistemologies and practices, aesthetic co.uk/1/hi/sci/tech/1314012.stm>.
modes of knowledge, non-human ontologies,
and awareness of political economy and exhaus- Chun, Wendy Hui Kyong. “Crisis, Crisis, Crisis, or
tive global capitalist production and consump- Sovereignty and Networks.” Theory, Culture and
Society 28.6 (2011): 91–112. Print.
tion. In a manner similar to the way in which
our mediatic culture is increasingly defined Coupland, Douglas. Generation A. London:
by non-visibles that range from electromag- Heinemann, 2009. Print.
netic transmissions to algorithmic image Cubitt, Sean. “Ubiquitous Media, Rare Earths – The
processing as the non-visible generation of Environmental Footprint of Digital Media and
what we see, we need to extend this to What to Do About It.” Pervasive Media Lab,
ecology and natures too, embedded in aesthetic University of the West of England. 22 Sept. 2009.
“practices.” Such art that is able to tap into the Unpublished Talk.

118
parikka

Edwards, Paul N. A Vast Machine: Computer Models, Parikka, Jussi. Insect Media: An Archaeology of
Climate Data, and the Politics of Global Warming. Animals and Technology. Minnesota and London: U
Cambridge, MA: MIT P, 2010. Print. of Minnesota P, 2010. Print.
Epstein, Jean. “Fernand Léger.” Écrits sur le Parikka, Jussi, ed. Medianatures: The Materiality of
cinéma tome 1 (1921–1947). Paris: Seghers, 1974. Information Technology and Electronic Waste. Open
Print. Humanities Press, 2012. Web. 7 Feb. 2013.
<http://livingbooksaboutlife.org/>.
Ernst, Wolfgang. Digital Memory and the Archive. Ed.
and intro. Jussi Parikka. Minneapolis: U of Parisi, Luciana. “Technoecologies of Sensation.”
Minnesota P, 2013. Print. Deleuze/Guattari and Ecology. Ed. Bernd Herzogenrath.
Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2009. 182–99. Print.
Fuller, Matthew. “Art for Animals.” Deleuze/
Guattari and Ecology. Ed. Bernd Herzogenrath. Pickrell, John. “Mass Extinction of Insects May be
Basingstoke: Palgrave, 2009. 266–86. Print. Occurring Undetected.” National Geographic News
20 Sept. 2005. Web. 7 Feb. 2013. <http://news.
Fuller, Matthew. Media Ecologies: Materialist
nationalgeographic.com/news/2005/09/0920_050
Energies in Art and Technoculture. Cambridge, MA
920_extinct_insects.html>.
and London: MIT P, 2005. Print.
Rosol, Christoph. RFID. Vom Ursprung einer (all)
Grosz, Elizabeth. Becoming Undone: Darwinian
gegenwärtigen Kulturtechnologie. Berlin: Kadmos,
Reflections on Life, Politics and Art. Durham, NC:
2007. Print.
Duke UP, 2011. Print.
Russell, Edmund. War and Nature: Fighting Humans
Grosz, Elizabeth. Chaos, Territory, Art: Deleuze and
and Insects with Chemicals from World War I to Silent
the Framing of the Earth. New York: Columbia
Spring. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2001. Print.
UP, 2008. Print.
Sterling, Bruce. “Introduction.” The Glass Bees. By
Guattari, Félix. The Three Ecologies. Trans. Ian
Ernst Jünger. Trans. Louise Bogan and Elizabeth
Pindar and Paul Sutton. London and New
Mayer. New York: New York Review of Books,
Brunswick, NJ: Athlone, 2000. Print.
2000. vii–xii. Print.
Haraway, Donna. When Species Meet. Minneapolis:
United Nations Environment Programme (UNEP).
U of Minnesota P, 2008. Print.
Global Honey Bee Colony Disorders and Other Threats
Harrington, John Walker. “The Canary Birds of to Insect Pollinators. New York: UNEP, 2010. Print.
War.” Popular Science 93.2 (Aug. 1918): 258–60.
Wolfe, Cary. What is Posthumanism? Minneapolis
Print.
and London: U of Minnesota P, 2010. Print.
Heise, Ursula K. “Lost Dogs, Last Birds, and Listed
Species: Cultures of Extinction.” Configurations
18.1/2 (2010): 49–72. Print.
Heise, Ursula K. “Unnatural Ecologies: The
Metaphor of the Environment in Media Theory.”
Configurations 10.1 (2002): 149–68. Print.
Hertz, Garnet, and Jussi Parikka. “Zombie
Media: Circuit Bending Media Archaeology into
an Art Method.” Leonardo 45.5 (2012): 424–30.
Print.
Jussi Parikka
Jünger, Ernst. The Glass Bees. Trans. Louise Bogan Winchester School of Art
and Elizabeth Mayer. New York: New York University of Southampton
Review of Books, 2000. Print. Park Avenue, Winchester
Kittler, Friedrich A. Gramophone, Film, Typewriter. Hants, SO23 8DL
Trans. Geoffrey Winthrop-Young and Michael UK
Wutz. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1999. Print. E-mail: j.parikka@soton.ac.uk
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

exhibit 1: the green-eyed monster


Envy and jealousy are the shameful private
parts of the human soul.
Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human

Man never understands how anthropo-


morphic he is.
Goethe, Maxims and Reflections

W ithout question, jealousy looms over


the reader as one of the greatest and
most enduring of literary thematic shadows.
The “green-eyed monster” has stalked the
verses of Homer and the pages of Shakespeare dominic pettman
up to the hyper-neurotic chroniclers of today.1
Jealousy itself, however, was both exacerbated
and complicated in nineteenth-century Europe,
thanks to rapidly changing social and economic
TOLSTOY’S BESTIARY
circumstances – the “woman question” being animality and animosity in
one of the most salient.2 Tolstoy’s remarkably
economical novella The Kreutzer Sonata the kreutzer sonata
manages to create one of the most intense,
vivid, and thought-provoking portraits of jea-
lousy in the canon, and is as disturbing to read fictional murderer and the real patriarch;
today as it no doubt was in 1889 (especially if many of these explicitly flagged by Tolstoy
you happened to be Tolstoy’s wife, Sofia himself in the subsequent epilogue to the
Andreyevna, who – despite, or because of, story, that he felt obliged to write in order to
appearances – promptly lobbied the Tsar underline the moral of the story (for those
himself, to have the official ban on this work rather slow-witted souls who could not see it
overturned, so that people would not presume written in blood on the surface of the text
the portrait was based on her marriage to the itself, before even seeping down into the
author). The madman’s tale – and we will not subtext). The lesson to be learned revolves
waste our breath speculating on degrees of around the value of “continence,” not only
sanity or insanity – is at once compelling, regarding women in general but even toward
counter-intuitive, carefully reasoned, and con- one’s own wife. Celibacy is presented as an
tradictory. Without completely identifying ideal to which all civilized human beings
Pozdnyshev as the author’s ventriloquist should aspire, in order to more faithfully
dummy, there are certainly many moral and follow Christ’s teachings; for carnal appetites –
ideological parallels between the ideas of the even the lawful kind, sanctioned by

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010121-18 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783446

121
tolstoy’s bestiary

marriage – lead to sensuality, which leads to doubt still be living with him to this day. You
infidelity, which leads to jealousy, which poten- mustn’t allow them any freedom from the
tially leads to irreparable violence. As Pozdny- word go. Never trust a horse in the paddock
shev himself puts it: “Of all the passions, it is or a wife in the home” (11).6 Indeed, this obser-
sexual, carnal love that is the strongest, the vation foreshadows a key moment later in the
most malignant and the most unyielding” (48). story, when Pozdnyshev becomes most
And so we meet the first of thirteen exhibits in concerned about his wife at the very moment
Tolstoy’s bestiary: the green-eyed monster. she has learned the malefic art of contraception,
This unpleasant affect, this “rabid beast of and thus morphs into a threatening equine state
jealousy” (115), is a creature we shall merely in his own mind: “She was like an impatient,
introduce at this point, and examine in more well-fed horse that has had its bridle taken off,
detail later in the tour, after meeting some the same as ninety-nine percent of our women.
more of such zoological specimens, themselves I could sense this, and it scared me” (83).
embedded in a book which is figuratively burst- It is this ambiguous tension which will serve
ing at the seams with animal metaphors. as the focus of this present essay, that is, the tug-
While sitting in a train carriage, traveling of-war between the animal and the angel, in
through the Russian night, Pozdnyshev tells which the human being replaces the role of the
his terrible tale to the narrator in an almost rope (the human being, in this instance, itself
uninterrupted monologue. The homicidal being little more than a tug-of-war between the
climax approaches as inexorably as the destina- genders).7 Scarcely a page of The Kreutzer
tion of the journey, and as inevitably as the Sonata neglects to set up and then develop an
dawn which will greet the weary travelers.3 explicitly coded, and morally loaded, distinction
The first movement of the novella, however, is between humans and beasts. The logic behind
comprised of a discussion between decent citi- this common form of ontological apartheid,
zens riding the same train – “a plain, elderly however, becomes less and less coherent the
lady,” a lawyer, and an old man. This conversa- closer we seek to examine it. And the motivation
tion concerns the rapid mutation of social cir- for doing so is not to fault Tolstoy for his fuzzy
cumstances, especially the new status and logic alone – since even his contemporaries
visibility of divorce. The older gentleman found the author’s theo-philosophical writings
blames the education of women for all the wanting in comparison to his literary efforts –
trouble and fuss surrounding modern “marital but to show how this kind of species-based poli-
discord.” The others are both amused and cing continues into the present, despite press-
appalled by this man’s reactionary reasoning,4 ures from all sides to the previously
the woman responding, “After all, it’s only unassailable confidence of human exceptional-
animals that can be mated at their master’s ism. In other words, this essay deals with the
will; human beings have inclinations and attach- ways in which implied definitions of “animality”
ments of their own” (8). “You’re wrong there, and “animosity” represent two sides of the same
missus,” replies the old man. “The true differ- coin in Tolstoy’s libidinal economy; and, more-
ence is that an animal’s just an animal, but over, how these two terms are deployed in the
human beings have been given law to live text to clear a pure zone for the potential salva-
by.”5 The young woman counters, “but I tion of human souls, at some future time, at the
think you would agree that a woman is a ultimate expense of nonhumans. As the meta-
human being, and that she has feelings just as narrator crucially observes, “this animosity
a man has, wouldn’t you? So what’s she sup- was nothing other than the protest of our
posed to do if she doesn’t love her husband?” human nature against the animality [ozlo-
(10). The old man fends off her objections by blenie] that was suffocating it” (56; my
referring back to the animal kingdom: “If he’d emphasis).
never given her any leeway in the first place For Pozdnyshev, as for Tolstoy, “man” exists
but had kept her properly reined in, she’d no under the ethical imperative to strive for a truce

122
pettman

in the battle of the sexes, whereby men respect natural” relations with women have been
women enough not to lust after them, ideally ruined, perhaps forever (25). As the protagonist
not to impregnate them, and certainly not to tells us, “A fornicator may restrain himself,
continue venal relations in the unfortunate struggle for self-control, but never again will
case of conception. (“Man” here includes his relation to women be simple, clear, pure,
woman, since Tolstoy sees a perverse equality that of a brother and sister” (25).
in the susceptibility of both genders to “becom- Which leads us already to the fourth exhibit
ing-animal,” figured – in contrast to Deleuze in our monstrous menagerie (since they are all
and Guattari – in a negative sense.) related, actively encouraging the others into
Such are the debauched behaviors of the very existence): the Venus fly-trap. Pozdnyshev
average citizen, magnified in depravity as one complains:
climbs the social ladder, the worst offenders
being the upper classes, thanks to the obscene Women know perfectly well that the most
elevated love – the most “poetic,” as we call
hypocrisy involved, and their covert conscrip-
it – depends not on moral qualities but on
tion of the poor into their own therapeutic
physical proximity and also on things like
pleasures.8 hairstyle, or the color and the cut of a dress
[…] She knows that our man’s lying when
he goes on about lofty emotions – all he
exhibits 2, 3 and 4: the fornicator, wants is her body, and so he will willingly
the reptile-doctor, and the venus forgive her the most outrageous behavior.
What he won’t forgive, however, is an outfit
fly-trap that is ugly, tasteless or lacking in style. A
And so we meet the second exhibit in Tolstoy’s coquette’s knowledge of this is a conscious
bestiary: the fornicator. The fornicator is the one; but every innocent young girl knows it
unconsciously, as animals do. (31–32)
monstrous product of an emerging biopolitical
regime, in which the “solicitous government” Tolstoy, the Puritanical Christian, even inserts an
is in cahoots with the medical establishment, ironic reference to women who use the writings of
the class structure, as well as the patriarchal Darwin as bait for our presumably progressive
institution of the family, in order to encourage suitor-cum-fornicator. “Ah, the origin of
and regulate the libidos of young men in the species,” trills the young nubile, “how interest-
interest of the homeostatic health of the body ing!” Pozdnyshev is thus quite blunt in his insis-
politic. Through a combination of gluttony tence that “Marriages nowadays are set like
and sloth, the bourgeoisie are the all-too- traps” (36). What we thus see is the author’s die-
willing prey for “a systematic arousal of lust” getic recognition of a generalized “technopoetics
(34), although, truth be told, even the of capture” deployed by women in order to snag
muzhaks have “fallen” without the same deca- a socially acceptable, if not beneficial, mate; their
dent stimuli. In Pozdnyshev’s account, the clothes, their cosmetics, their somatic grammar,
erotic insights of Freud and Reich are antici- all simultaneously manifesting the cause and
pated by the Russian state (as well as in other effect of “the prism of our artificial way of life”
countries throughout Europe), and pre-emp- (35). Indeed, the technical aspect of this massive
tively controlled in the form of “tidy, legalized capture operation is made explicit in Pozdny-
debauchery” (24). This in turn creates a new shev’s descriptions of women instrumentalizing
type of male subjectivity, as Foucault could their own social alienation and sexual objectifica-
also have well told you (although without the tion into a perverse, reverse form of allure. He
moral disapproval): a kind of artificial hybrid stresses that “it’s this domination by women
between goat and peacock. Thanks to the we’re suffering from, it all stems from that.”
“reptile” witch-doctors – our third member of
Tolstoy’s bestiary – and their obsession with “What domination?” I asked. “All the rights
public hygiene via private parts, “simple, and privileges are on the side of men.”

123
tolstoy’s bestiary

“Yes, yes, that’s just the point […] Women The confusion is highly symptomatic:
are exactly like the Jews, who by their finan- animals are figured as the lowest of the low in
cial power compensate for the oppression to one gesture – subhuman, in other words. Yet
which they’re subjected. ‘Aha, you just they are also held aloft as the avatars of
want us to be merchants do you? All right, Nature, on the other, from which humanity
then, it’s as merchants that we’ll lord it
has become exiled or estranged. The animal
over you,’ say the Jews. ‘Aha, you just want
us to be objects of your sensuality, do you?
pulls double-duty as disgusting example and
All right, then, it’s as objects of your sensual- noble ideal. Like “the primitive,” of which
ity that we’ll enslave you,’ say women.” (39) this period was also enthralled, animals are at
the same time guilty (of not being civilized
The pardoned murderer describes this particular enough) and innocent (of the crimes committed
master–slave dialectic in terms of a “technique” by so-called civilization). Now this would make
which when abused “acquires a terrible power sense if contemporary Europeans divided them-
over men” (40).9 Moreover, “Women have selves ideologically on one side or the other, but
turned themselves into such effective instruments the fact is that in the majority of thinkers – and
for acting on our senses that we can’t even speak to especially vividly in Tolstoy – this ambivalence
them with equanimity” (41; my emphasis).10 is problematically co-present in the same mind,
These biotechnologically enhanced Venus fly- and in the same argument. (Witness, for
traps are at once predator and victim, as we see instance, the absurdly confused and earnest
Pozdnyshev’s (and by extension Tolstoy’s) circu- notion that privileged children have become
lar logic in full force. On the one hand they are unnaturally sensual because they have been
the height of civilized artistry, and on the other raised “like the young of animals.” That is to
they are behaving according to unconscious say, “The attire, the reading, the shows, the
animal instincts. (Remembering that “human music, the dances, the sweet food, the whole cir-
nature” is the ultimate oxymoron.) For women cumstance of life, from the pictures on the
to embrace their full humanity, they must not boxes to the novels, stories, and poems” – as if
seduce, consciously or unconsciously. They bunnies or piglets are exposed to such
must not play the game, for sex itself is an ines- things!)11 And yet there remains some kind of
capable vice for our species: whether you figure graspable parallel at work, in which the
us as the children of Adam, or the children of overfed animal becomes a freak of nature, just
Darwin. And the irony of this is not lost on our as the over-stimulated child becomes less-than-
narrator, trying to follow the curvature of this human. Such an equation would be at least
slippery line of argumentation. internally consistent if Pozdnyshev and/or
Tolstoy could resist switching inconsistently
“Why vice?” I asked. “I mean to say, you’re between their figuration of nonhuman rhetorical
talking about one of the most natural human devices.
activities there is!” For the author himself, as expressed in the
belated epilogue, carnal love is an “animal con-
“Natural?” he said. “Natural? No, I tell you,
quite the contrary’s true, I’ve come to the
dition.” (“Yes, I was a dirty pig, and I thought
conclusion that it isn’t … natural. (46) I was an angel” (42).) And yet, as we have
seen, it is enabled and encouraged through the
And what is Pozdnyshev’s evidence? The fact most exquisite forms of human technology.
that young women are traumatized by it, Nothing less than humanity’s much-lauded,
especially on their wedding night, if brought but rarely seen, “human dignity” is at stake (a
up in a good home. The madman continues, condition which is, according to Tolstoy, an
“Eating is natural. Eating is something joyful, asymptotic ideal, but no less important to
easy and pleasant which by its very essence strive toward, for all that).12 Unlike pigs and
involves no shame. But this is something loath- rabbits, humans do not exist merely to “repro-
some, ignominious, painful.” duce themselves as abundantly as possible,”

124
pettman

nor should they succumb to the temptations of wildly that it often collapses into conflation (if
“monkeys and Parisians,” who shamelessly only to better illustrate the potential ethical dis-
“enjoy sexual pleasure with the greatest degree tance in some more enlightened epoch). Almost
of refinement possible” (48).13 The only like a mantra, variations of the phrase “pigsty
answer is to refrain from sexual intercourse existence” (or “swinish behavior” in some trans-
altogether.14 lations) are bitterly spit out of Pozdnyshev’s
mouth, only washed back by the much-too-
exhibit 5: the porcine couple strong tea which he offers our almost speechless
narrator. Love, for the murderer, is thus
And at this fork in the road we meet the next nothing but lust made presentable, the public
and fifth exhibit in Tolstoy’s toxic zoological face of animalistic animosity. “I was regularly
gardens: the porcine couple. Pozdnyshev is a affected by bouts of animosity that used to cor-
great cynic when it comes to love: he denies respond to the bouts of what we called ‘love,’”
that this all-important affect is anything more confesses Pozdnyshev. “We didn’t realize it
than a poetic form of camouflage for the most then, but this ‘love’ and animosity were just
debased of animal instincts. Soon after his mar- two sides of the same coin, the same animal
riage to the woman who remains nameless, the feeling” (78). Furthermore, love, in practice, is
reality of the situation becomes disturbingly “just a sordid matter that degrades us to the
clear to him: an experience he extends to all level of pigs, something it’s vile and embarras-
his fellow men and women, assuming they do sing to remember and talk about. After all,
not see this reality so clearly, due to the spell nature didn’t make it vile and embarrassing
of denial which the troubadours of love have for no reason” (56). Again, the confusion con-
woven throughout society. Pozdnyshev could cerning that ur-referent “nature” comes to the
thus be caricaturing Kant’s infamous statement fore. What is more shameful – to act naturally
that the wedding ceremony functions primarily like an animal, or to pervert nature to the
as a way to ensure that the happy couple enjoy degree that most humans do, turning raw sex
exclusive and mutual legal access to each into a slow-cooked sensuality (as we have seen,
other’s genitals. “Our amorous feelings for both monkeys and Parisians do)? What pre-
each other,” he recalls painfully, “had been cisely is to blame for this sorry situation of
drained by the satisfaction of our senses, and lust: nature or artifice, especially given that
we were now left facing each other in our true the counter-phrase “instrument of pleasure”
relation, as two egotists who had nothing what- weaves its way through the same narrative?
ever in common except our desire to use each Men are simians in suits, just as women are
other in order to obtain the maximum amount exquisitely calibrated, but highly immoral,
of pleasure” (52). A secular sin, of course, in stimulation machines.
Kant’s schema, since humans – as opposed to Humanity is thus described as “the filthy
animals – are never to be utilized as means to king of nature” – a liminal sovereign who
an end, but as ends in themselves. “What were refuses to abide by the laws of his own kingdom:
the first signs of my love?” Pozdnyshev asks
himself, for his interlocutor’s benefit. “They The animals seem to know that their off-
were that I abandoned myself to animal spring assure the continuation of the
excesses, not only quite unashamedly, but species, and they stick to certain laws in
this regard. It’s only man who doesn’t know
even taking pride in the fact that it was possible
these laws, and doesn’t want to know them
for me to indulge in them, without ever once
[…] You’ll notice that the animals copulate
taking thought for her spiritual or even her with one another only when it’s possible for
physical wellbeing” (56). them to produce offspring [not true, of
In the second movement of Tolstoy’s sonata – course, ethologically speaking]; but the
the adagio as it were – the moral contrast filthy king of nature will do it any time,
between animals and humans vacillates so just so long as it gives him pleasure. (60)

125
tolstoy’s bestiary

Love, this putative “pearl of creation,” is little natural ideal, at least during quick glimpses in
more than the elevation of the “monkey the rear-view mirror of hindsight. “For these
pastime” of carnal relations. The inconsistencies creatures,” he notes, meaning the fruit of their
are enough to invoke vertigo at this stage in the union, “she felt a passionate animal devotion.”
tale. Animals are obliged to represent both good The poor woman, however, is trapped
morals and disgusting habits. And yet it is only between the two poles which constitute the
man who would continue to have sex after con- human condition – the animal and the angel –
ception, something Pozdnyshev remembers at least when it comes to her maternal side.16
with a shudder, given that he did not choose In a sobering reminder that today’s much-
to suspend his connubial rights during any of lamented “helicopter parenting” was not a
his wife’s five pregnancies. Nevertheless, this recent invention, Pozdnyshev’s retrospective
exclusively human transgression of natural compassion clearly emerges when he thinks
laws is described once more as “pig-like.” back to his wife’s anxieties over the children’s
health and habits. As he explains:

she did not, however, have what the animals


exhibit 6: the mutated mother hen have – an absence of reason and imagination.
Which leads us to the sixth inhabitant of the The hen isn’t afraid of what may happen to
her chick, knows nothing of all the diseases
bestiary: the mutated mother hen. Pozdnyshev
that may attack it, or all those remedies
describes the situation as follows:
human beings imagine will save them from
And so for the woman there are really only sickness and death […] If the chick dies,
two ways out: one is to turn herself into a she doesn’t ask herself why it has died, or
freak of nature, to destroy or attempt to where it’s gone, she merely clucks for a
destroy in herself her faculty of being a while, then stops, and goes on living as
woman – a mother, in other words – so that before. (72)
the man can continue to take his pleasure
What is usually considered a metaphysical lack
without interruption; the other isn’t really a
on the part of the animal, is here – exceptionally
way out at all, just a simple, gross and
direct violation of the laws of nature, one – figured as faculty. But the deceased was
that’s practised in all so-called “decent” trapped in a double-bind, by both her species-
families. In other words, the woman has to being and her individual character: “After all,
go against her nature and be expectant if she’d really been an animal, she wouldn’t
mother, wet-nurse and mistress all at the have suffered like that; if she’d really been a
same time; she has to be what no animal human being, she’d have believed in God, and
would ever lower itself to be. (58) she’d have said and thought what the peasant
women say: ‘The Lord gave, and the Lord hath
Our protagonist thus anticipates Heidegger, and
taken away’” (74).
other thinkers of the “creaturely life” of
mankind, in believing that “Man can sink
lower than the animal.”15 Contraception is con- exhibits 7, 8, 9 and 10: the shape-
sidered just such a fall, since “with the help of shifting rook, the bitch-in-heat, the
those shark doctors” Pozdnyshev’s wife is able cuckold, and the beast-with-two-
to prevent pregnancy, and thus becomes “a com-
backs
plete whore,” descending below the level of an
animal to mere material object (for it was only Moving now a little faster through the exhibits
procreation which gave any kind of alibi to the (in order to allow more time to linger just up
sleazy status quo) (63). And yet, anticipating ahead), we come to the seventh specimen in
the stinging pathos of the climax of the story, our curated zoological garden: a sinister shape-
Pozdnyshev also sees his pregnant wife and his shifter who recognizes and responds to “the
children as embodying a certain animal or woman” buried beneath the duties and concerns

126
pettman

of motherhood. He is an interloper who sees not with excitement, at the implications of this com-
a beast-of-burden but an alluring quasi-feline pletely unprecedented self-reflexivity in terms
femininity. He is the snake in the grass, the of subjectivity itself. In simpler terms, people
intruder, the rival, who flatters Pozdnyshev’s began to explicitly reflect on their own self-con-
wife and executes his rather automatic stitution, and the perceived threats to that very
program of seduction, optimized by years of same self-constitution. The self was exposed as a
default debauchery. Our protagonist takes an fragile and always already jealous ego. Indeed,
instant dislike to this man, for little other since Hegel, identity is defined negatively and
reason than he is a man, hovering around his absolutely as a struggle of recognition,
now radiant wife, suddenly freed from the Jealousy becomes, in and of itself, a problem
shackles of cyclical biology. (In passing, on – especially for a class that considers itself the
your left, you can just glimpse our eighth torch-bearers of a more reasonable and enligh-
exhibit, the bitch-in-heat – of course, she is tened age, unencumbered by the kinds of
one of the least understood of creatures, since brutal Old Testament codes of ownership
she does not have a voice in Tolstoy’s mena- inscribed in the Domostroy (mentioned twice
gerie.) However, were we forced to settle on at the beginning of the book, and personified
one phenotype for the character of “the other by the reactionary old man). Shakespeare’s
man,” for the sake of taxonomic convenience, Othello literally set the stage for a less allegori-
then we would be forced to choose between cal and more psychological exploration of jea-
the cock – an almost universal phallic symbol lousy by novelists who were, after all, almost
– and the rook; a bird which, accurately or exclusively members of this new historical
not, has traditionally been a symbol of the incor- class. And they realized that this most violent
rigible theft of women-folk, and for the willful and unstable of affects threatened to undo all
fouling of nests. Given the specific resonance those “techniques of the self” which promised
of “home-wrecking” of the rook, we shall to make society such a functionally civilized
settle on this, a species notorious for creating experience. Thus we see in Maupassant’s last
the ninth of our cast of creatures: the cuckold.17 book, translated recently as Alien Hearts (and
Slavoj Žižek makes the compelling point that published in the same twelve-month period as
a paranoid husband, who thinks his wife is The Kreutzer Sonata), a protagonist who is a
having an affair, is no less paranoid if his wife proto-Proustian Swann: surely the ultimate,
is actually having an affair. This observation and still the most lacerating, portrait of male
has the advantage of avoiding the reflex logic sexual jealousy.18
of bourgeois censure, and helps us better ident- In Maupassant’s story, the protagonist, Mar-
ify the psychosocial mechanisms which both iolle, labors under the impression that “he had
muffle and amplify jealousy, in heavily coded gained what he had always dreamed of, always
terms (the classic triple-play of race, class, sought: complete possession of a woman he
gender, but also – as I have been arguing – loved.” However, “[s]uch completeness is not
species). The literature on jealousy is vast, and of this world.” And so, “he would never
it would take an entire book even to begin embrace for his very own the ever-extending
addressing such a complex and significant surface of this woman who belonged to every-
phenomenon. But as I suggested at the very one” (92). The other gender begins in this
beginning of this piece, jealousy evolved into a period to unfold itself in a form of ontological
new genus in the nineteenth century, because origami, defying any attempt to contain her in
of the radical restructuring of the meta-cat- oppressively Euclidian romantic or domestic
egories I just mentioned, and the creation of spaces. As Mariolle’s lover, Madame de Burne,
more fluid commerce between them. As the begins to speculate silently, and a little sadly,
uncharted internal territory of the psyche is “Could it be that her fine delicate flesh, so
charted by Charcot and then in more detail by exceptionally aristocratic and refined, harbored
Freud, a profound unease emerges, coupled unknown shames, shames of a superior and

127
tolstoy’s bestiary

sacred animal, shames still unknown to her Heidegger, for whom animals are incapable of
modern soul?” (113). A new cultural phenom- the “as such.” So is it more a case of natural
enon is recognized – a women’s ego, with its competition and selection? I leave this specu-
own sovereign imperatives and impulses – and lation to the ethological experts, but the trope
is ambivalently condemned by the masculine is established: competition and instinctual
establishment as pure, frivolous selfishness, envy is natural. Jealousy is cultural. The
while also being celebrated as the obscure green-eyed monster is thus not a primal creature
cathected target of luminous fascination. That emerging from the slime and ooze of reptilian
obscure object of desire indeed! Hence the resentment, but a modern symptom of specifi-
million dollar Freudian question – “what does cally human melancholia. It can be found at
woman want?” – is asked for the first time in that smoking interface of agonistic traction
earnest: a question which to this day remains where the rubber of the ego meets the road of
unanswered (at least if the pathologically the superego. What is more, there is a perverse
jealous Mel Gibson is anything to go by).19 jouissance to be found deep within its mental
However, the reference to extra-humanity per- and emotional anguish.21 As Deleuze notes,
sists – “a superior and sacred animal” – “there is something sublime in the jealous
suggesting that any tentative answer should be man’s memory” (52). As men finally acknowl-
sought on the hinge between the theological edge that women are their own autonomous
and the evolutionary. (A hinge recently lubri- beings, female attentions can no longer be
cated by the rather viscous intelligence of taken for granted, or simply purchased. Or
Giorgio Agamben, of which more in the con- rather, their attentions can be purchased in
cluding section of this essay.) various currencies, and under the right con-
All of which makes it all the more surprising ditions, but not their hearts or souls. Hence
that Tolstoy expressed disdain for Maupassant’s the title of Maupassant’s book, and hence Pozd-
novel, on the grounds that none of the charac- nyshev’s childish tantrum that: “What was
ters were tagged with moral legibility – surely really so horrible was that I felt I had a complete
a charge one could make of The Kreutzer and inalienable right to her body, as if it were
Sonata as well (unless, conversely, one wants my own, yet at the same time I felt that I
to make the case that Tolstoy’s novella is wasn’t the master of this body, that it didn’t
overly didactic in this regard).20 It would take belong to me, that she could do with it whatever
nearly half a century, two world wars, and she pleased, and that what she wanted to do with
another Russian before jealousy would be it wasn’t what I wanted” (124–25). And it is this
depicted with such feverish, penetrating, and profound, almost metaphysical, insecurity
unflinching detail – Vladimir Nabokov’s which inflames passion (for the libido responds
Lolita. As detailed in the introduction, Nabo- positively, seemingly perversely, to the possi-
kov’s narrator, Humbert Humbert, is forced bility or actuality of rejection).22
to call upon the mundane materials of his pen One of the most vivid illustrations of this
to re-capture the object of his desires (and sado-masochistic self-infliction and self-indul-
thus the catalyst of his being: according to the gence is provided by Luis Buñuel’s classic film
same metaphysical logic that a guitar string That Obscure Object of Desire, in which the
does not really exist until it is strummed accord- love-lust interest literally vacillates between
ing to a seemingly pre-destined chord). Not for two incarnations, and the jealous male lover is
his mortal hands are the “aurochs and angels” of obliged to watch her make love to another
more divine distillers of exceptional experience. (younger) man, while trapped on the other
And so, for all the abject animosity that jea- side of a locked and barred gate. The man is lit-
lousy creates, the question still beckons, in erally imprisoned by his own impotent and
terms of its fraternity with animals or animality. enforced voyeurism, and he is forced to watch
In other words, do animals experience his ego’s worst-case scenario, something he
“jealousy” as such? Certainly not according to flees from at first, but then returns to,

128
pettman

compelled by the frisson of his libido. And so he tenth specimen in our menagerie: the beast
is almost disappointed to find that the act has with two backs. And as with other freak
finished without his bearing agonistic witness, shows, the lure is a combination of disgust and
or perhaps may have only been simulated, as curiosity.
the woman soon insists (although her state- However, as with the bitch-in-heat, there is
ments are far from reliable throughout the no need to dwell on this part of our tour, as
film). As Niklas Luhmann says, the lover we all know what the dual-backed beast looks
“enjoys” equally the sweet fruit and the bitter, like, and we all know that its structuring
for the only consistent demand is intensity, as absence is the pivot around which the tale of
an antidote to libidinal entropy.23 revenge takes place. Even long after the fateful
Jealousy is thus less about an embodied rival deed, Pozdnyshev probes his memory for
than the very structure and geometry of modern traces of his rival, as one’s tongue compulsively
romantic love.24 If all love is mediated or tri- searches for the most painful part of a tooth.
angular, as René Girard famously demonstrates, The husband notes that his potential rival
then jealousy is inevitable (at least as long as “had a particularly well-developed posterior, as
“possession” is a decisive motif – the jealous women have, or as Hottentots are said to
person is possessed by the knowledge that it is have” (87), an elliptical reference to a virile,
impossible to truly possess).25 That is to say, almost equine, animality. And yet there was
no couple avoids being, let alone becoming, nothing particular about this fellow, who –
extra-dyadic (as the psychologists call it). Pozd- like the wife – goes without a name, clothed
nyshev seems aware of this dilemma when it only in pronouns; nothing specific to fascinate
comes to the passively aggressive third term in the lady of the house: “If it hadn’t been him,
his marriage. Like Anna Karenina’s husband, it would have been someone else, it had to
Alexei Alexandrovich Karenin, he at first tries happen” (86). The inevitability of infidelity
to transcend his negative feelings, aware that, has been flagged all along, nurtured since birth
if cultivated, they will bloom fatal flowers.26 by the social matrix. The tragedy of this
But in contrast to the situation in Tolstoy’s novella is that the anti-hero chooses murder
most celebrated novel, there is no fork-in-the- over divorce, and that he spirals into white-
road where personal enlightenment might con- knuckled grasping and lashing out, rather than
ceivably win out against crude self-interest and learning that painful lesson of letting go, and
flattery.27 The tension between public face and letting be. “Are there not lovers,” asks Maupas-
private pragmatics is narrated in The Kreutzer sant, in an observation seemingly tailor-made
Sonata with little room for generous or altruis- for The Kreutzer Sonata, “who are retained
tic considerations of anyone else.28 A traditional for better or worse, with resignation, out of
premium on domestic honor wins out against fear of the next?” (148).
personal development and inter-personal com- And yet there is one skill that marks this gen-
passion, thanks to what Žižek calls, by way of tleman out from the throng of would-be lovers
Petrarch, “the plague of fantasies.” These are for the wife who is chafing at the bit, and that
the claustrophobic, crowding images that is his musical proficiency, especially on the
assault the jealous person, creating the kindling violin. The same culture which officially
for the green flames to lick ever higher. Pozdny- forbids adultery ensures the maximum opportu-
shev shivers as he recalls: “my imagination: it nities for such, via sanctioned social intercourse
began to paint for me, in the most lurid between the sexes. And as Pozdnyshev observes,
fashion, a rapid sequence of pictures which the playing of music, a deux, is one of the most
inflamed my jealousy […] a kind of strange, commonly exploited scenarios – a case of bour-
drunken enjoyment of my own hurt pride” geois morals thwarted, or at least tested, by
(120–21). The main character in this nightmare bourgeois rituals. Which leads us to the ele-
phantasmagoria – the prime exhibit in the venth entrant in Tolstoy’s bestiary: the siren,
human freak show – is, of course, the next and aka music itself.

129
tolstoy’s bestiary

exhibit 11: the siren for its Study. As far as composers were con-
cerned, Beethoven seems to have inspired
Pozdnyshev stretches the credulity of the lis- in him a kind of love–hate relationship;
tener when he insists that his jealousy was not perhaps he resented Beethoven’s power to
the cause of his psychological and juridical carry him out of himself.29 (Green 441–42)
torment, but rather the effect. As he explains
to the narrator, the culprit is really his rival. Such resentment is expressed by the murderer
“He and his music were the real cause of it all. as well, when obliged to reflect on the piece of
At my trial the whole thing was made to look music that makes up the title of the novella:
as though it had been caused by jealousy. Do you know its first movement, the presto?
Nothing could have been further from the […] Ah! It’s a fearful thing, that sonata.
truth. I’m not saying jealousy didn’t play any Especially that movement. And music in gen-
part at all, mind – it did, but it wasn’t the eral’s a fearful thing. What is it? I don’t know
most important thing” (87–88). Were we to sub- […] Music makes me forget myself, my true
tract one element from the cascading series of condition, it carries me off into another state
events, however, then clearly Pozdnyshev’s jea- of being, one that isn’t my own […] the effect
lousy is more decisive and destructive than the produced by music is similar to that pro-
aural ghost of Beethoven. What is more, it was duced by yawning or laughter: I may not be
sleepy, but I yawn if I see someone else
the husband’s jealousy which – at least accord-
yawning, I may have no reason for laughing,
ing to his own account – created the ideal con-
but I laugh if I see someone else laughing.
ditions for their retroactive justification: (110–11)
“I saw that right from the first meeting her
eyes began to shine in a peculiar way and that, The power which this particular piece of music
probably as a result of my jealousy, there was has – the intangible force and inexpressible sig-
immediately established between them a kind nificance which it represents – anticipates Vin-
of electric current which seemed to give their teuil’s melodic phrase in Proust, which
faces the same expression” (96). (As the literary becomes a hook buried in Swann’s mind, just
critic Dorothy Green quotes in a different trans- as Beethoven places a barb in Pozdnyshev’s.30
lation, “From the first moment his eyes met my As George Steiner (one of the great commenta-
wife’s I saw that the animal in each of them, tors on Tolstoy, of course) observes: “Because
regardless of all conditions of their position music is so immediately inwoven with
and of society asked ‘May I?’ and answered changes in the shapes of time, the development
‘Oh yes, certainly!’”) of Beethoven’s tempi, of the driving pulse in
Nevertheless, it is through the siren song of his symphonic and chamber music during the
music that the wife and her lover ensure the relevant years, is of extraordinary historical
possibility of sensual consummation. (As the and psychological interest” (12). It is this
debauched master of innuendo Maurice Cheva- self-same “driving pulse” which Pozdnyshev
lier exclaims in The Smiling Lieutenant – “I blames on initiating the fatal sequence of
love chamber music.”) For Pozdnyshev, in con- thoughts and emotions – the “cause and
trast, it is a “fearful medium,” for the very same affect,” as it were – which would lead to our
reason that the well-to-do skirt-chasers love it, penultimate exhibit in Tolstoy’s zoo: the wild,
because it is “the most refined form of sensual murderous beast.
lust” (117). Tolstoy himself was

an accomplished pianist and made up his exhibit 12: the wild murderous
mind at one stage to become a great musician beast
and composer. He was carried away by the
combination of sounds, and attempted to for- Pozdnyshev confronts the agonistic dialectic we
mulate his own theory of harmony, under the have been exploring throughout, between ani-
title The Fundamentals of Music and Rules mosity and animality, most searingly at the

130
pettman

climax of his tale: a climax he painfully relives in clothing and the expensive China, Pozdnyshev
the retelling (and who can say how many times walks in on a beastly scene – his wife sharing
he regales his fellow passengers with this an intimate dinner with his lover – so that he
grisly confession?). “I’m seized with horror only sees something inhuman. “No, she isn’t
whenever I think of the wild beast that lived human, she’s a bitch, a repulsive bitch!” (130).
in me during that time,” he admits (100–01); The scene in which the crime of passion takes
ashamed also of the fact that, “In the last days place, by way of a knife between the ribs, is a
our quarrels became terrifying; they were par- masterpiece of unsettling representation: the
ticularly shattering because they alternated equivalent of catching lightning in a bottle, in
with bouts of animal sensuality” (88). The terms of the technopoetics of capture. Here a
more he suspects the affair, the more his tragic “event” is logged microsecond by micro-
senses – his nonhuman senses – are inflamed second, in forensic detail, but fleshed out via
by the possibility.31 The “animosity” (zhivot- the “unreal time” of psychological distress (as
noe) which overwhelms him reaches the level Tolstoy also does with such consummate skill
of a linguistic tic or mantra for Anna Karenina’s suicide). Pozdnyshev’s
wife does not die immediately though – her
I was seized by a feeling of animosity towards mortal flame continues to flicker to better con-
her more terrible than any I’d ever experi-
front him with the irreversibility of his
enced before.
actions. Even then, as her life flows silently
For the first time I felt a desire to give my
animosity physical expression. I leapt to my out of her body, the madman wrenchingly
feet and went up to her; I remember that at recalls, “I saw displayed on her face the same
the very moment I got up I became aware inveterate look of cold, animal hatred I knew
of my animosity and asked myself whether so well” (142). He continues:
it was a good thing for me to abandon
myself to this feeling, and then told myself I looked at the children, at her battered face
that it was a good thing, that it would give with its bruises, and for the first time I forgot
her a fright; then immediately, instead of about myself, about my marital rights and
fighting off my animosity, I began to fan it my injured pride; for the first time I saw
up in myself even further, rejoicing in its her as a human being […] I realized that
steadily increasing blaze within me. I’d killed her, that it was all my doing that
“Go, or I’ll kill you!” I shouted suddenly, from a warm, moving, living creature she’d
going up to her and seizing her by the arm, been transformed into a cold, immobile,
consciously exaggerating the level of animos- waxen one, and that there was no way of
ity in my voice. (106) setting this to rights, not ever, not anywhere,
not by any means. (142–44)
Five repetitions of the word in barely more than
a paragraph! What is more, Pozdnyshev’s wife And here lies the supreme irony of Tolstoy’s
remains “a mystery, just as she’s always been, tale; Pozdnyshev cannot fully register his
just as she’ll always be. I don’t know her. I wife’s humanity – that is her monadic autonomy
only know her as an animal. And nothing can – until the very moment she is reduced to “ani-
or should hold an animal back.” The two malistic” bare life. Or rather, bare lifelessness.
forces feed on each other with a deepening And, of course, at that same moment it is too
hunger. late. In the agonizing hour between the punctur-
After leaving his wife alone on official ing of her organs, and the breath leaving her
business, Pozdnyshev’s paranoia draws him body forever, the adulteress exists in that
back to home and hearth, only to be confirmed fraught zone Eric Santner calls “creaturely
in such sickening circumstances that time life”: an abject space in which the inherent
itself seems to be stretched into a substance of pathos of the human condition is rendered
pure nausea. As feared, the rook is there, befoul- animal, only to ontologically enhance the Fall
ing the nest of the cuckold. Despite the fine from its assumed and exceptional dignity.

131
tolstoy’s bestiary

Again, the irony is that our nebulous “human- which cannot be completely domesticated by
ity” is touched most to the quick when our Tolstoy’s pen. Obliged to personify in reverse,
humanness is swiftly compromised, evacuated, these creatures suggest a struggle far more wide-
or stolen.32 Pozdnyshev appreciates his wife’s spread than between husband and wife, man and
personhood only when he holds a bruised, woman, but one identified by one of the author’s
virtual carcass – a revelation denied him by most controversial and celebrated contempor-
the blinders of jealousy; that “fatal energy” aries.33 For Nietzsche, humanity was little
(95) which seeks only revenge, because it more than the animal that had learned to
cannot see beyond the horizon of the ego. As make promises; the marriage vow being one of
Jean Baudrillard so accurately puts it: the most iconic. Indeed, The Genealogy of
Morals alludes to the rather terrifying set of
To love someone is to isolate him from the technologies assembled by men as pre-emptive
world, wipe out every trace of him, dispossess
and punitive mnemonics, so that this rather
him of his shadow, drag him into a murder-
frail and forgetful creature remembers to
ous future. It is to circle around the other
like a dead star and absorb him into a black remember. Hence morality itself, as the most
light. Everything is gambled on an exorbitant splendid and suffocating architecture. For men
demand for the exclusivity of a human being, like Tolstoy, morality is a cathedral, reaching
whoever it may be. This is doubtless what for the heavens. For those like Nietzsche, it is
makes it a passion: its object is interiorized nothing more than a cage, preventing man
as an ideal end, and we know that the only from transcending himself toward an empower-
ideal object is a dead one. (105) ing animality. Tolstoy’s obsessive cataloguing of
animals in The Kreutzer Sonata could be read as
Pozdnyshev’s remorse stems directly from
his attempt – conscious or unconscious – to
reaching this ideal, and the reader wishes that
grapple with Nietzsche’s challenge (itself a pro-
he had the foresight and wisdom of Tolstoy’s
vocation enabled by Darwin).
own wife, Sofia, who at least anticipated the
As such, this novella represents a particularly
agony which follows swiftly on the heels of the
fraught cog in the discursive device Agamben
ecstasy of passionate homicide. “If I could kill
calls “the anthropological machine,” that is, a
him and create a new person exactly the same
comprehensive engine designed by humanity
as he is now,” she wrote, only a matter of
and for humanity, whose primary function is
months after their wedding, “I would do so
to sort “the human” (as abstract privileged
happily” (qtd in Meek).
subject) from the nonhuman (an equally
abstract object). In terms simplified to a
exhibit 13: the empty shell of a degree that may give Agamben himself a
man – by way of summary and migraine, the anthropological machine is all
those cultural artifacts which combine into a
conclusion vanity mirror for our species, reflecting and reg-
Which brings us to the final, unlucky thirteenth ulating our assumed superior status. Agamben
exhibit in the bestiary: the haunted creature, the thus considers the trajectory of humanity to be
husk of a human being. As readers – as visitors at once located on a continuum with other
to Tolstoy’s zoo – we can do little more than pity animals – after all, Linnaeus himself could not
the poor fellow, or at least find him pitiful. offer any unique identifying features – and
Whether we as proxied interlocutors forgive exceptional in its self-recognition as different.
Pozdnyshev after his full confession is not In other words, it is only through our delusional
really the point. Nor should we measure our narcissism that “we” stand apart as a modern,
own reactions against “the moral of the story,” secular Adam. And yet, miraculously, this delu-
as painstakingly detailed by the author himself sion (aka, anthropocentrism) seems to be
– or at least, not only. For as I have argued, enough to forge an ontological difference,
there is a veritable jungle of animal types given all the mediating devices engineered and

132
pettman

employed to maintain that very distinction. With the active complicity of the siren (music),
(This is where and why Agamben can still be she is subsequently easily seduced by the cock
accused of a latent humanism, with tinges of or rook, whose own sensual delights are at the
the theological.) expense of the cuckold. Upon gaining indirect
In any case, Agamben shares Nietzsche’s fas- carnal knowledge of his wife’s infidelity, the
cination with a post-historical transcendence of cuckold is confronted with the mocking
ourselves, in which we would be ultimately specter of the beast-with-two-backs; an image
reconciled with our animal natures, and all the so infuriating that it can lead to a Hulk-like
freer for it. This would not be a return to a transformation, into a murderous wild beast.
bestial state but an inclusive fusion of soma The storm of passion passes, however, as soon
and spirit, no longer troubled by the agonistic as the irreversible deed is done, leaving only
detour of culture (as defined against and in con- the haunted shell of a man.
trast to nature). It would be a last supper as These are the figures deployed in Tolstoy’s
illustrated in the thirteenth-century Hebrew story – sometimes explicitly, sometimes
Bible, with “the righteous” depicted with through allusion – to describe the ultimately
animal heads, rather than human faces (1–3). inhuman dispensation of love. Moreover, Pozd-
For Tolstoy, this is anathema. The spiritual nyshev’s tale illustrates how jealousy can func-
superiority of humankind can only be under- tion as an efficient lubricant for the smooth
stood in relief to an animalistic background. operation of the anthropological machine,
And as long as men and women lapse back thereby fueling all the undesirable products of
into the sensual realm, their bestiality will species-based chauvinism. Tolstoy was correct
create a dangerous animosity. in insisting that humankind will forever lan-
Let us recap, then, our zoological itinerary, guish in spiritual limbo as long as it hitches its
cage by cage. First there was the green-eyed wagon to institutional matrimony. He was mis-
monster himself, gnashing his sharp, greedy taken, however, in attempting to locate human-
teeth, and possessed with the impossibility of ity in monogamous chastity (and not only
possession. Then the fornicator, who indulges because he was incapable of practicing what he
in debauchery at the expense of his consorts. preached). Sex is not the problem, but rather
Followed by the doctor-reptile, who encourages the site in which a secular and fleeting form of
such irresponsible behavior, under the relatively salvation is possible. At least according to
novel alibi of public health. Remember too, the Agamben, sex enables and enacts a “mutual dis-
Venus fly-trap – the female response to such rav- enchantment” which nevertheless affords
ishments, determined to parry her social disad- “a new and more blessed life, one that is
vantage into an economic advantage. Together, neither animal nor human” (87). Beyond
the fornicator and the Venus fly-trap morph pious, mythologizing pedestals, intimacy
into the porcine couple, in the nuptial reaches the point where it is capable of refusing
chamber, using each other for pleasure only, the potentially fatal fetishism of the individual.
as means rather than ends. Which in turn As Agamben cryptically puts it:
leads to the mutated mother hen, who first vio-
lates herself, and then her child, by continuing These lovers [he is speaking of Titian’s paint-
to have sex after conception. Eventually she ing Nymph and Shepherd] have initiated each
learns – once more with the aid of the reptile- other into their own lack of mystery as their
most intimate secret; they mutually forgive
doctors – to avoid conception altogether (one
each other and expose their vanitas […] In
of many noted inconsistencies or ironies in
their fulfillment, the lovers who have lost
Pozdnyshev’s account, whereby human science their mystery contemplate a human nature
paradoxically and perversely encourages a rendered perfectly inoperative – the inactiv-
heightened animal state). In turn, sterility ity and desœuvrement of the human and of
creates the bitch-in-heat, not for procreation, the animal as the supreme and unsavable
however, but for a wicked kind of gratification. figure of life. (87)

133
tolstoy’s bestiary

Tolstoy – unlike Titian, and unlike Nietzsche – possible way. For if women had their greatest
was incapable of seeing the admirable side of power in morality, what would they have to
post-human, neo-animalistic sexual congress: an grasp in order to regain a comparable ampli-
admittedly messianic state in which “people” tude of power after having given up morality?
may indeed enjoy each other’s bodies and souls (230–31)
without the folly of possessive vanity. Let it be, 3 It is also worth noting the recurring motif of
rather than let it bleed. In contrast, the great connection between trains and confessional
Russian author made the ulti- encounters, as practiced also by Maupassant and
mate human error – assuming Buñuel, amongst many others. Anna Karenina
the autonomous existence of herself, of course, is tragically linked with this
something called humanity in rather totemic form of transport, singled out by
the first place. Freud as a privileged stimulator of the libidinal sen-
And also in the last place. sorium. At one point Pozdnyshev exclaims, “Oh,
I’m so afraid, so afraid of railway carriages; I get
stricken with horror in them” (122), swallowed
up inside this new mechanical beast. He also tells
notes of killing time by visiting “a Jew” in a third class
compartment, “the interior of which was spattered
1 While the precise origin of the phrase is with the husks of sunflower seeds” (123), empha-
unknown, it was certainly popularized by Shake- sizing the circus-like aspect of train travel, in
speare’s usage in Othello. which the passengers are little more than animals
2 Given its resonance with Pozdnyshev’s account, in transit.
it is worth quoting Nietzsche in full: 4 The Domostroy was a sixteenth-century collec-
tion of archconservative domestic rules and guide-
In the three or four civilized countries of
lines pertaining to common public and private
Europe, a few centuries of education would
matters of Russian society. The core values con-
suffice to make women into anything we
tained therein uniformly endorsed obedience and
want, even into men – not in the sexual
submission to God, Tsar, Church, and Father,
sense, admittedly, but at least in every other
especially through modest dress, prayer, the
sense. Acted upon in this way, they will at
veneration of icons, and charity.
some point have assumed all the male
virtues and strengths, at the same time, of 5 While not a daily practice, let us not forget that
course, having to assume their weaknesses the practice of putting animals on official trial, and
and vices as part of the bargain: this much, as holding them accountable to human law, was only
noted, we can accomplish by force. But how phased out altogether in Europe in the first
will we endure the intermediate state that decade of the twentieth century.
this will bring about and that might itself last
6 Nowadays, rather than simply pulling on the
for a few centuries, during which female
proverbial reins, husbands use a passive-aggressive
follies and injustices, their age-old birthrights,
species of “trust” to try to control the behavior of
will still assert their supremacy over all that
their spouse.
has been newly won and acquired? This will
be the time when anger will comprise the 7 “It’s horrible,” exclaims Pozdnyshev, “[t]he
essential male affect, anger at the fact that all abyss of error we live in regarding women and
the arts and sciences have been inundated our relations with them” (20).
and clogged with an unprecedented dilettant-
ism, that philosophy has been talked to death 8 In her diary, Sofia Andreyevna reflects on her
by bewildering chatter, that politics have husband’s hypocrisy:
become more fantastic and partisan than
ever, that society is completely dissolving If only the people who read The Kreutzer
because the keepers of the old morality have Sonata so reverently had an inkling of the
become ridiculous to themselves and are voluptuous life he leads, and realized it was
striving to stand outside of morality in every only this that made him happy and good-

134
pettman

natured, then they would cast this deity from 13 Pozdnyshev enquires:
the pedestal where they have placed him! Yet
perhaps you’re an evolutionist? The out-
I love him when he is kind and normal and full
come’s still the same. In order to defend its
of human weaknesses. (In Meek n. pag.)
interests in its struggle with the other
9 According to Pozdnyshev, the very engine of the animals, the highest form of animal life – the
luxury economy is driven by the libidinal economy human race – has to gather itself into a
of women’s covetous desires: “Women are like unity, like a swarm of bees, and not repro-
empresses, keeping nine tenths of the human duce infinitely: like the bees, it must raise
race in servitude, doing hard labour. And all sexless individuals, that’s to say it must
because they feel they’ve been humiliated” (40). strive for continence. (49)
An observation with perhaps a disconcerting
14 A conclusion taken to a drastic degree by at
grain of truth even today, if we cast a cold eye on
least one disciple of the master, who sliced off his
the mediascape’s share dedicated to feminized
own penis – the source of animalistic desires, and
consumables.
constant saboteur of human aspirations – before
10 In a line which no doubt echoes Tolstoy’s own making the pilgrimage to visit Tolstoy. As James
thoughts later in his life, Pozdnyshev confesses, in Meek notes, in 1909, Sofia wrote in her diary:
almost a fit of male hysteria, that when he sees a
woman in a ball-gown he wants to call the police, This morning we had a visit from a 30-year-
“demanding that the hazardous object be confis- old Romanian who had castrated himself at
cated and taken away” (41). the age of 18 after reading The Kreutzer
Sonata. He then took to working on his
11 This curious tick of Pozdnyshev’s – a kind of
land – just 19 acres – and was terribly disil-
reverse anthropomorphism – is also in evidence
lusioned today to see that Tolstoy writes
when he paints a portrait of domestic banality, in
one thing but lives in luxury.
which man and wife suffer “the sort of conversa-
tions I’m convinced animals carry on with one
Apparently Tolstoy himself wrote in his diary:
another. ‘What’s the time? Bedtime. What’s for
“An exceedingly interesting man.”
dinner? Where are we going to go? Is there any-
thing in the newspaper? Send for the doctor. 15 For a critique of this position, see my article
Masha’s got a sore throat’” (78). “After the Beep.”
12 For all of Tolstoy’s gestures to “human dignity” 16 We see echoes of this inclusion/exclusion
and related elevated strivings, the question remains dynamic in the widely held contrary position, that
concerning the depth of his misanthropy. G.K. “only parents truly know what it is to be human.”
Chesterton, for instance, used the occasion of
17 The OED explains that
the famous author’s eightieth birthday to criticize
his attitude toward his own species, noting that
The origin of the sense is supposed to be found
Tolstoy is not content with pitying humanity in the cuckoo’s habit of laying its egg in another
for its pains: such as poverty and prisons. He bird’s nest; in Ger., gauch and kuckuk, and in
also pities humanity for its pleasures, such as Pr., cogotz, were applied to the adulterer as
music and patriotism. He weeps at the well as the husband of the adulteress, and
thought of hatred; but in The Kreutzer Littré cites an assertion of the same double
Sonata he weeps almost as much at the use in French; in English, where cuckold has
thought of love. He and all the humanitarians never been the name of the bird, we do not
pity the joys of men. find it applied to the adulterer.

Moreover, addressing his target directly, Ches- 18 If the reader will forgive me: literary criticism
terton adds: “What you dislike is being a man. seems to call for such anachronistic pronounce-
You are at least next door to hating humanity, ments of incontrovertible aesthetic fact. Or
for you pity humanity because it is human” perhaps I’ve just been reading too much George
(Illustrated London News 19 Sept. 1908). Steiner lately.

135
tolstoy’s bestiary

19 What Women Want, dir. Mel Gibson (2000). As the competition that turns guys on. That’s
I write, Gibson is in legal hot water for threatening why it’s mostly intellectuals who are into
his ex-lover over the phone with highly sexualized cuckolding: because other guys are crippled
violence, and thus providing the very voice of by jealousy. They’re aroused and upset and
hyper-phallic jealous panic. One wonders if this is don’t know why.”
indeed the voice of Pozdnyshev himself.
The problematic and elitist implications of such
20 Two years after Maupassant’s death, Tolstoy
statements are obvious enough without metacom-
wrote: “In this last novel the author does not
mentary here. (All quotes from Rufus n. pag.)
know who is to be loved and who is to be hated,
nor does the reader know it, consequently he
23 Luhmann believes that “it is impossible in love
does not believe in the events described and is
to calculate the costs or weigh up the accounts,
not interested in them” (viii). Which only makes
because both one’s profits and one’s losses are
it even more ironic that Theodore Roosevelt
enjoyed; indeed, they serve to make one aware
described The Kreutzer Sonata as the product of
of love and to keep it alive” (67).
“a sexual moral pervert” (in Lessing 27).
24 Pozdnyshev notes: “In our section of society all
21 Both the cuckold and the rook are vulnerable
husbands are jealous” (102).
to indulging in a particular instance of “the plague
of fantasies”; one which represents a variation on 25 One cannot help but consider this as a
the famous fable of Buridan’s Ass – the beast of symptom of Lacan’s dictum, “There is no sexual
burden that died of hunger, unable to choose relationship.” However, in some cases, the more
between two equally delicious bales of hay. In that this metaphysical obstacle is felt, deep in the
this instance, when it comes to extra-marital heart or loins of the lover, the more frenzied and
affairs (such as the one in The Kreutzer Sonata), disturbing the attempt to bridge the unbridgeable,
neither man has a choice. And yet both are to catch the uncatchable. Exhibits A and B for
haunted by an impossible emotional alternative: twentieth-century literature would be John
to be the husband, and make love to the beloved Fowles’ The Collector and Nabokov’s Lolita.
while she thinks of another; or be the lover,
26 A fascinating, emotionally scarring, postmodern
whose solace-cum-torture is to know that he is
twist on the “tolerant husband” can be found in Lars
in his beloved’s mind as she makes love to her
von Trier’s film Breaking the Waves. From a certain
husband.
angle, Bess could be considered a strange love-
22 Amazingly, as I write this, the blogosphere is a child of Anna Karenina’s – a woman who dies not
twitter about an alleged new “sex fetish for intel- because of possessive jealousy but quite the oppo-
lectuals” called Cuckolding. To quote the original site, because her (invalid and possibly insane)
article introducing this concept to the wider husband pushes her out into the public sphere, to
world, “It’s S&M for Ph.D.s […] in which men have sex with as many strange men as possible.
watch their wives have sex with other guys” – a
27 Today’s “polyamorous” community puts much
trend which “is catching on among people with
stock in the concept of compersion – a notion orig-
high IQs who revel in the psychological agony.”
inally conceived by the Kerista Commune in
The piece quotes one avid practitioner, “The high
San Francisco. Compersion is an extended erotic
point of cuckolding is when your wife says she
form of empathy, in which the subject experiences
wants the other guy all the time and never wants
joy via a third term, up to and including the figure
you.” This fetish is thus presented as a self-reflexive
usually considered to be a threat or rival. In
exploration of the libidinal economy, whereby jea-
other words, compersion is the positive and inclus-
lousy can be something other than a hostile take-
ive flip-side of jealousy. (Just as some would say a
over bid, launched on behalf of an unwise over-
smiling unicorn is the positive and inclusive form
investment in the self. As one behavioral expert
of a snorting, angry stallion.)
puts it, jealousy
28 A fascinating case in Russian life and literature
is a social construct based on the notion that of the same period is Turgenev, who not only
husbands own their wives, and is thus “much enthusiastically introduced Maupassant’s writings
more recent, evolutionarily speaking, than to Tolstoy but who wrote of unjealous husbands

136
pettman

(cf. Spring Torrents) from his literally eccentric pos- 33 For an insightful, and long overdue, reading of
ition. As one critique notes, “It was a constant Nietzsche’s nuanced relationship to the animal
refrain of Turgenev that he failed to ‘weave kingdom, look no further than Vanessa Lemm’s
himself a nest’ in life and had been forced to book Nietzsche’s Animal Philosophy.
perch on the edge of strange nests” (Schapiro
197) – most notably the nest inhabited by the
Spanish singer Pauline Garcia-Viardot. Clearly Tur- bibliography
genev was not a rook, since he never presumed to
poach a woman from another man, and yet neither Agamben, Giorgio. The Open: Man and Animal.
did he consider wedlock to be an obstacle to living Trans. Kevin Attell. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2004.
with his true love (and her exceedingly tolerant Print.
husband). Baudrillard, Jean. Fatal Strategies. Trans. Philip
29 In the same piece, Green makes the interesting Beitchman and W.G.J. Niesluchowski. Ed. Jim
claim that Fleming. New York: Semiotext(e), 1990. Print.
Buñuel, Luis, dir. That Obscure Object of Desire.
the reader of this novel, should be in a very Greenwich Film Productions, 1977. Film.
real sense a listener. We need to remind our-
selves again that Tolstoy conceived his story Deleuze, Gilles. Proust and Signs. Trans. Richard
with the living voice of an actor in his mind. Howard. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2000. Print.
That is, it was written, as the sonata was, Girard, René. Deceit, Desire and the Novel.
for an instrument. (447) Trans. Y. Freccero. Baltimore and London: Johns
Hopkins UP, 1988. Print.
30 See the illuminating comments on “the refrain” Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von. Maxims and
in Deleuze and Guattari’s A Thousand Plateaus Reflections. Trans. Elisabeth Stopp. London:
(chapter 11), and on Vinteuil’s phrase more specifi- Penguin, 1998. Print.
cally in Deleuze’s Proust and Signs.
Green, Dorothy. “The Kreutzer Sonata.” Tolstoy’s
31 No doubt an evolutionary biologist, or even Short Fiction: A Norton Critical Edition. Ed. Michael
sociobiologist, would read such passion as the cul- R. Katz. Austin: U of Texas P, 1991. Print.
tural froth of genetic imperatives. But as useful and
sobering as such accounts are in reminding us of Jonason, Peter K., Norman P. Li, and Jessica
our mammalian heritage, they are almost univer- Richardson. “Positioning the Booty-Call
sally reductive when it comes to interpreting and Relationship on the Spectrum of Relationships:
contextualizing human behavior. Psychology, Sexual but More Emotional than One-Night
affect, aesthetics, and other “cultural” factors are Stands.” Journal of Sex Research (July 2010). Web.
ignored, or, at best, alluded to as inessential contin- 7 Aug. 2010. <http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/
gencies (cf. Jonason et al.’s article “Positioning the 00224499.2010.497984>.
Booty-Call Relationship on the Spectrum of Lemm, Vanessa. Nietzsche’s Animal Philosophy:
Relationships”). A point I make not to preserve Culture, Politics, and the Animality of the Human
the exceptionalism of humans in this regard but Being. New York: Fordham UP, 2009. Print.
rather to identify as underdeveloped influences in
general within such fields. Of course, the huma- Lessing, Doris. “On Tolstoy.” Time Bites: Views and
nities have been guilty of over-emphasizing the Reviews. New York: Harper, 2004. 27–41. Print.
role of finer forces, and the more sharing of
Lubitsch, Ernst, dir. The Smiling Lieutenant.
conceptual lenses we can have between the huma-
Paramount Pictures, 1931. Film.
nities and the sciences, the more comprehensive
and revealing will be the readings. Luhmann, Niklas. Love as Passion: The Codification of
Intimacy. Trans. Jeremy Gaines and Doris L. Jones.
32 The vast and growing literature around this is
Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998. Print.
usually framed by questions of biopolitics (cf. the
vast bibliography issuing from Agamben’s render- Maupassant, Guy de. Alien Hearts. Trans. Richard
ing of Foucault’s concept, especially in Homo Howard. New York: New York Review of Books,
Sacer). 2009. Print.

137
tolstoy’s bestiary

Meek, James. “Some Wild Creature.” London


Review of Books 32.14 (2010): 3–8. Web. 7 Aug.
2010. <http://www.lrb.co.uk/v32/n14/james-meek/
some-wild-creature>.
Nabokov, Vladimir. The Annotated Lolita.
Ed. A. Appel, Jr. New York: Vintage, 1991. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. Trans.
Gary Handwerk. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1995. Print.
Pettman, Dominic. “After the Beep: Answering
Machines and Creaturely Life.” boundary 2 37.2
(2010): 133–53. Print.
Pettman, Dominic. Human Error: Species-Being and
Media Machines. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P,
2011. Print.
Proust, Marcel. In Search of Lost Time. Trans. D.J.
Enright, Terence Kilmartin, and C.K. Scott
Moncrieff. New York: Modern Library, 2003. Print.
Rufus, Anneli. “Cuckolding: The Sex Fetish for
Intellectuals.” The Daily Beast 29 July 2010. Web.
5 Aug. 2010. <http://www.thedailybeast.com/
blogs-and-stories/2010-07-29/cuckolding-the-sex-
fetish-for-intellectuals/>.
Santner, Eric L. On Creaturely Life: Rilke, Benjamin,
Sebald. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2006. Print.
Schapiro, Leonard. “Critical Essay – Spring Torrents:
Its Place and Significance in the Work of Ivan
Sergeyevich Turgenev.” Spring Torrents. By Ivan
Sergeyevich Turgenev. London: Penguin, 1980.
183–239. Print.
Steiner, George. In Bluebeard’s Castle: Some Notes
towards the Redefinition of Culture. New Haven:
Yale UP, 1971. Print.
Tolstoy, Leo. Anna Karenina. Trans. Richard Pevear
and Larissa Volokhonsky. London: Penguin, 2006.
Print.
Tolstoy, Leo. The Kreutzer Sonata. Trans. David
McDuff. London: Penguin, 2007. Print.
Žižek, Slavoj. The Plague of Fantasies. London and
New York: Verso, 1997. Print.
Dominic Pettman
Eugene Lang College
The New School for Liberal Arts
65 West 11th Street, Room 350
New York, NY 10011
USA
E-mail: pettmand@newschool.edu
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

the anthropocentric frame of


screen animals

W hen animals appear as central figures in


mainstream films, they tend to stand in
for none other than human characters or
nothing but unruly antagonistic nature. In Hol-
lywood cinema, these extreme cases are salient
in two typical genres: animation and disaster.
A lion prince in The Lion King (Roger Allers
and Rob Minkoff 1994), tricked by his uncle
into believing he killed his father, flees the
kingdom, but after years of exile he returns
home to overthrow the usurper and retrieve seung-hoon jeong
his royal identity. What is staged in this
Disney animation is not a National Geographic
on wildlife but a human drama newly mixing
the old motifs of Oedipus and Hamlet in the A GLOBAL CINEMATIC
character-driven, goal-oriented classical Holly- ZONE OF ANIMAL AND
wood narrative. On the contrary, the SF adven-
ture Jurassic Park (Steven Spielberg 1993) TECHNOLOGY
shows a utopian theme park with biotechnologi-
cally created dinosaurs turning into a cata-
strophic dystopia by accident, in an instant. into the conceptual frame of what humans
Animals may look “beautiful” when put in a believe as reality.1 Only within this frame does
touristic zoo under human control, but their nature appear to be the opposite of our life-
potentially insurmountable power is in nature world, while the frame itself remains cultural.
“dynamically sublime” in Kant’s terms, always Therefore, animals exist as the Animal only
ready to manifest itself as dangerous monstros- and always as viewed by, and related to, the
ity that can run amok, terrifying us and Human. We immediately recognize animal alle-
making us feel powerless. gories for human characteristics, good or evil,
These two oppositional modes of animal rep- brave or cowardly, generous or greedy, and so
resentation, however, work in the same anthro- on (thus animal characters are inherently civi-
pocentric paradigm in which the notion of lized); otherwise we consider animals to be
nature, the animal world, could not come into either domestic and helpful or untamable and
being without its insertion into the cultural harmful (thus the prevailing “pet or pest”
dichotomy of nature and culture. Nature did binary persists). Our binary attitude to them,
not preexist culture in that its idea was not at least in our civilized safety without sublime
born until culture named and incorporated it threat from wild animals, is then sentimental

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010139-19 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783435

139
animal and technology

or brutal, “sometimes aglow with the welcoming humanitarian leader builds a self-sustaining
hearth but just as often coldly shutting out the commune through the early modern manufac-
unwanted outsider” (Chaudhuri and Zurkow).2 ture of firearms; the boars and the apes in
The point is not that hospitality can easily nature are destructive and even counterproduc-
change into hostility, but that this Manichean tive, while the deer-like forest deity shishigami,
reaction itself deprives animals of their Real the spirit of nature, stands for neither good nor
that could not be fully symbolized in our evil, neither life nor death. Nature is a realm of
reality; or, say, it deprives our reality of room events simply to be accepted, which appears
for approaching or encountering their Real. unfair to the werewolf girl who cries out on
Conversely, the animal Real, even if absolutely her mother wolf’s death by humans (Levi
aggressive and invincibly destructive to 152).3 In other words, our common sense of
humans, subsists primarily as being-in-itself, wild/erness implies the discrepancy between
which we only secondarily view as being-for- animal and nature, which actually insinuates
us, similar or opposed to us. the discrepancy within nature itself. Nature is
Then how could we conceive cinematic not simply organic in its totality or antagonistic
alternatives that are open to the lost Real? We to humans, but deeply antagonistic and even
first need to be aware of a certain self-contradic- indifferent to itself. One might call this self-
tion in our ideological conception of the animal destructive inexplicable nature “anti-nature”
and nature: the animal is wild in the wilderness, (antiphusis), as Jacques Lacan suggests,
whereas wilderness often connotes nature as the insofar as it challenges precisely not the
organic, holistic, hippie-spiritualized ground of human world but the humanist frame of
peace and harmony which has been not only nature. Anti-nature is the barred Real, not a
uncontaminated by human civilization but unified wholeness but a fractured materiality
“must be biologically intact and legally pro- blocked from the symbolic order of smooth
tected” as the WILD Foundation states (www. linguistic translation and logical intellectual
wild.org). This virginal environment valued understanding (Johnston 34–37).4
for moral, cultural and aesthetic reasons If Japanimation exposes this unnatural
remarkably colors the Japanese animation rep- nature, unlike Hollywood animation, Alfred
resented by Miyazaki Hayao, whose works Hitchcock may be one of the first Hollywood
have been no less globally consumed and auteurs who introduced a different sort of disas-
appreciated than those of Disney or Pixar: ter film with the animal behavior being in no
Nausicaä of the Valley of the Wind (1984), way completely explicable. His famous Birds
My Neighbor Totoro (1988), Princess Mono- (1963) begins in a pet shop where Melanie
noke (1997) and Spirited Away (2001), to buys a pair of lovebirds, but her romantic boat
name a few. Imbued with local animism and trip with this animal gift to Mitch is cracked
spiritualism, the Gaia-evoking Japanese nature by a seagull’s sudden hit on her forehead. This
he depicts nurtures life and cures wound, small incident is followed by all kinds of
exerts magical power and defeats colonial vio- bird attacks on the entire seaside town of
lence. But despite this apparent “green” Bodega Bay in their immeasurable number
message, Hayao is evidently not a naı̈ve New taking on the “mathematically sublime.” We
Age conservationist appealing mainly to chil- know that this natural violence has a multi-
dren. Princess Mononoke, a unique Asian were- layered classical psychoanalytic allegory: the
wolf film, does not just focus on a human- intervention of Mitch’s jealous mother, a Hitch-
animal’s individual psycho-social struggle in cockian superego, in his romance with Melanie;
the Western horror format that demonizes the unconscious attachment as aggressivity
either humanity or animality. It rather reveals inherent in the mirror phase entered by the
how the human and the animal are complexly couple; the punishment of Melanie’s active sexu-
interrelated and how each side is divided as ality in phallocentric classical narrative; the
well: beside imperial and samurai forces, a uncanny return of the repressed in human

140
jeong

civilization with caged animals turning into wild Americans, do whatever like liberals, subvert
ones; and so forth.5 We nonetheless find no domestic power relationship like feminists …
comprehensively comprehensible answer to the Likewise, ontological others such as zombies,
primary question of why birds attack. What is monsters, ghosts, and vampires have been inter-
the actual motivation of those peaceful preted as figuring such minorities, including
animals’ abrupt change into brutal monsters? communists, immigrants, foreigners, workers,
But the answer lies in the question itself. This and even capitalists sucking the blood of the
incomprehensibility, this unmotivated self- proletariat. In short, animal-like beings on
mutation of natural balance is the nature of screen cannot help being more or less personi-
nature, the anti-natural core of what we take fied in the frame of cultural studies whose iden-
for granted as nature. The first bird’s attack tity politics is built on differences in class, sex,
on Melanie’s euphoric boat in the bay appears, gender, race, ethnicity, and so on, within
Slavoj Žižek says, as a “Hitchcockian blot” human societies. And in this aspect they are
(Looking Awry 88–106); a visual smear that treated as favorable or unfavorable, our friends
triggers the overturn of our picture of reality, or enemies. Thus, again, the two modes of
the catastrophe of our harmonious ecology of animal representation mentioned at the begin-
environment – Greek katastrophē means over- ning are intermingled into one: the Animal as/
turn. We are helpless in accounting for this for the Human.
intrusion of the Real, and our powerlessness Undoubtedly, this anthropomorphic ten-
proves nothing but the absurd otherness of the dency works according to what Fredric
animal. Jameson calls hermeneutic “depth models”: dia-
The mainstream cinema often leaves room for lectic, psychoanalytic, existential, or semiotic –
multiple interpretative entry points to this the hierarchical dichotomy that there is a
otherness, but again, anthropocentricity is the latent meaning, essence, signified below the
common hermeneutic matrix of social, political, appearance of manifest signifier (Jameson 12).
mythical, religious references or allegories What matters is the invisible deeper level full
itself. We easily recognize the biblical plagues of human-oriented meanings and not their
of locusts in The Omen (Richard Donner animal image. Put differently, however, the
1976), the crime investigation through the com- absolute difference between human and animal
munication with insects in Phenomena (Dario is reduced to relative differences among
Argento 1985), the bestial eroticism of human-looking animal groups. The “reading”
Western werewolves in Cat People (Jacques of animals as disguised humans is then at risk
Tourneur 1942; Paul Schrader 1982) and Wolf of being blind to animals themselves; our
(Mike Nichols 1994), etc. In the genre cycle of vision has a blind spot with regards to their
disaster film, Gremlins (Joe Dante 1984), for animal being as just seen on screen. More signifi-
example, where cute eponymous pets turn into cant than the depth of humanized meanings is
malevolently mischievous monsters, sutures the surface of the animal; it is the surface that
the motif of The Birds into the 1980s “campy” exhibits the animal as radical difference above
trend of disaster comedy that parodies former cultural differences among human-animals.
genre films (Feil 31–58). Rather than confront- The fundamental conceptual task is therefore
ing animality as such, this kitsch film trans- to add ontological others (including the
forms the animal as the external ontological machine, as we will see) to cultural others
Other into internal sociological others of the while replacing the latter in reading films.
majority in a human community. Gremlins’ This supplement would help retool established
mathematically sublime proliferation is then cultural studies while remobilizing identity poli-
read, ironically or critically, to stand for the tics in the contemporary context of the so-called
growing threat to the mainstream middle-class “ethical turn of the political” – to simplify
white America by stereotyped social minorities: Jacques Rancière’s diagnosis, the political con-
the disgusting creatures are black like African flict among oppositional identity/interest

141
animal and technology

groups in a society now gives way to the ethical of the symbolic construction of fictive reality.
one between a global community of harmonious This liminality is another name for animality.
differences as a whole and its exception A positivist lessen in this context is found in
(Rancière 109–32). The national politics of Project Nim (James Marsh 2011), a pure docu-
bourgeoisie vs. proletariat in a country, for mentary on behavioral scientist Herbert
instance, becomes less fundamentally decisive Terrace’s 1970s project of raising a chimpanzee
than the global antagonism between an encom- called Nim in a human family and teaching it
passing multicultural society and a small band American Sign Language. Not long after the
of terrorists. Rancière argues that the ethical phenomenon of Woodstock, the project took
turn results in the globalized world’s “war on place not in a laboratory but mostly in a huge
terror” that ends up being indistinct from house with large natural grounds outside
terror itself in its operation, so he critically New York. The ambitious experiment of bring-
points out political side-effects of this turn. ing human communication to the animal was
Nevertheless, given the direction of ongoing glo- conducted in the hippie mood of bringing the
balization that tolerates ever more diverse class/ human back to nature. Its home-movie-style
sexual/racial identities while generating unpre- footage indeed shows the most positive com-
cedented global issues beyond national sol- munication that could occur “when species
utions, the place of the remnant of the world meet,” if we borrow a book title from Donna
system could be conceived of as larger than Haraway, who draws attention to the everyday
just terrorism. It is the place of the environment practice of intersubjectivity between human
whose catastrophe would impact the entire and animal and their mutual response in work
global village beyond individual political com- and play. Notably, Haraway criticizes contem-
munities. Ontological others of the human call porary Continental philosophy on the animal
for our attention in this regard, urging us to for ignoring ordinary and mundane inter-
explore a larger bio-polis emerging between, species companionship. She argues that Derri-
and encompassing both, the human world that da’s famous speculation on his cat’s gaze at his
becomes ever more globally homogenized and naked body, which virtually ignited recent
its radically external-immanent environment, animal studies in the humanities, “failed a
natural or technological. The question of how simple obligation of companion species” by
to face this environment requires complexly lacking curiosity about “what the cat might
ethical rather than simply political attitudes, actually be doing, feeling, thinking, or perhaps
since biopolitics concerns not a new public making available to him in looking back at
sphere so much as the condition of any such him” (Haraway, When Species Meet 20).
polis, as we will see. We need to review the Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari’s anti-
ethical turn expansively as eco-ontological. Oedipal and anti-capitalist project proposed
the provocative notion of “becoming-animal,”
which, however, proves the profound absence
of respect for and with actual animals, only “fig-
redirecting ethics of the animal uring relentless otherness knotted into never
To do so, I look at a series of contemporary films fully bounded or fully self-referential entities.”
that seem to embody a facet of “global cinema” Against this “philosophy of the sublime, not
made in the twenty-first century in the sense the earthly, not the mud” (27–32), Haraway
that, even if very locally produced, they could builds on behavior semiotics and ecological
directly confront us with animality as a globally biology that shed light on life-entities’ autopoi-
eco-ontological other of the human. Animals in esis, the self-making and self-maintaining feed-
such films, made in Western or Third World back with other entities in Gaian systems,
countries, appear on the boundary between the cybernetic or otherwise.6 When becoming-
Symbolic and the Real, between fictional and animal works as the deterritorialization of
documentary aesthetics – that is, at the limit human subjectivity into the liberating molecular

142
jeong

state immanent in all beings, animal companion- conditioned, limited, just like the religious
ship serves the individuation of animal subjec- notion of tolerance taking the form of a Chris-
tivity in the systemic environment of tian charity – its paternalistic gesture of invita-
communication. tion still implies the juridical subordination or
Unfortunately, however, Project Nim finally assimilation of the other to the host’s symbolic
failed despite the deep and long emotional con- order: “I invite you, I welcome you into my
nection made between Nim and his educators. home, on the condition that you adapt to the
Nim’s understanding of sign language was laws and norms of my territory, according to
remarkable but limited, while his occasional vio- my language, tradition, memory, and so on.”
lence hurt several dedicated animal lovers. Pure hospitality, on the contrary, is open “to
Terrace abandoned the project; Nim was sent someone who is neither expected nor invited,
to a farm and put in a pen with iron bars. The to whomever arrives as an absolutely foreign
project started on the hopeful fact that 98.7 visitor, as a new arrival, nonidentifiable and
percent of the DNA in humans and chimpan- unforeseeable, in short, wholly other” (Haber-
zees is identical, but its end suggests that the mas and Derrida 162). The first case of partial
unbridgeable abyss is inherent in the 1.3 hospitality resonates with Žižek’s critical view
percent difference between the two species. of capitalist multiculturalism whose liberalist
Nim’s linguistic precariousness and unpredict- tolerance is limited to benevolent other cul-
able violence may all be condensed in this tures, music or food, which are deprived of
small yet decisive portion of alterity for which their excessive intolerable otherness: violence,
humans have nothing to offer but the old patriarchy, fundamentalism, etc. (Žižek, “Mul-
alternative: care or cage. That is, care-taking ticulturalism”). The second case of hospitality
companionship between species could not be itself implies the complete loss of anthropo-
as symmetrically mutual as Haraway desires; it centric initiative that sets up the field of inter-
would still face the risk of treating the animal action as such, returning to pure nature prior to
other as an object of hospitality or hostility, tol- the birth of the notion of nature. If the first is
erance or intolerance. Haraway, of course, related to the ethical turn of politics in the
emphasizes the training in the contact zone for public sphere, the second insinuates a state in
practical interactivities with animals that can which this civilized polis as a cultural frame
challenge human exceptionalism. A fundamen- itself no longer exists. This ideal hospitality is
tal question is, however, who initiates such put in a double bind: it is inevitably con-
interactivities. It is always the human and not ditioned in practice through the host’s aware-
the animal that desires to bridge their ness and management of it; or when
gap, and thereby the human always takes the unconditioned, it couldn’t maintain itself as
position of a host who invites animal guests to hospitality.
his home. Project Nim tests the limit of such hospitality
The ideal of mutual companionship, then, as cannot but be imperfect in reality. Its con-
evokes the idea of impossible hospitality. For crete trans-species companionship is done
Derrida, pure hospitality is impossible in through the invitation of the animal to a linguis-
both ways: first, the host cannot be hospitable tic community owned and controlled by the
towards the guests who take over his property human host. The guest who hurts this hospital-
ownership and control of the situation, that ity is deported and imprisoned, which implies
is, who threaten the precondition of hospitality that hospitality cannot be unconditional
itself; second, if unconditional hospitality is because of the host’s self-protection. In his
offered through non-mastery and the abandon polis, the host can declare a “state of exception”
of all property, there is no longer the possibility in which the detention of the threatening other
of hosting anyone as there is no ownership or is executed in the way of degrading it from a
control (Derrida and Dufourmantelle 135– community member to just a “naked life”
55). Conversely, hospitality is possible only as whose political subjectivity is suspended like

143
animal and technology

the homo sacer (Agamben). Politics is underlain One should ask here if this humanitarian ideol-
by this biopolitics that the host operates ogy is not the unavoidable compromise of ethics
through his sovereignty to distinguish the politi- or the way it is actualized in reality; an ethics
cal from the natural state of subjectivity. Yet that is defined primarily as one’s obligation to
this bio-polis does not mean that the state of the other’s suffering, and furthermore the
exception restores pure nature, but rather human’s compassion on the animal’s vulner-
creates a sort of simulated natural state where ability. Judith Butler finds humanity in such
life becomes vulnerably animal and thus its an empathy-laden ethics towards the neighbor
right to live completely depends on the sover- living a precarious life, its vulnerable face we
eign’s power. Nim finally becomes an animal must not kill in the context of post-9/11 bio-
after his long human education, but then he is politics (Butler xvii–xviii). But this Levinasian
an encaged animal, a bestial terrorist under sur- ethics as the reverse of narcissistic aggression
veillance and punishment. is grounded on the cultural (thus still anthropo-
One may be tempted to save such an animal centric) tradition in which the place of the other
homo sacer in the name of its “rights” drawn traces back to that of infinity opened by God’s
from the liberal justice tradition. Animal acti- calling to which Christian sacrifice could
vists, protectionists, anti-fur protesters, and respond fully. What counts is one’s ability to
even vegetarians more or less assume animal respond to this infinite otherness, one’s “respon-
rights to be legally endorsed and accepted, just sibility” for the Other.
like the human rights of the unrepresented Werner Herzog’s Grizzly Man (2005) leaves
rabble, voiceless people, Guantanamo prisoners, room for thinking about a different ethics. To
and so on. Paradoxically, this kind of political begin with, this auteuristic documentary con-
struggle results in the ethical turn of politics; fronts us with the maximum paradox of hospi-
the more social subalterns register as equal sub- tality embodied in the life of Timothy
jects in a community, the more inclusive the Treadwell, a self-claimed animal keeper who
concept of rights becomes – it becomes no was, however, devoured by the very grizzly
longer a political goal to achieve but an ethical bears he loved for eight summers in Alaska.
bottom to accept, almost like a Kantian categori- The point is not simply that his ethical act led
cal imperative: we ought to embrace suffering to a perplexing horrible end. The film shows a
others! Cary Wolfe, however, points out that substantial amount of the video footage made
ethical standing and civic inclusion in the and left by Treadwell himself, in which we actu-
“rights” conversation are predicated upon ally notice some distance between big “sublime”
rationality, autonomy, and agency as intention- grizzlies in the background (nature) and the
ality of a member of what Kant called “the com- grizzly man with a movie camera as well as a
munity of reasonable beings” (Wolfe 127). Ron small “beautiful” pet in the foreground (civiliza-
Broglio argues that “rights” thus presumes tion). This physical gap is filled only with Tread-
community as founded on humanist ideals, well the speaking subject’s ceaseless words that
which would inevitably set juridical limits to set his psychological connection to the bears. It
the nature and exercise of animal rights is as though language, the lack of which defines
(Broglio and Young). As a result, while the the animal for many philosophers from Des-
ethical turn expands the established polis bio- cartes to Lacan, built an invisible barrier
ontologically, the humanely endowed rights between two species, disguised as their compa-
could paradoxically keep animals more or less nionate communication. Treadwell’s one-sided
segregated, degraded, or at best specially verbal love letters to peaceful animals are
treated through “affirmative actions” taken by virtually like a symbolic wall that protects the
the enlarged community. Then hospitality animal protector from the animal Real, its
would be reduced back to tolerance, the falsely dangerous unpredictable violence.7 Despite his
neutral and potentially hegemonic ideal in the proclamation of animal protection, or rather,
Enlightenment tradition of endorsing others. because of its linguistic humanism itself, the

144
jeong

grizzly man thus remains an ecological multicul- vulnerable precariousness? I will go into this
turalist whose hospitality partakes of patroniz- issue below, but at this point it seems more
ing distanciation from the animal other. All important to focus on the total absence of
his talk to bears might imply this hidden animal subjectivity connected to the human. A
message: “I love you, but please stay there!” remarkable moment in Grizzly Man is when
Liberalist tolerance works only insofar as Treadwell finds the steaming lump of a grizzly’s
others are not harmful. Treadwell’s tragedy is feces and calls it “Wendy’s poop,” as if it were a
that this distance was too shortened to keep “gift” by which he can feel the bear’s inside,
him in safety at a certain point, unawares to that is, the inside of what is outside him. The
him. That is, his hospitality could be main- dirty material trace of anti-natural rottenness
tained only on its own self-contradictory con- is named and appreciated by the man who
dition that it couldn’t be unconditional, thereby feels belongingness to the other. This
though it pretended to be. means not an intersubjective gifting as give-
Interestingly, however, we realize here that and-take economy but a paradoxical revelation
what renders “ecological hospitality” impossible that what is given to him as a gift is never
is not the human host’s abandonment of his given and even acknowledged as a gift by the
ownership and control (Treadwell kept this con- animal giver, thus never to be returned. Is it
dition) but primarily the animal guest’s com- not a miraculous example of pure gift
plete indifference to the host. No grizzly bear irreducible to exchange which Derrida
in fact has recognized his hospitality as hospital- views as impossible, just like pure hospitality
ity; no animal indeed has the concept of and irreducible to tolerance (Derrida, Given Time
respect for the hospitable human’s property 34–70)?
and protection. What underlies this animality In other words, pure hospitality that is always
is antiphusis as aforementioned, with nature impossible when offered by the human to the
as dark, violent, rotten, hostile, which appears animal might be possible when we rethink it
negative in the anthropocentric frame, but the other way around. The subject of gifting,
which fundamentally implies neutrality for the of hospitality, is not Treadwell but an originally
human. A skeleton of a bear devoured by anonymous bear which, however, has no subjec-
another bear and decaying animal corpses that tivity related or intended to him, that is, which
Treadwell encounters prove not so much a has subjectivity, if any, absolutely indifferent to
certain animal tragedy as the natural contin- him. The animal offers Treadwell unconditional
gency of anti-nature that resists our symbolic hospitality neither with call, contract, control,
explication. Through Treadwell, Herzog sees nor with property, protection, or precondition.
this permanent crisis of nature as its own In fact, it is not that the grizzly man invites
homeostasis which blocks any sentimentalized grizzlies to his home but that he is accepted
politics of nature. And despite his well-arranged and nurtured in their home (called a national
narration, Herzog’s symbolic language is more park), which he visits without invitation.
into the ecstatic truth of this enigmatic nature Genuine hospitality is, then, that which can be
through ephiphanic images of animals and only recognized, retroactively, by the visitor
thus much less rationalist than Lacan’s formu- and not the inviter, in an exceptional state
lations of antiphusis as barring the Symbolic, where there is actually no host/guest power
that is, as still conceptualized in relation to structure. Derrida also suggests “a hospitality
culture (Noys 49).8 In passing, Wolfe argues of visitation rather than invitation,” adding
that Žižek treats the animal as a mere metonymy that the visit might actually be very dangerous,
for the Lacanian Real and thus his approach is but “a hospitality without risk, a hospitality
also still anthropocentric without thinking the backed by certain assurances, a hospitality pro-
“distribution” of subjectivity across species tected by an immune system against the wholly
lines (Wolfe 125). But what kind of subjectivity other” could not be true hospitality (Habermas
could be distributed to the animal if not and Derrida 162). This true hospitality is again

145
animal and technology

almost impossible to realize whereas its signifi- as a naked man who can shape-shift into an
cance may lie in that it serves as the conceptual animal, must be the very shaman-tiger that
ideal of actual tolerance, if not perfect, still undoubtedly devoured him. A baboon tells
needed in reality – for Derrida, le don absolu Keng in an animal language (subtitled) to kill
is also like the impossible ground on which the lonesome tiger to free it from its world, or
actual exchange economy is enabled just as to let it devour him to enter its world. But all
ungraspable différance catalyzes any system of this weird setting does not imply the mere
concrete differences. Yet we can go further anthropocentric antagonism between animal
than this conceptual justification of pure hospi- and human, nature and civilization. Rather,
tality or gift on the human’s side if we posit the the jungle appears as what Charles Baudelaire
visitor not as the host but as the guest of animal called “forests of symbols” which correspond
hospitality in a zone of indeterminacy between to each other, with a Heideggerian “clearing,”
subject and object. Visitation would thus be an open empty space of the forest where Being
viewed as an ethical adventure of abandoning is unconcealed. At the end, Keng encounters
one’s subjectivity as a host, becoming a volun- the tiger in the dark, which has been watching
teer homo sacer who can be killed without him like the gaze from the Real before his sight-
being sacrificed in anti-nature, and finding ing of it (see Figs 1, 2). Perching on a tree, it
oneself to be in an unprepared and unexpected stares directly forward with its calm, fixed,
hospitality without any symmetrical exchange silent sublimity, evoking the bottomless,
or companionship with the other. Does this unreadable, impassive gaze of Derrida’s cat.
not suggest an ethics that is not responsible And just as naked Derrida feels ashamed in
for the other as a vulnerable sufferer but respon- front of his naked pet and yet realizes that the
sive to the other as a pure gift? A truly ethical binary of naked/clothed itself is humanist,
act might be to accept the other’s being in improper to the animal for which the notion of
itself as a gift to me in the realization that it is nudity does not exist, so Keng feels first
I who is vulnerable and thus virtually accepted fearful and undressed, but then disarmed and
by the very other, gifted its unintended opened to the tiger that does not appear to be
hospitality. simply a bestial enemy to hunt. The animal
Brilliant in this regard is Tropical Malady gaze destabilizes the frame of nature vs.
(2004) by Thai director Apichatpong Weera- culture and seemingly addresses the man in an
sethakul, whose locality depicted in a surreal unheard inhuman voice, which Derrida com-
as well as hyperrealist (often documentary- pares to God’s calling (The Animal That There-
looking) style has opened a new territory of fore I Am 17–18).
world cinema. The film consists of the first But rather than tracing back to Judeo-Chris-
half showing a shy gay couple Tong and tian theology, we could see here the thickly con-
Keng’s euphoric meanderings mostly in a city cealed face of the tiger representing neither a
and the second half unfolding in the jungle vulnerable other to save nor a hostile other to
into which Tong suddenly disappears and subdue, but an inert interface to a world larger
Keng jumps to trace his lost love. This abrupt than human, the Virtual immanent in the
spatial shift is also temporal, marked by the Actual in Deleuze’s terms, the “plane of imma-
audacious intermission of a ten-minute blank nence” to which Keng whispers: “I give you my
screen that looks as though “time is out of spirit, my flesh, and my memories … Every
joint.” It ruptures the present, while opening drop of my blood sings our song, a song of hap-
its subsisting past in itself, the mythical piness.” Of course there is no inter-species dia-
memory of the world retained in the jungle. logue; Keng’s giving of himself would rather
There, it is narrated that a folkloric shaman indicate his acceptance of the animal gaze as
has transformed himself into a tiger and is ter- an unplanned invitation to nature, his response
rorizing the countryside that Keng’s army pro- (without responsibility) to unbounded hospital-
tects. In effect, Tong, appearing in the jungle ity from the universe that offers a chance to

146
jeong

Fig. 1. The tiger in the dark, which has been watching Keng. Still from Tropical Malady (dir. Apichat-
pong Weerasethakul 2004).

Fig. 2. The moment at which Keng encounters the tiger. Still from Tropical Malady (dir. Apichatpong
Weerasethakul 2004).

undress his civilized identity and join an imme- from society (Agamben) and becoming stripped
morial world. Far from creating a romantic of humanity in front of the naked animal
happy ending, this hospitality invites him to a (Derrida) but also becoming desubjectified in
radical dissolution or liberation of subjectivity Deleuze’s terms. Though Keng kneels down
into a primordial zone where animal and and moves like a beast, this gesture may not
human, body and spirit, matter and memory signal the imitation of an individual organism
are all indeterminate in deindividuated happi- so much as a life-changing line of flight from
ness. “When species meet,” the human now the (Oedipalizing) organization of subjectivity
thus tries no longer befriending animals but towards “the marvelous of a non human life”
experiences “becoming-animal” in multiple on the plane of immanence (Deleuze and Guat-
senses: not only becoming a bare life detached tari 231–34).

147
animal and technology

Furthermore, as his face loses its identity in 1972), molecule-like rats inundating a vampire’s
the dark jungle, just like the tiger immersed in coffin and town (Nosferatu 1979) … Herzog’s
darkness, becoming-animal involves becoming politics of the animal, if any, certainly disturbs
part of the environment where animality and anthropocentrism (Sheehan). At this point,
humanity become indistinct in their molecular however, we should note that, rather than
state. The tiger is virtually “apparent without being liberating, these animals often represent
appearing,” like the “phasmid,” that stick the remnants of anti-nature, a dead end of mys-
insect that Georges Didi-Huberman describes tical romanticism where the sublime adventure
whose body perfectly resembles twigs or leaves of surpassing humanity fails or faces death. In
so as to incorporate rather than imitate its effect, the encounter with animals does not
environment (Didi-Huberman 15–20). And as always and literally lead to radical molecular
its etymology shows, the phasmid implies “phan- desubjectification, which is practically infeas-
tasm” and “apparition” between being and non- ible. We therefore need to review Deleuze’s
being that can in a trice mutate into a dangerous anarchic becoming-animal in terms of the
beast, devouring us into the abyss that effaces all more or less actual potential to transform
ontological boundaries. Likewise, the shaman- socially organized subjectivity through contact
tiger, a human-animal that devoured Tong, is with animals. This contact occurs in liminal
about to devour Keng’s body or at least eat his space where one’s life becomes “bare” in the
soul, lurking like a ghost-shadow in the dark.9 first place, as in Apichatpong’s jungle – his
Now, the ontology of the animal takes on the Uncle Boonmee Who Can Recall His Past
hauntology of the ghost, and the threshold Lives (2010) shows not a beast but a ghost in
between the human and these ontological the jungle, a human phasmid that reincarnates
others appears all the more fatal because its the world’s memory of itself. The cave is
transgression entails the complete surrender of another significant place where the animal and
the master’s position. But again, this risk- the ghost reside in the Apichatpong films; one
taking visitation to the matrix of others would may recall the cave-looking Zone in Andrei Tar-
be the ecstatic price of dismantling rigidified kovsky’s Stalker (1979) too, where those who
humanist subjectivity. Keng enters the enter it enter their own unconscious reverie
uncanny realm of immanent connectedness to and desire. Slightly differently, Herzog’s Cave
the animal, the ghost, namely all virtual life, of Forgotten Dreams (2010) deserves attention,
becoming imperceptible and clandestine like a 3D documentary on the Chauvet caves of
them. In short, becoming-animal exercises the Southern France containing the oldest known
ethical act of embracing the animal as gifted. pictorial creations of humankind. Painted
Through its indifferent hospitality man does 32,000 years ago, these first frescos bear
not so much become an animal as disintegrate evidence of primitives’ life surrounded by
into the virtual grounding of all actual beings. animals to watch, hunt, fight, tame, admire,
play with, and so on. Notable are some of
them depicting the transformation of human
reinforcing subjectivity through bodies into, or hybridization with, animals,
which seemingly expresses more than species
becoming-other companionship. That is, what are represented
In light of this context, one could draw on in the cave – humankind’s first cultural space
Herzog whose films abound with animals: a cat – are actually people’s bare life and their
witnessing to people like Derrida’s pet (Heart fantasy of animal life, with the boundary of
of Glass 1976), domestic animals resisting culture and nature blurring. The initial desire
human mastery (Woyzeck 1979), decayed for becoming-animal, if we still use this term,
corpses of horses scattered in the desert (Fata is imaginatively figured here, not disfiguring
Morgana 1971), monkeys besieging a quixotic but refiguring humanity and thus prefiguring
hero’s broken raft (Aguirre, Wrath of God its reinforcement through animality in the

148
jeong

form of a new species like the cyborg. Even if not destroy the organic form of life. Rather,
still unrealistic or futuristic, the upgrading humanity is mutated in mimetic ways of becom-
reterritorialization of human subjectivity via ing different organisms, which lets us imagine
non-human others has indeed been more palp- new potentials of retooling our being, often in
ably imagined and envisioned than its radical conjunction with technology.12
deterritorialization since the era of the The spectrum of this organic change and its
caveman.10 implication is, however, wide. If becoming-
It is therefore possible to take the opposite other in The Falls is radical but comical, thus
direction of visitation to nature as deindividua- somewhat lightly treated, it is seriously staged
tion, a direction in which humans can embody as a fictive yet painful process in Black Swan
ontological others, now including the machine (Darren Arnofsky 2010), for instance. The
that takes the place of the animal in technologi- story is simple: Nina is a perfect ballerina for
cal civilization. This turn may be less an anti- the White Swan with innocence and grace, but
thetic reversion to anthropocentrism than a Lily is better for the Black Swan with guile
dialectic reaction to the environment in which, and sensuality. They compete to be the
as Wolfe says, subjectivity could be distributed heroine of Swan Lake who must play both the
across species lines and thus reconfigured even roles, while this rivalry expands into a twisted
into certain, unprecedented species. Let us friendship that provokes Nina to discover and
briefly recollect Peter Greenaway’s fake docu- explore her dark side of violence and sexuality.
mentary The Falls (1980) that presents ninety- Obviously we see a variation of the Jekyll &
two victims of the Violent Unknown Event Hyde motif in an Oedipal/Electra triangle:
(VUE), which has caused immortality, disabil- Nina’s unconscious desire repressed under her
ity, and ninety-two new peculiar languages. mother-superego’s suffocating control explodes
Among the victims whose surnames begin through her uncanny double Lily and her artis-
with the letters FALL are those who really tic director who is a seductive father figure; yet
“fall” from buildings and Icarus-style her inner Black Swan’s power becomes so
homemade wings, a prosthetic device for uncontrollable that it finally engulfs her White
becoming-animal. Such symptoms of man’s Swan ego, destroying her body. What attracts
metamorphosis into bird recall the hubristic us to this perverted family drama with its
ambition of flying, suggesting the VUE as a typical black-and-white Hollywood moral is
modern Babel myth about the end of civilization Nina’s extreme desire to imitate the Black
(the title also invokes fallout).11 Despite the Swan, the desire for an artistic ideal that is orig-
apocalyptic scenarios it introduces, however, inally impossible to realize but virtually imma-
The Falls is not a Stanley Kubrick-style black nent in her unconscious. The finale visualizes
comedy or a dystopian science fiction. The all realistic details in which she embodies the
VUE, the attack of the Real, brings about a character in the form of becoming-animal; her
somewhat jovial disorder of all human systems body transforms into a black swan as if this
and causes new hybrid changes to human animal inside her casts off its superficial
bodies. That is, the apocalypse was perhaps human skin. But this process turns out to be
the VUE itself, time was already out of joint, hallucinatory, as the audience in the diegetic
and what the film shows is a post-apocalyptic space only sees Nina’s perfect performance
new world that reassembles subjectifying appa- without bodily change. In other words, the
ratuses by producing diverse languages, Real of becoming-animal appears only in the
changes of sex, identity, and skin, physical form of fantasy, and its discrepancy from
deformities, and even a dog’s becoming-bird. reality indicates the unbridgeable fissure of sub-
Such a collective schizophrenia partakes of jectivity in itself. This immanent fissure would
Deleuze and Guattari’s revolutionary disorgan- open the subject’s primordial “body without
ization of the entire solidified actuality, but mul- organs,” what Deleuze and Guattari term the
tiple modes and actions of becoming-animal do molecular matrix of any potential organism

149
animal and technology

prior to being organized, yet what the film shows radical passivity, “a forced, ecstatic abjection,
is not this unrepresentable body but Nina as a form of captivation” (Shaviro 49).13 This
split into two identifiable bodies, human and process entails the sensation of touch as ground-
animal. The fantasy is then all the more ing self-transformation. The hero changes into a
painful as it perfectly mimics the organic form “video-activated body,” becoming ever more
of a single animal, betraying the failure of biotechnologically transgressive. The slit on
becoming-animal in reality. his belly becomes a slot for videocassettes, a
This animal mimesis deserves more examin- link between surface (skin, retina, image
ation. It is iconic in that Nina resembles the screen) and volume (convoluted thick entrails),
Black Swan and this animal is not real but and a vaginal orifice indicating his feminization,
fictive, so the cinematic depiction of her as “interfaces between biology and technology
bodily transformation is basically a digital run amok” (142–44). The embodied desire for
version of the caveman’s painting of animal– radical tactility ultimately turns his hand into
human hybrids; the animal icon is a simulacrum a techno-fleshed pistol, whose trigger he pulls
produced by the cutting-edge computer technol- on himself at the end. That is, he destroys the
ogy. However, it looks indexical as well in that tactile body that blocks him from completely
Nina’s body not only becomes visually similar joining the other on TV and its virtual world
to a swan in appearance but also physically of videodrome; like Nina, he is stuck between
incorporates the animal’s color, shape, skin – actual and virtual bodies. One could say that
the causal traces of her actual connection to his intensive experience of the other on screen
material animality – into the iconic simulation. reaches the impossibility of becoming the
What matters more than the film’s visual rep- other within the possibility of becoming a mech-
resentation of the swan is Nina’s tactile presen- anical interface to the videodrome; thus, becom-
tation of it, the bodily performativity of ing-other is possible only as becoming-interface,
becoming-animal which may be all the more which implies becoming-abject in society.
dangerous than Treadwell’s adventure because Despite the dystopian mood of the film, this
of the lack of distance between Nina’s and the technological bare life ends up forever floating
swan’s bodies. This sensational corporeality as an immaterial ghost image in the videodrome
makes her becoming-other as risky as wanted, as if Max were liberated from his gendered,
and ultimately more passive than active. Her socialized mortality. The final manifesto
self-centered desire for the swan turns into “Death to videodrome; long live the new
(and out to be) the other-centered desire that flesh!” sounds like this: Death to the interface;
forces her to become it out of her control; she long live the techno-body! We now need haun-
is swept by monstrosity inside her that is more tology of technology.
than she is. In short, there is a double ambivalence: the
This dialectics of active and passive is salient subject’s apparent aggressivity towards the
in David Cronenberg’s work, whose films have screen-body entails his passive transformation
provocatively incorporated the machine along into an interface, and this becoming-interface
with the animal into the human body. Video- entails both abjection and liberation as well as
drome (1983) now looks like a precursor to regression and transgression. This ambivalence
Black Swan: on the border between reality concerns bio-ontology at large in Cronenberg’s
and hallucination, Max, a mediaholic man, lit- films such as Scanners (1981), The Fly (1986),
erally penetrates a woman’s vulva-like mouth and Dead Ringers (1988), wherein the human
on TV, but this phallocentric aggression is body embodies parasite alterity in forms of
none other than the submission to the screen- other minds or even the non-human. Becom-
body that seduces and sucks the spectator, ing-other, biological or technological, is
replacing visual distance with tactile proximity. nothing other than this becoming-parasite that
In analyzing this film, Steven Shaviro argues puts the subject in the double bind between
that the passion for the image is not far from self and other. Radically dispossessed and

150
jeong

decentered, subjectivity remains all the more moreover the fusion of both fiction and lived
vulnerable and constrained so that its “schizo- reality, but first and foremost a cybernetic
phrenic dislocation” involves “bizarre distor- organism, that is, a(ny) self-making organic
tions and topographical transformations of life as an autopoietic system of feedback
physical, corporeal, and social space” (Shaviro through other organisms in the environment.
117). In a broader history, the evolution of In this sense an animal, a machine, just like a
this body transformation on screen could be man, is all more or less cyborgian (cybernetics
traced this way, following Shaviro’s cue: (1) has combined biology with mechanics); the
Buster Keaton’s body combined with machines cyborg in SF is a technologically externalized
represents early capitalist mechanism, practical form of this cybernetic mechanism immanent
materialism, subversive Dadaism; (2) Jerry in the environment and shared by various organ-
Lewis’s body reflects late capitalist simulation, isms. Then one’s connection to this cybernetic
multiple and pulverized mass media images; network could be governed in order to build
(3) Cronenberg’s body reembodies the late capi- up oneself without being disorganized there.
talist technology of disembodied information Nina in Black Swan could have been upgraded
and algorithm by morphing into hybrid, corpor- into a more powerful female subject – even as a
eal interfaciality, dismantling old dichotomies femme fatale – through her becoming-animal
of mind/matter, male/female, and human/ without leading to death; through the use of
inhuman to show the unshowable monstrous CGI, her sensual transformation even looks
ambivalence between fascination and disgust. like the birth of a sexy cyborg, evoking the
The Cartesian–Hegelian epistemology that female robot in Metropolis (Fritz Lang 1927).
interrupts immediate embodiment based on Most Hollywood films externalize such embo-
the opposition between active subject and died hybridity in the simplistic negative form
passive object now gives way to a fatal phenom- of separate antagonistic species, mainly updat-
enology of embodiment: dangerous passivity is ing the classical Frankenstein motifs: the
open to “a Bataillean ecstasy of expenditure, human hubris of becoming a creator and the
of automutilation and self-abandonment – subsequent anxiety over technology. Suffice it
neither Imaginary plenitude nor Symbolic to recall the war between the machine and the
articulation, but the blinding intoxication of human in the Terminator series; in the place
contact with the Real” (54). of the machine, the Planet of the Apes series
The question is then: can there be any posi- positions an upgraded animal species. This
tive contact with others that reinforces subjec- type of dystopian global cinema obsessively
tivity in the actual rather than renouncing it? depicts the dominance of ontological others in
How can one productively transform oneself the wake of global catastrophes as the inevitable
through otherness while not being entrapped outcome of triumphant (biotechnological)
in schizophrenic fantasy, the failure of becom- modernization.
ing-other or impasse of the Real? Going back By extension, finally, Avatar (James
to Haraway, we should recall her “Cyborg Mani- Cameron 2009), however, serves as a counterex-
festo” that declares we are all theorized and fab- ample that envisions a technological future of
ricated hybrids of machine and organism nature with an animal cyborg introduced. In
(Haraway, “Cyborg Manifesto” 150). Her fact, this groundbreaking digital 3D science
usage of the futuristic buzzword “cyborg” is fiction with a clichéd narrative has been a
metaphorical in an attempt to challenge natural- target of postcolonial criticism: on a green
ism and essentialism so that feminists can break planet called Pandora (evoking the mythical
away from Oedipal narratives and Christian West), the blue humanoid Na’vi fight human
origin myths like Genesis. She thus sounds invaders (just as American Indians resisted
somewhat Deleuzian, but more important gold-rushing white colonizers), led by a white
appears to be the multiple implication of cybor- male hero outcast from his own race in order
gism: it means the human–machine hybrid, to save the ethnic Na’vi community while

151
animal and technology

getting (if not marrying) a beautiful local prin- interfaces have actually been increasingly incor-
cess – Žižek, among others, blames the film’s porated into the body in this order: punch
multiculturalist stance for being invertedly card, mouse, touchpad, touch screen, gesture
racist (Žižek, “Return of the Natives”). sensing, voice recognition, and forthcoming
However, such criticism repeats the aforemen- Brain–Computer Interfaces that one can
tioned hermeneutic frame of reading allegory. control through cerebral stimulation, as does
What is missing is the film’s surface level on Jake, the hero of Avatar. Input devices for
which we see not the reincarnation of the the cybernetic feedback loop thus tend to
apache and cowboys but unprecedented amal- come into the body. If material interfaces,
gams of human and animal on the one side, including Jake’s coffin-like pod to plug in his
and of human and machine on the other. The avatar, are still external to the human body,
human and the Na’vi literally become part of interfaces are indeed internalized for the
mechanical- and animal-vehicle-weapons as Na’vi. Their braided hair functions as an embo-
more than external tools. The soldiers do not died interface: its terminus, or its “digit” if we
simply operate thirteen-foot-tall robots that want, consisting of sensitive tendrils are neural
they ride by means of buttons or joysticks; links able to mesh with other Na’vi and other
rather, their muscular action itself is amplified sentient creatures as living interfaces such as
into the robot’s physical movement just as a flying dragons (which make a one-to-one bond
child plays at being a windmill or train by with a Na’vi) and trees of souls (which also
moving its whole body. That is, they indexi- have biological USB-like links). The Na’vi’s
cally embody the machine by performing sensori-motor capability is maximized, with
what Walter Benjamin calls the “mimetic no artificial mediation, when connected to this
faculty”: not the visual or linguistic imitation empowering fauna and flora. Pandora is a
that maintains a certain transcendent distance Bio-Internet on which embodied interfaces
from the object, but the tactile incorporation upload and download data-memories electro-
that eclipses such abstraction (Benjamin). chemically, as the roots of the trees communi-
This sensational assimilation of the other is cate with each other like the synapses
more organic between the Na’vi and the between neurons. A “global village” is fully
animal, as their bodies are so seamlessly fleshed out in this natural network whose
coupled that the animal looks less like a mechanism resonates with the historical shift
useful prosthetic device than like an empow- from modern mechanics to postmodern bio-
ered human itself. In other words, the technology (Rosenfeld).
animal-vehicle is not the natural opposite of In this background Jake’s shift from the
the machine-vehicle but its higher version human-machine to human-animal side
with regard to the human’s embodiment of suggests that animality is not prior or inferior
ontological otherness. to technology but rather posterior or superior.
Notably, the army’s control center is full of Pandora reflects not so much the nostalgic past
high-tech human–computer interfaces, malle- of pure nature as a lost paradise but an ideal-
able and multilayered digital screens that ized future of planetary intelligence with
operate on the human digit’s touch and thus embodied interfaces towards which current
reduce the gap between the image and its human civilization is oriented. The sacred
viewer, who thus becomes a user, player, and Hometree called the Unobtanium might be
conductor of digital interfaces.14 This tactile not merely a post-oil energy source or primi-
indication of information thereby enhances tive shamanistic center but literally and figura-
the embodiment of technological interfaces, tively a power “plant” that generates the
resonating with contemporary spectatorship in network of rhizomatically interconnected
haptic cinema, installation art, interactive interfaces.15 Jake’s adventure would be no
games that rearticulate eye and hand, sight other than changing his network to a more
and touch, and vision and body. Computer evolved one. He lives a biological bare life as

152
jeong

a result of his paraplegia, and even becomes terrorism (Galloway and Thacker), Avatar
socially bare after “betraying his own race,” seems to reflect this reality in the near-future
which suspends his political subjectivity as a global frame of eco-ethical networking and
human soldier. But the Na’vi accept him posthuman bio-informatics. Pandora is not
with hospitality, and he himself becomes a unobtainable, but already immanent on our
gift to a Na’vi woman and her entire commu- planet.
nity. Since the Na’vi are not indifferent
animals but emotional humans, this gifting in
zooesis and technesis
positive reciprocity finally leads to Jake’s res-
toration of political subjectivity through his We have gone through a series of contemporary
resurrection as a more upgraded human, a films broadly in two directions so far. First, it is
member of the Na’vi community. The more fundamentally ethical to accept (or visit)
“virtual reality” interface to his avatar disap- the animal not as a vulnerable other but as a hos-
pears behind the embodied interface of a real pitable gift, and thereby open human subjectiv-
Na’vi that he becomes. ity to liberation in the natural environment.
The dilemma is life’s total dependence on the Second, on the contrary, human subjectivity
network without which it cannot be sustained. can be reconfigured and reinforced through
Individual subjectivity is guaranteed only contact with ontological others, including the
through deindividuation into monadic agencies machine in the technological environment.
acting on, and reacting to, interfaces. From Dangerous anti-nature beyond anthropocentr-
another perspective, an individual is a parasite ism in the former takes the form of terroristic
to the host network site, even when he or she catastrophe immanent in the networked
uses prosthetic interfaces from it. Rather than system of the latter. Ontological otherness
a war between good nature and evil civilization, resides in such an environment as challenging
Avatar might show the process by which this and transforming our being. In this context,
vast host fights, defeats, and repels humans as we will need to go through both zooesis – by
an army of antagonistic parasites like virulent which Una Chaudhuri means the discourse on
viruses or terrorists. Here, we see the verso of the animal – and technesis – Mark Hansen’s
Pandora even though Eywa, “the earth term for the discourse on technology – in
Mother,” is the metaphysical Soul that colors general in their combination, so as to better
this eco-utopia with harmonious wholeness and map and address the global cinema of ontologi-
spiritual plenitude. Anti-nature within nature cal others. Inspired by Alice Jardin’s critique
now takes the form of global complexity imma- of gynesis, a reduction of woman in the
nent in the very networked system itself. service of phallogocentric theory, Chaudhuri
Because of the global connection, even small, criticizes the way the animal is viewed in
local damage to the network affects all its para- zooesis and proposes artistic ecology beyond
site-members like a global catastrophe, just as anthropocentrism (Chaudhuri and Enelow).
all animals rush to help the endangered Na’vi, More complexly, Hansen argues that even post-
receiving the Jake-avatar’s SOS at the end. In modern technesis reduces the radical external-
other words, this last-minute rescue results ity and concrete materiality of technology to a
less from animals’ companionship with the mere material support for instrumentality, tex-
Na’vi than from the nature-network’s self-regu- tuality, subject constitution, or social organiz-
lation and self-protection to maintain its homeo- ation (Hansen).16 Like the animal, technology
stasis. The double side of networking is that the is subversive to traditional thought, yet its
more connected we are, the more contaminated exteriority is relativized (i.e., the technology
we may be; the more subjective we are, the more of writing; the actualized form of the Real or
subject to others we can be; and the more holis- Virtual) through the ontogenetic mechanism
tic the network is, the more holes for terrorists it of différance, becoming, etc. What Hansen
might have. If it is true that networks create pursues is, then, the absolute exteriority of

153
animal and technology

technology that conditions our “noncognitive world. This zone thus exists like an eco-onto-
and nondiscursive affective bodily life” as logical heterotopia, to use Michel Foucault’s
embodied in Benjamin’s practice of mimetic term, whose identity is not anchored in our
faculty (21–30).17 society but exists only in the exceptional state
Reserving further discussion for a later of temporary potential to depoliticize or repoli-
chance, let me just point out that zooesis and ticize any humanistic politics.
technesis will continue to be updated in a dialec- Movie going is a visitation to
tic struggle to overcome their own limits. For, this zone of ontological others
simply, we cannot help reframe our ontological where we are ultimately invited
others in the symbolic discourse. But we also to revisit our own being in the
have the image beside language, especially the world.
cinematic image that never stops the movement
of confronting us with the outside of any linguis-
tic frame. It deserves noting here that cinema is notes
in essence the amalgam of animality and tech-
1 The common sense that nature is followed by
nology: first, still images are animated, their culture is reversed here, but this reversion does
mobility underlies the foundational “move- not imply the anthropocentric hierarchy that
ment-image” that keeps opening narrative culture is superior to nature. Recollect Jacques
space in Deleuze’s term, and its genre format Derrida’s deconstruction of this hierarchy:
is called animation; second, this motion is pro- culture is a differed-differing nature just as speech
duced by the cinematic apparatus, stored in is another writing that is différée and différante; ulti-
the archive of images, which forges and mately, différance underlies any conceptual opposi-
remains an artificial intelligence of the world. tion which thereby turns out to be the “theoretical
It is no coincidence that the zoopraxicope, a fiction” (Derrida, Marges de la philosophie 18–25).
Our view of reality including nature and culture
pre-cinematic device for displaying motion pic-
is itself a constructed fiction, an ideological
tures, created the illusion of animals running
fantasy whose anthropocentricism is hardly recog-
inside rotating glass disks, and its inventor Ead- nized, yet always immanent in our daily life.
weard Muybridge’s photographic work on
animal locomotion set the history of the 2 As Una Chaudhuri and Marina Zurkow say,
moving image in motion. Since its inception, beloved animals in our pet culture are
coddled and pampered at home, shown off and
cinema has indeed functioned as an imaginary
admired in the street, invited to intimate places,
zoo for animals reentering vision and a
given catchy names and special diets, and thus nor-
scientific laboratory for futures coming in malized in civic and domestic space. By contrast,
motion. And as aforementioned, the ontological when not belonging with humans, animals are
nature of the cinematic image is ontologically made to disappear, are eradicated, excluded, or
other than the living or dead: animate but insub- forgotten.
stantial, visual but intangible, spectacular but
3 Antonia Levi examines “the werewolf in the
unreal. Before there is ghost film, film itself is
crested Kimono” in comparison with its Western
a ghost.18 counterpart, looking at other Japanese anime/
A final note should be about the human’s manga works too: Phoenix: the Sun (Tezuka
ontological hybridity as a futuristic but imma- Osamu 1986), Wolf’s Rain (Nobumoto Keiko
nent a-venir of the inevitable evolution of bio- 2005), InuYasha (Takahashi Rumiko 2004), etc.
technics and interface culture. Animality and
4 Adrian Johnston consults Lacan’s several semi-
technology no longer form a naı̈ve dichotomy
nars of the 1970s, which must have influenced
of nature vs. civilization but connect with Žižek’s idea on nature even when he does not
each other in ways of making more visible the refer to Lacan (Žižek, “Nature and its Discon-
posthuman condition of life. It unfolds in a tents”). Below, we will ask whether the Lacan–
cinematic “zone” that now goes global, an illu- Žižek line doesn’t still conceptualize the Real of
sory clearing for bare life within the globalized nature only in view of the symbolic and thus

154
jeong

cultural frame, but for now I take their schema as a the sense of normal cinematic illusory space
channel to the other side of “our” nature. without using stereoscopic technology) is also
found in Tropical Malady, just after Keng encoun-
5 These interpretations were common in the ters the tiger: a low-angle panning of the 3D
1970s–1980s when film theory first and foremost actual forest connects with a horizontal tracking
borrowed structuralist semiotics and classical psy- shot of the 2D painted forest depicting the
choanalysis centering on Freud’s Oedipal triangle legend of a tiger stretching out its long tongue to
and early Lacan’s mirror stage (Rose; Bergstrom; a praying man as if to try to devour him. The
Bellour). point is that becoming-animal is in any event still
6 She draws on a broad sense of American prag- virtual, only iconically imagined, while always
matist tradition, including such scholars and scien- inspiring the human (to create “virtual reality” in
tists as Gregory Bateson, Jane Goodall, Marc which it is possible).
Bekoff, Babara Smuts, and Lynn Margulis. 11 Such eschatological concerns provoke nonsen-
Obviously, animal studies in this theoretical back- sical conspiracy theories on the event. For
ground repeats and updates the old dichotomy of example, one of the victims “Obsian Fallicut had
Continental and analytic philosophy. a theory that the VUE was an expensive elaborate
7 In a full review of the film, I pointed out this hoax perpetuated by A.J. Hitchcock to give some
unnoticed paradox which also resonates with credibility to the unsettling and unsatisfactory
Herzog’s ambivalent attitude to Treadwell, attrac- ending of his film, The Birds.”
tion and distanciation (Jeong and Andrew). 12 I somewhere else took an emphatically Deleu-
8 At the end of his essay on Herzog’s antiphusis, zian perspective on this film (Jeong 183–84), but
Benjamin Noys expresses a certain anxiety about now slightly modify the view. It must be noted in
the dehistoricization of this nature into mysticism, passing that Greenaway has also created a cine-
and argues: “To begin to restore a politics of nature matic zoo with diverse animals screened, as seen
involves the restoration of a signifier, and what in A Zed & Two Noughts (1986; which means
Herzog provides are the images that call for the “zoo”), among others, though we do not have
re-inscription of the signifier of nature” (Noys space for their analyses here.
50). But this need for the Symbolic would be 13 Vivian Sobchack also discusses the double
only regressively abstract unless it rather goes meaning of passion, “passive suffering” and “active
beyond the very political frame of reducing the devotion,” embodied by both Jesus Christ and
impenetrability of anti-nature to simply ahistorical Videodrome. On the level of prereflective and
mysticism. passive material, “passive suffering” engages us
with “response-ability,” and “active devotion”
9 An interesting literary reference: at the end of
with “sense-ability”; on the level of reflective and
Henry James’s short story “The Beast in the
active consciousness, these correspond to the
Jungle,” an uncanny bestial face bursts out of such
ethical and aesthetical concepts of “responsibility”
darkness towards the hero as if it figures his
and “sensibility” (Sobchack 288–90). Returning to
hidden past, his unconscious memory. If the
our reformulation of ethics, we could say that
animal is a physical other of the human body, the
the ethics of responsibility for the vulnerable
ghost is a psychological other of the human spirit
other is less fundamental than the ethics of respon-
like one’s repressed double. The animal appears
siveness to the hospitable other.
in space and nature; the ghost returns through
time and memory. 14 Not only such cutting-edge interfaces but also
characters’ operation of them are a cinematic spec-
10 Notably, Herzog’s 3D image that maximizes
tacle and an attractive show in recent SF films
the “indexical” nature of the cinema – the image
including Minority Report (Steven Spielberg 2002)
as the physical proof of real objects – looks both
Déjà vu (Tony Scot 2006), and Iron Man 2 (Jon
excessive and insufficient. For what it captures in
Favreau 2010).
enhanced spatial illusion is the cave’s 2D wall
with painted “icons” of fictive animal-humans, and 15 Ken Hillis points out that the green network of
not their actual 3D entity. A similar dimensional global Pandora has been envisioned through such
shift from 3D indexicality to 2D iconicity (3D in models as World Brain (H.G. Wells), electronic

155
animal and technology

noosphere (Teilhard de Chardin), Hive Mind (Kevin Chaudhuri, Una, and Shonni Enelow. “Animalizing
Kelly), electronic hyperbody (Pierre Lévy), etc. Performance, Becoming-Theatre: Inside Zooesis
Why not Google? with the Animal Project at NYU.” Theatre Topics
16.1 (2006): 1–17. Web. 30 Dec. 2011.
16 That is: instrumentality (Heidegger’s Zuhan-
denheit (handiness) concerns the usefulness of Chaudhuri, Una, and Marina Zurkow. “Zoöpolis.”
the tool), textuality (Derrida’s différance operates Web. 20 Aug. 2010.
the text as machine), subject constitution (Lacan’s
Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. A Thousand
objet a often appears in mass media as technologi-
Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia. Trans. Brian
cal effect), and social organization (Deleuze’s
Massumi. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 1987. Print.
agencement means the assemblage of a social
machine). Derrida, Jacques. The Animal That Therefore I Am.
Ed. Marie-Louise Mallet. Trans. David Wills.
17 This critique seems arguable. Hansen (over)
New York: Fordham UP, 2008. Print.
interprets the “text” and “mass media” as the
clue to the “machine reduction of technology,” Derrida, Jacques. Given Time: I. Counterfeit Money.
though his quotes from Derrida and Lacan do not Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1992. Print.
even contain the word “technology.” He also
reduces any ontogenesis to his model of technesis, Derrida, Jacques. Marges de la philosophie. Paris:
when one may ask how his notion of material tech- Minuit, 1972. Print.
nology could be produced if not mechanically. Derrida, Jacques, and Anne Dufourmantelle. Of
18 Akira Lippit points out that psychoanalysis, Hospitality. Trans. Rachel Bowlsby. Stanford:
X-rays, and cinema all emerged in 1895, opening Stanford UP, 2000. Print.
the interiority of the mind, the body, and the Derrida, Jacques, and Bernard Stiegler.
world respectively. His term “avisuality” revolves Echographies of Television: Filmed Interviews. Trans.
around Derrida’s idea of spectrality of the image Jennifer Bajorek. Cambridge: Polity, 2002. Print.
(Lippit; Derrida and Stiegler).
Didi-Huberman, Georges. Phasmes: Essais sur
l’apparition. Paris: Minuit, 1998. Print.
bibliography Feil, Ken. Dying for a Laugh: Disaster Movies and the
Camp Imagination. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan UP,
Agamben, Giorgio. Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power
2005. Print.
and Bare Life. Trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen.
Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998. Print. Galloway, Alexander R., and Eugene Thacker. The
Exploit: A Theory of Networks. Minneapolis: U of
Bellour, Raymond. “System of a Fragment (on The
Minnesota P, 2007. Print.
Birds).” The Analysis of Film. Bloomington: Indiana
UP, 2000. 28–68. Print. Habermas, Jürgen, and Jacques Derrida. Philosophy in a
Time of Terror: Dialogues with Jürgen Habermas and
Benjamin, Walter. “On the Mimetic Faculty.”
Jacques Derrida. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2003. Print.
Reflections: Essays, Aphorisms, Autobiographical
Writing. Ed. Peter Demetz. Trans. Edmund Hansen, Mark B.N. Embodying Technesis: Technology
Jephcott. New York: Schocken, 1978. 333–36. Print. beyond Writing. Ann Arbor: U of Michigan P, 2000.
Print.
Bergstrom, Janet. “Enunciation and Sexual
Difference.” Feminism and Film Theory. Ed. Haraway, Donna J. “A Cyborg Manifesto.” The
Constance Penley. New York; London: Cybercultures Reader. Ed. David Bell and Barbara
Routledge; BFI, 1988. 159–85. Print. M. Kennedy. London: Routledge, 2000. 291–324.
Print.
Broglio, Ron, and Frederick Young. “The Coming
Non-human Community: A Conversation.” Art Haraway, Donna J. When Species Meet.
and Research 4.1 (2011): n. pag. Web. 5 Nov. 2011. Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2008. Print.
Butler, Judith. Precarious Life: The Powers of Hillis, Ken. “From Capital to Karma: James
Mourning and Violence. London and New York: Cameron’s Avatar.” Postmodern Culture 19.3
Verso, 2004. Print. (2009): n. pag. Web. 5 Jan. 2011.

156
jeong

Jameson, Fredric. Postmodernism, or, The Cultural Žižek, Slavoj. Looking Awry: An Introduction to Jacques
Logic of Late Capitalism. Durham, NC: Duke UP, Lacan through Popular Culture. Cambridge, MA: MIT
1991. Print. P, 1991. Print.
Jeong, Seung-hoon. “Systems on the Verge of Žižek, Slavoj. “Multiculturalism, or, The Cultural
Becoming Birds: Peter Greenaway’s Early Logic of Multinational Capitalism.” New Left
Experimental Films.” New Review of Film and Review 1.225 (1997): 28–51. Print.
Television Studies 9.2 (2011): 170–87. Print.
Žižek, Slavoj. “Nature and its Discontents.”
Jeong, Seung-hoon, and Dudley Andrew. “Grizzly SubStance 37.3 (2008): 37–72. Print.
Ghost: Herzog, Bazin and the Cinematic Animal.”
Žižek, Slavoj. “Return of the Natives.” New
Screen 49.1 (2008): 1–12. Print.
Statesman 4 Mar. 2010. Web. 28 Jan. 2011.
Johnston, Adrian. “Ghost of Substance Past:
Schelling, Lacan, and the Denaturalization of
Nature.” Lacan: The Silent Partners. Ed. Slavoj
Žižek. London and New York: Verso, 2006. 34–
55. Print.
Levi, Antonia. “The Werewolf in the Crested
Kimono: The Wolf–Human Dynamic in Anime
and Manga.” Mechademia 1 (2006): 145–60. Print.
Lippit, Akira Mizuta. Atomic Light (Shadow Optics).
Minneapolis: U of Minnesota P, 2005. Print.
Noys, Benjamin. “Antiphusis: Werner Herzog’s
Grizzly Man.” Film-Philosophy 11.3 (2007): 38–51.
Print.
Rancière, Jacques. “The Ethical Turn of Aesthetics
and Politics.” Aesthetics and its Discontents.
Cambridge: Polity, 2004. 109–32. Print.
Rose, Jacqueline. “Paranoia and the Film System.”
Feminism and Film Theory. Ed. Constance
Penley. New York; London: Routledge; BFI, 1988.
141–58. Print.
Rosenfeld, Kimberly N. “‘Terminator’ to ‘Avatar’:
A Postmodern Shift.” Jump Cut: A Review of
Contemporary Media 52 (2010): n. pag. Web. 5
Jan. 2011.
Shaviro, Steven. The Cinematic Body. Minneapolis: U
of Minnesota P, 1993. Print.
Sheehan, Paul. “Against the Image: Herzog and the
Troubling Politics of the Screen Animal.” SubStance
37.3 (2008): 117–36. Print.
Sobchack, Vivian. “The Passion of the Material:
Toward a Phenomenology of Interobjectivity.” Seung-hoon Jeong
Carnal Thoughts: Embodiment and Moving Image New York University Abu Dhabi
Culture. Berkeley: U of California P, 2004. PO Box 129188
286–318. Print. Abu Dhabi
Wolfe, Cary. What is Posthumanism? Minneapolis: U United Arab Emirates
of Minnesota P, 2010. Print. E-mail: seunghoon.jeong@nyu.edu
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

But knowing is far weaker than necessity.


Aeschylus

Stupidity is a scar […] [A]t the point where


its impulse is blocked a scar can easily be
left behind, a slight callous where the
surface is numb. Such scars lead to defor-
mations. bernard stiegler
Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer

∼ I believe you are very good. translated by daniel ross


∼ You are right, said the monster. But
besides being ugly, I have no sense [point
d’esprit]: I know I am only a beast.
∼ One is not a beast, replied Beauty, for DOING AND SAYING
believing they have no sense. That is what a
fool never knows. STUPID THINGS IN THE
Jeanne-Marie Leprince de Beaumont
TWENTIETH CENTURY
If they ask me whether such a man is not to bêtise and animality in
be reckoned an ass rather than a man, I
reply that I do not know.
deleuze and derrida
Spinoza

example, in making philosophical speeches in


“do we know who we ourselves
a political context where saying was doing,
are?” and letting happen, and even encouraging to

I n relation to responsibility, baseness, reason


and unreason, that is, both madness and stu-
pidity, the twentieth century would, in philos-
happen, for example in “The Self-Assertion of
the German University,” subtitled “Speech
given on taking solemn charge of the rectorate
ophy, be the century of the “great stupidity” of the University of Freiburg, May 27, 1933,”
of Heidegger – a Grosse Dummheit which has where Heidegger (before himself referring to
everything to do with the baseness of thinking Prometheus while forgetting his brother Epi-
referred to by Deleuze, and which, here, must metheus, the forgotten forgetful one who does
necessarily be related to horror – that which con- stupid things), asks: “But do we know who we
fronts humanity with the shame of being ourselves are, this body of teachers and students
human. of the highest school of the German people?”
What would this bêtise be – this “Grosse (Heidegger 5).
Dummheit”? It would consist in both saying There are times when to say is to do, and this
stupid things and doing stupid things – for is what John Austin called the performative

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010159-16 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783436

159
bêtise and animality

dimension of language. In certain circum- metamorphoses of critique into affirmation


stances, saying something does something to do not leave theoretical content untouched:
those one is addressing, and thereby creates a its truth evaporates […] the official spokes-
new situation: one’s speech is an action. men, who have other concerns, are liquidating
Jacques Derrida long meditated on this philoso- the theory to which they owe their place in the
sun before it has time to prostitute itself com-
phico-linguistic discovery by Austin, and we
pletely. (xv)
shall see that he relates the profession of profes-
sing proper to the university professor to this Progress (the Aufklärung understood as pro-
performativity. gress of reason) thus inverts its sign (through
I would like in the first place merely to point this prostitution and as rationalization): “pro-
out that in the case of performative utterances, gress is reverting to regression” (xviii).
saying something stupid amounts to doing The Aufklärung has failed and requires a leap,
something stupid, and that it is also and a jumpstart, because it has given up developing
especially for this reason that, today, the ques- the theoretical understanding of its reversing
tion of the responsibility of the university, or destiny, according to Adorno and Horkheimer:
of professors professing their profession (to
speak like Derrida in “The University without By leaving reflection of the destructive side of
Condition”) through more or less performative progress to its enemies […] the mysterious
statements, authorizing themselves from their willingness of the technologically educated
autonomy and their self-assertive sovereignty, masses to fall under the spell of any despot-
arises as never before. As never before: that is, ism, in its self-destructive affinity to national-
before knowledge began to move from “Pro- ist paranoia, in all this uncomprehended
senselessness the weakness of contemporary
methean” technics towards becoming technol-
theoretical understanding is evident. (xvi;
ogy, itself becoming the weapon of a global
translation modified; my emphasis)
economic war that is ruining the planet, and
which leads reason to self-destruction via the This theoretical weakness was present in 19471 –
“torrent of events” that Karl Polanyi refers to but it seems in 2011 to be even more present, and
in his book The Great Transformation. seems to be more present than ever in the eyes of
the younger generations, and not just to the
prostitution of theory, reification younger generation of philosophers trained in
France at the Ecole normale supérieure or in
and proletarianization
universities. This theoretical weakness, which
If regression (Rückschritt, to step back) is also seems present in “all classes of the popu-
induced by reason itself when it becomes ration- lation” (Marx and Engels 88), all afflicted by
alization (including that of mass death), leading to what I have analysed as systemic stupidity
“the tireless self-destruction of the Aufklärung” (Stiegler, What Makes Life Worth Living 22,
(Adorno and Horkheimer xiv), then this self- 131), has historically emerged from the prosti-
destruction (Selbstzertörung) rests for Adorno tution of the Aufklärung.
and Horkheimer on a prostitution of theory that This prostitution of reason and theory con-
denatures it and sends it into decadence: sists in making them serve rationalization, not
only as the secularization of society (in the
In the operations of modern science, the major
Weberian sense) but as legitimation, that is, as
discoveries are paid for with an increasing
rationalization in the sense of Ernest Jones and
decline of theoretical work, formation and
education. (xiv; translation modified) Sigmund Freud. And this inversion of sign,
through which reason leads to unreason, and
The eighteenth-century philosophy which […] progress to regression, is justified under the
put the fear of death into infamy, joined forces mask of reason itself, rationalization consisting
with it under Bonaparte […] Such in posing and in having accepted as a conclusion

160
stiegler

that “nothing can be done,” that is, that there is Regression thus forms a cocktail of ingenious
no alternative. stupidities that derive from cultural consumer-
This prostitution proceeds, moreover, from a ism.3 In a general way, however, stupidity or
vast subjugation of individuals to apparatus, Dummheit is a scar of desire 4 – of which
which induces a regression to minority affecting regression is precisely the return to its primor-
“all classes of the population,” deriving from dial stage, which is that of the drives.5
what Adorno and Horkheimer referred to as The fact that reason can regress and self-
reification (Verdinglichung), through which destruct, that is, lead to its opposite, which is
the economy (including today’s economy of “cog- unreason as stupidity or madness, is not
nitive capitalism”) disindividuates individuals: unique to our age: the “tendency toward self-
destruction has been inherent in rationality
The individual is entirely nullified in face of
from the first” (xix; my emphasis).
the economic powers […] While individuals
Stupidity is never foreign to knowledge:
as such are vanishing before the apparatus
they serve, they are provided for by that knowledge can itself become stupidity par excel-
apparatus and better than ever before. lence, so to speak. And this is so because knowl-
(Adorno and Horkheimer xvii) edge, and in particular theoretical knowledge as
passage to the act of reason – or more broadly,
What is here called “reification” refers to what I, noesis – only occurs intermittently to a noetic
along with Ars Industrialis – counter to the soul which constantly regresses, and which, as
dominant understanding of the discourse of such, is like Sisyphus, perpetually ascending
Marx and Engels – have tried to understand as the slope of its own stupidity, given that, as
a process of generalized proletarianization stated by Simonides and cited by Aristotle in
(on the basis of an interpretation of Marx by Metaphysics, “God alone enjoys this privilege”
Simondon [Du mode d’existence des objets tech- (982b), that is, the privilege of always being in
niques 15]), a process that liquidates all forms actuality, of never being stupid, of never
of knowledge, including and especially, today, going down the path of disindividuation, reifica-
theoretical knowledge (and not only savoir- tion and proletarianization.
faire and savoir-vivre, knowledge of how to do This is why not only can knowledge make
and how to live). thought base but it is essentially a matter of
This is the process of grammatization, and of its own baseness – always threatening, always
the proletarianization of thinking and of that the threat.
understanding which thus escapes reason,
that is, which escapes the “kingdom of ends”
(Kant) (and this is essentially what Weber’s
account of rationalization means). While this
epimetheus and sisyphus – “the
process of proletarianization may produce a most cunning of mortals”
kind of pragmatic intelligence, métis, ingenuity, Stupidity is not error or a tissue of errors.
a shrewdness or a cunning through which every- There are imbecile thoughts, imbecile dis-
one seems to have become “cleverer,”2 it in fact courses, that are made up entirely of truths;
leads to a generalized stupidity which, in 1944, but these truths are base, they are those of
comes along with the still very recent advent of a base, heavy and leaden soul. The state of
the culture industry: mind dominated by reactive forces, by
right, expresses stupidity and, more pro-
[The mind or intellect] must perish when it is foundly, that which it is a symptom of: a
solidified into a cultural asset and handed out base way of thinking. (Deleuze, Nietzsche
for consumption purposes. The flood of and Philosophy 105)
precise information and brand-new amuse-
ments make people smarter and more One would clearly understand nothing of these
stupid at once. (Adorno and Horkheimer lines by Gilles Deleuze extracted from Nietzsche
xvii) and Philosophy if one did not posit, with Dork

161
bêtise and animality

Zabunyan, that “stupidity [bêtise] must there- to this solemnity [gravité] with which thought
fore be understood as my own stupidity [ma progresses, that is, raises itself in climbing
propre bêtise]” (Zabunyan).6 [gravissant] that which is high, in advancing
This is above all a question of my stupidity towards what Simondon called “key-points”
such that it is capable – that is, such that I am (Du mode d’existence des objets techniques
capable – of making me ashamed: a stupidity 164) – but always with the risk that inevitably
such that I perceive my being stupid. Without accompanies elevation, the constant imminence
which (for want of being stupid, of being able of the fall, of which the tightrope walker is the
to be) I would not be able to be affected figure (Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra):
(pained, struck) by the stupidity of others, or the fact that one who thinks only thinks noeti-
to have shame for myself (as if their stupidity cally intermittently means that the one who
necessarily and immediately becomes mine): thinks, this one who thinks, always ends up
without that, I could not be made ashamed. falling back again, that all thinking can
It is from out of this experience of shame that become stupid, eventually becomes stupid
I begin to philosophize, writes Deleuze in his (again), and that any knowledge can end up jus-
reading of Nietzsche – and this means that stu- tifying and rationalizing the worst stupidity.8
pidity is “a properly transcendental question: This relation stupidity/knowledge, bêtise/
how is stupidity (not error) possible?” savoir, Dummheit/Wissenschaft, such that
(Deleuze, Difference and Repetition 151). knowledge will never be done with stupidity
This is the question of individuation and disin- in so far as it is firstly and above all its own stu-
dividuation. If we are able to be stupid, it is pidity – that stupidity proper to knowledge, that
because individuals only individuate themselves is, the impropriety of knowledge (that which is
from out of preindividual funds from which taught to us by the figure of Epimetheus and
they can never break free: from out of which, by epimetheia which only thinks from out of
alone, they can individuate themselves, but its own stupidity, posing stupidity as its point
within which they can also get stuck, bogged of departure, and which provided the name for
down, that is, dis-individuate themselves. the collection Epiméthée founded by Jean Hyp-
polite at Presses Universitaires de France) – this
[Stupidity] is possible by virtue of the link relation, stupidity/knowledge, is what is at
between thought and individuation […] Indi- stake in what, relying notably on Jacques
viduation as such, as it operates beneath all Derrida and Paul Valéry, I have tried to think
forms, is inseparable from a pure ground
as the pharmacological condition of knowledge,
[or fund] that it brings to the surface and
that is, of noesis as the existence possible for
trails with it […] Stupidity is neither the
ground nor the individual, but rather this
non-inhuman beings faced with the fact of
relation in which individuation brings the being-inhuman (faced with the shameful, and
ground to the surface without being able to as deficiency of shame, absence of shame, of
give it form. (151–52; my emphasis) aidos) (see Stiegler, Taking Care of Youth
and the Generations 180–81).
That is, it cannot produce what Simondon called The pharmacological (that is, Epimethean)
“taking form” (Simondon, L’Individu et sa condition of knowledge and of noesis is
genèse physico-biologique 46). Such a fund or equally that of the university in so far as it is
ground may be that of knowledge itself, knowl- an institution in constant struggle against stu-
edge that has become “well-known,”7 and the pidity, and more particularly against its own
best thoughts – those that make knowledge, stupidity (which is always already expropriated,
that open what I describe as a new circuit of beginning with what Derrida analysed as exap-
transindividuation. And yet the best thinking propriation), constantly climbing anew the
always remains susceptible to regression. gravity of this pharmacological condition – in
The question of stupidity is the question of order to refound, like a “happy Sisyphus”
regression (of lowering, of baseness) in relation (Camus 110–11), the meaning and value of the

162
stiegler

universal which derives its name from universi- according to Derrida, is “not exactly” the
tas, that is, such that, in the universe, some- animal – just as this odd animal who is Deleuze
thing has still not happened, remains still to is not exactly Derrida, however much the latter
be climbed [à gravir] in gravity … and to be plays the fool [fait la bête, acts the beast, plays
engraved [à graver], according to the mnemo- the fool, makes a blunder]: Deleuze does not
technical condition described in the “Second say exactly what Derrida says, Derrida tells us,
Essay” of Nietzsche’s On the Genealogy of because he says it “without equivocation, decid-
Morality. edly and determinedly.”
Now, beyond the fact that decided and deter-
mined clarity, which is not always useless or
derrida plays the fool – and deleuze harmful, does not necessarily always lead to a
logic of opposition – it can and even must be
is not exactly derrida the clarity of a distinction – beyond the fact,
Derrida has commented on this passage in also, that the verb “to be” in Deleuze, as in
which Deleuze asks how stupidity is possible, Derrida, is a copula9 that we cannot do
firstly in relation to the question of the animal, without at the very moment when we want to
basing his response on the beginning of deconstruct and to deconstruct this very
Deleuze’s argument, where he proposes that impossibility of doing without it, as, for
“Stupidity [bêtise] is not animality. The example, when one says that “bêtise is not ani-
animal is protected by specific forms which mality,” or that “the beast is not exactly the
prevent it from being ‘stupid’ [bête]” animal” (and it would here be necessary to
(Deleuze, Difference and Repetition 150). deconstruct the question of exactitude,10 and
Following the “well-known” method of everything that this raises – a thousand necess-
deconstruction, Derrida, in The Beast and the ary tasks which, equivocating, could neverthe-
Sovereign – a work that derived from a less end up resembling what Hegel called
seminar that was part of a series dedicated to Räsonieren, quibbling), beyond all this, I
the question of responsibility – tries to reduce believe that here, Derrida totally misinterprets
Deleuze’s reasoning to a classical opposition the discourse of Deleuze, and that he pro-
between the human and the animal. He thus foundly misunderstands the provenance of
challenges the possibility of identifying this this discourse on individuation (and disindivi-
“property of man” that according to Deleuze duation) in repetition that is the book Differ-
stupidity would constitute. ence and Repetition.11
Now, I cannot help but think that Derrida, Deleuze tried to think stupidity from out of
here, is playing the fool, fait la bête, as one individuation – that is, with Simondon. Indivi-
says in French, when, for example, he writes duation, he writes, is “inseparable from a pure
that “Deleuze intends to separate man from ani- ground that it brings to the surface and trails
mality as to bêtise, saying without equivocation, with it” (Deleuze, Difference and Repetition
decidedly and determinedly, that ‘bêtise is not 152). And it is in relation to this inseparable
animality’” (Derrida, The Beast and the Sover- ground [ fond] that stupidity takes place as a
eign, Volume 1 180). It is hard to understand transcendental structure of thinking.
why, if this is this case, Derrida himself To develop his argument against this analy-
declares, at the beginning of the first session sis, Derrida focuses on one sentence where
of his seminar devoted to the beast and the Deleuze posits that animals “are in a sense fore-
sovereign, that “the beast is not exactly the warned against this ground, protected by their
animal” (1). explicit forms” (152).
One could no doubt respond that Derrida But what is this ground? Is it, for example,
reproaches Deleuze by saying something that is what Derrida called the “groundless ground
close to what Deleuze says, but that is not (Urgrund as Ungrund)” (Derrida, The Beast
exactly what Deleuze says, just as the beast, and the Sovereign, Volume 1 180)? Nothing is

163
bêtise and animality

less certain. It is a matter of the ground of what working as a group […] What we refer to as
Deleuze named individuation of any kind the individual in biology is in reality in
whatsoever, that is, whether it be animal or some ways a sub-individual more than an
human, that “operates beneath all forms, [and individual; in biology, it seems that the
which] is inseparable” from such a ground. notion of individuality is applicable at
several stages, or at different levels succes-
Animals, according to Deleuze, would,
sively included within each other […] The
however, be “in a sense forewarned against unity of life lies with the complete group,
this ground, protected by their explicit forms.” not the isolated individual. (Simondon, L’In-
To this assertion Derrida objects that “if they dividuation à la lumière des notions de
are forewarned, then they must be in a relation, forme et d’information 157–58)
in some relation, with this ground and the threat
of this ground” (180). In Civilization and Its Discontents, Freud high-
Deleuze would not, of course, deny this, and lighted that:
he himself speaks of a relation. But what are
we should not think ourselves happy in any of
these forms that “forewarn” or “forearm” these animal States or in any of the roles
animals from their ground, of which we con- assigned in them to the individual. (123)
tinue to ask (we have not yet had an answer)
in what this ground (or fund) consists? And In the language of Simondon taken up by
why are they “explicit”? Deleuze, it could be said that we consider our-
All individuals (humans, animals, vegetables selves happy to find material with which to
and crystals, that is, minerals) are individuated individuate ourselves psychically.
through an individuation process. In the vital
individuation process, the genuine individual
repetition as individuation
is the animal group that forms the species in
so far as it is affected by that which, in its Derrida does not understand the meaning of the
vital preindividual fund (or ground), constitutes words fond, rapport and individuation as they
the mark of a phase difference (that molecular are used in Difference and Repetition. That
theory, for example, relates to copying errors animals are “forewarned against this ground”
that give rise to singularities, which, within does not mean for Deleuze that they are not in
their milieu, may in extreme cases lead to mon- relation to this ground: it means that their
strosity or to a mutation of species): the phase relation to this ground passes through specific
shift is not marked in the vital individuation organizations, where the word “specific”
process at the level of the animal, but rather at means that which characterizes an animal
the level of the animal group that constitutes species, as specific relations typical and deter-
and individuates the species. minate for this or that animal species, consti-
The individuated species constitutes the vital tuting as such “explicit forms,” that is,
unit, writes Simondon: recognizable forms (including by the animals
themselves as imago – which makes it possible
The group is integrative. The only concrete for the locust to adopt its “gregarious” form,
reality is the vital unit, which in certain as Lacan says in “The Mirror Stage” [Lacan
cases can be reduced to a single being and 77]) and describable forms, through which the
in other cases corresponds to a highly differ- preindividual fund from which they come indi-
entiated group of many beings. viduates itself diversely and specifically – that
is, at the level of the living group that constitu-
This is particularly visible in termites:
tes a species – and without the isolated animal
Thus, termites construct the most complex individual itself being affected by an
edifices in the animal kingdom, despite the indetermination.12
relative simplicity of their nervous system: It is here completely impossible to follow
they act almost as a unique organism, Deleuze’s reasoning without referring in detail

164
stiegler

to the Simondonian philosophy of individuation Repetition – that I cited above, which is also
– which Derrida seems totally to ignore. The to say, without referring to what Nietzsche
“explicit” forms that species form (as “taking wrote about the relation between philosophy
form”) are the processes of vital individuation and bêtise in §328 of The Gay Science),
of which the “concrete” forms consist in pro- Deleuze speaks of a process of vital individua-
cesses of specification. In the first chapter of tion on the ground of which, from out of the
Difference and Repetition, “Difference in funds of which, and in which appears an indivi-
Itself,” specification and individuation are duation process of a new type: psychic and col-
linked together by Deleuze, both with reference lective individuation, which no longer has the
to Simondon, as when Deleuze paraphrases same relation to this ground or fund because
Simondon by asserting that “the individuating it constitutes, precisely, a new regime (that is,
is not the simple individual,” and against a new kingdom) of individuation.
Duns Scotus, about whom he nevertheless Individuation in general must be thought as
states: relation and process and not as stasis and iden-
tity. What is new is the relation between the
[Duns Scotus was] not content [despite this] determined and the undetermined, and the
to analyse the elements of an individual but way in which they are instantiated in different
went as far as the conception of individuation
types of individuation (mineral, vital, psycho-
as the “ultimate actuality of form.” (Deleuze,
social13). The question of the undetermined is
Difference and Repetition 38)
posed by Deleuze in Difference and Repetition
If it is necessary to pass through the thought of above all in reference to Kant – and to the ques-
Simondon, this is because: tion of the “I think.” In Simondonian thought,
this becomes the question of the “phase shift”
We must show not only how individuating which constitutes the dynamic principle of the
difference differs in kind from specific process itself, and which is concretely expressed
difference, but primarily and above all how
as the “taking form” of an individuation in an
individuation properly precedes matter
individuated being.
and form, species and parts, and
every other element of the constituted indi- There is a common ground to all individua-
vidual. (38) tion processes, which are not at all opposed to
one another by this thought, contrary to what
One of the principal aims of Difference and Derrida would have us believe. But there is a
Repetition is precisely to think this link other new relation to this ground or these funds
than according to tradition and everything with each new type of process (mineral,
that follows it up until Heidegger (who was vital, psycho-social), this relation consisting
also a reader of Duns Scotus) and beyond: it is in the distinction and the inscription of a
a matter of thinking with Simondon beginning difference – and which is, in addition, a new
with the animal and, more generally, with the regime of différance – and which itself
vital – the animal and the vital being themselves derives from a repetition (and I shall return
thought beginning with the crystal, that is, with to this below).
the individuation of the mineral. The regimes of This is why Deleuze can write:
individuation are here kingdoms, that is, forms
of sovereignty of which the juridico-social form The animal is protected by specific forms
which prevent it from being “stupid”
is therefore merely a case – given that indivi-
[bête]. Formal correspondences between the
duation in general is sovereign.
human face and the heads of animals have
In the passages of Difference and Repetition often been composed; in other words, corre-
commented on by Derrida (which it is hardly spondences between individual differences
possible to read without referring to the peculiar to humans and the specific differ-
passage from Nietzsche and Philosophy – pub- ences of animals. Such correspondences,
lished six years before Difference and however, take no account of stupidity as a

165
bêtise and animality

specifically human form of bestiality. not a specific trait, not the trait of a species:
(Deleuze, Difference and Repetition 150) the head of the animal is not a good represen-
tation), results in the passage from the mineral
Between the human and the animal there is a
to the biological (16, and Simondon, L’Individu
change of regime of individuation which is a
et sa genèse physico-biologique 115ff.).16
change of relation to its preindividual funds.
Since “stupidity” is a transcendental trait,
Humans individuate psychically whereas
that is (in Deleuze), psychic rather than specific,
animals individuate specifically.
“[c]owardice, cruelty, baseness and stupidity
If “individuation as such, as it operates
are not simply corporeal capacities or traits of
beneath all forms, is inseparable from a pure
character or society; they are structures of
ground that it brings to the surface and trails
thought as such” (Deleuze, Difference and Rep-
with it” (152), this is because it is always associ-
etition 151).
ated with its milieu, which must be understood
Nevertheless, these structures of thought
as a potential for individuation, that is, as a pre-
must be thought from out of the psycho-social
individual fund. This potential constitutes pos-
(that is, both psychic and social) preindividual
sibilities, and it is from these possibilities
ground or funds such that:
that it is necessary to think being, and not the
other way around.14 The individual distinguishes itself from it,
but it [this psychic and social preindividual
fund] does not distinguish itself, continuing
indeterminacy and determination – rather to be wedded to that which divorces
the wanderer and his shadow in itself from it. It is the indeterminate, but
the indeterminate in so far as it continues
psycho-social individuation to embrace determination, as the ground
The preindividual is conceptualized by Simon- does the shoe. (152)
don through the analysis of crystallization as
That the psychic individual cannot psychically
the individuation of the mineral:15 the crystal
individuate itself without socially individuating
congeals (crystallizes) and stabilizes a tension
itself is, in Simondonian theory, the proper trait
coming from a metastable milieu that Simondon
(specific, this time, in the logical sense of this
thinks in terms of the pairs “wave or particle,
word) of psychic and collective individuation,
matter or energy” (Simondon, L’Individuation
but this dual individuation always operates in
psychique et collective 15), whereas a living
an intermittent tension between the psychic
thing is an incomplete and unfinishable form
individual and the social group from which it
of mineral. A living thing is a crystal that
cannot be separated: from which it can only dis-
does not take, which is “in between,” in a situ-
tinguish and “divorce” itself while remaining
ation of metastability, between stability and
“wedded” to it.
instability, engendering a succession of specific
It is also in this sense that The Wanderer and
metastable forms that concretely express this
His Shadow must be read, where man
“perpetuated individuation” (16).
This vital incompleteness that perpetuates is always living in manifold dependence but
the individuation process instead of congealing regards himself as free when, out of long
it as a crystal establishes and metastabilizes a habituation, he no longer perceives the
situation of différance – it is this situation weight of his chains. (Nietzsche, Human,
which, constantly forming and de-forming, All Too Human 306)
that is, differentiating itself, and thus perpe-
tually individuating itself, and in struggling This freedom, however, consists in forging and
thus against its crystallization, that is, adopting new chains. If animals “are in a sense
against its pure stabilization, against its harden- forewarned against this ground, protected by
ing, if not its “stupidity” (“stupidity” being a their explicit forms,” this is because they are
psychic and transcendental trait in that it is not chained in this way – given that it is only

166
stiegler

possible to have chains if it is possible to not be actually carry out. Derrida did not carry out
chained, and therefore to make and adopt new this history of the supplement even though he
ones. Animals, through their species, “are” announced it, a history which, in the language
not a species: they are this species. of Simondon, pursues individuation – in what
If man can suffer (from having that which he we should perhaps call the psycho-social
is not), then it is “only from new chains that he kingdom – by compensating for an incomplete-
suffers: – ‘free will’ really means nothing more ness that is other than that of the living, even
than not feeling his new chains” (306; trans- though that is its pro-venance, just as the vital
lation modified). Now, there are such chains has its pro-venance in the mineral.
because, from out of the psycho-social preindi-
vidual funds, psychic individuation and collec-
tive individuation are simultaneously différance and repetition
arranged, according to Simondon, and all this
Simondonian thought overcomes the opposi-
presupposes, as I feel it necessary to add at
tions between types of individuation by refer-
this point, a technical individuation. Psychic
ring to traits common to all individuation
individuation and social individuation (of the
processes – always constituted through the indi-
group) can, however, be turned against one
vidual/super-saturated milieu (crystalline,
another, and nullify one another: their con-
vital, psycho-social) which exceeds the opposi-
fusion is their mutual disindividuation, and it
tion inside/outside – and such that these
is precisely this confusion that leads to stupid-
traits individuate themselves through types of
ity, bêtise, Dummheit 17 (baseness), yet psychic
individuation and as relations in what Simon-
individuation and social individuation can
don called an “ontogenesis,” but which I,
never individuate without each other, which is
however, prefer to call a genealogy: the geneal-
what the eighteenth century called intelligence.
ogy of different regimes of individuation (differ-
It is by separating in a new way that which
ent kingdoms which are forms of sovereignty –
links them together (as a new relation), thus
including within species, including within that
establishing a new form of phase difference in
species called human, or rather non-inhuman
the process of individuation (which is always
within inhuman being, including between
changing phase, since otherwise it would not
psychic individuals, and so on) as local indivi-
be a process, that is, a dynamic system rather
duations within a much broader process
than a determinist system), it is through this
binding and connecting them together.
binding separation (the purest form of which
Such a thought of individuation as process is
is friendship, in the sense given to this by Blan-
not foreign to that process that différance also is
chot18) that these psycho-social preindividual
– this “kind of gross spelling mistake”20 on the
funds make possible a new type of incomplete-
basis of which alone it is possible and necessary,
ness and constitute through this a new regime
in the eyes of Derrida (I was convinced of this
of individuation which produces the transindi-
from the moment I began to read it), to think
vidual – that is, meaning.
“gross stupidity,” that gross stupidity through
Even though he did not himself thematize the
which was expressed, historico-politically, that
necessity for technical individuation to support
hyper-metaphysical sludge in which citizen Hei-
psycho-social individuation, Simondon did
degger got bogged down (and disindividuated
propose (in Du mode d’existence des objets tech-
himself, that is, betrayed himself, in both
niques 248) that the transindividual presup-
senses of the term). This relation between indivi-
poses artefacts, technical objects, which are
duation and différance is something of which we
also image-objects19 that must be understood
can easily be convinced if we re-read, for
as hypomnesic supports, hypomnemata, phar-
example, the following lines:
maka and everything that Derrida analysed as
supplementarity in that history of the sup- Différer […] is to temporize, to take
plement that Derrida did not himself ever recourse, consciously or unconsciously, in

167
bêtise and animality

the temporal and temporizing mediation of a this genesis. (Simondon, L’Individu et sa


detour that suspends the accomplishment or genèse physico-biologique 163)
fulfillment of “desire.” (Derrida, Margins of
Philosophy 8) As is now well known, neoteny, in the the-
ories of Kapp then of Canguilhem and Leroi-
“To differ” is in this sense, which is that of dif- Gourhan, is thought as “organic projection”
férance, to implement the structural incomple- and “process of exteriorization,” that is, as tech-
teness of the vital or psycho-social (but not nicization of the living and “technical form of
mineral) individuation process such as it was life.” Neoteny does not only mean that the
thought by Simondon: “this temporization is living thing needs artefacts in order to live –
also temporalization and spacing, the which is already the case for certain living
becoming-time of space and the becoming- things which modify their vital milieu by
space of time” (8). In other words, this indivi- imprinting their form of life upon it. It means
duation that is différance gives a difference that, “if the living being could be completely
which spatially concretizes this différance peaceful and satisfied in itself” (163; my
“to be not identical, to be other, discernible, emphasis), as “the animal does not reason or
etc.” (8). work” (Bataille 121), and is in this sense sover-
The individuation of differences through dif- eign – in a sense which is not that of the
férance is only possible through an originary psycho-social kingdom where sovereignty
phase difference which is also a default of derives on the contrary from a primordial in-
origin that spaces itself (out) by repeating quietude and dis-satisfaction – “there would
itself (from out of a primordial repetition 21): be no appeal to the psyche” (Simondon, L’Indi-
When dealing with differen(ts)(ds), a word vidu et sa genèse physico-biologique 163).
that can be written with a final ts or a final ds, Psychic and collective individuation is what
as you will, whether it is a question of dissim- occurs when “life problematizes itself” (163).
ilar otherness or of allergic and polemical This problematization results in a decoupling
otherness, an interval, a distance, spacing, between perception and action, that is, it
must be produced between the other means behaving differently, otherwise than
elements, and be produced with a certain per- merely a reaction, becoming through that an
severance in repetition. (8) act, an action as passage to the act. And this
constitutes a transformation of affectivity: affec-
problematization of the living tivity itself becomes emotion as the différance
of the effect from the affect, a différance
Within the broader processes of individuation, which retains (a retention) and reflects, which
regressions are always possible. This does not psychically individuates – but in transindividu-
mean that psycho-social individuation could ating as the work of the psycho-social regime of
devolve to vital individuation, that is, specific différance.
individuation, or that vital individuation could This is why there are not
devolve to mineral individuation.22 It means,
rather, that psycho-social life oscillates beings that merely live, and others that are
between dynamic possibilities which character- living-and-thinking: animals probably
ize types of individuation without separating occasionally find themselves in a psychic situ-
ation. Such situations which lead to acts of
them:
thinking are, however, less frequent in
animals.
The psychic and the vital cannot be distin-
guished like two substances, nor even as In man, on the contrary, it is
two parallel or superimposed functions; the
psychic acts as a brake, decreasing the the purely vital situation which is […] rare
speed of the individuation of the living, a […] There is no nature, no essence on
neotenic amplification of the first state of which to found an anthropology; simply, a

168
stiegler

threshold is crossed: animals are better is not only something that can happen to the
equipped to live than to think, whereas man psychic individual: it is a condition of its
is better equipped to think than to live. psychic individuation to the extent that it
(163 n. 6) must become collective individuation, and in
Dissatisfaction is a new modality of incomplete- this necessity lies the “transcendental” charac-
ness (of différance) through which the living ter of stupidity.
individual becomes a psychic and social individ- This does not mean that stupidity would be a
ual. Psychic différance is immediately social fall of the psychic individual into a disindividua-
individuation because “the vital functions tion which would be the passage to the social –
cannot solve the problems posed by living” (164). as is the case in Heidegger with the “falling
To the extent that he posits explicitly and in prey” (Verfallen) of Dasein – since, as we
principle that technical concretization is the have seen, this passage to the social is on the
condition of appearance of the transindividual, contrary, as collective individuation, the con-
it is very surprising that Simondon does not dition of psychic individuation. This means,
engage with the process of exteriorization theo- however, that participation in the transindivi-
rized by Leroi-Gourhan as the consequence of dual can in fact fall into an interindividuality
neotenization, that is, of the technical proble- within which individuation is suspended:
matic – of technical problematization – in the
Interindividuality is an exchange between
différance of psychic life.23 For the psychic individuated realities who remain at their
individual only individuates when the resolution level of individuation, and who seek in
of the problems of life, having become psychic other individuals an image of their own exist-
problems – because the neotenic living thing ence parallel to this existence. (165)
that is the psychic living thing can no longer
solve them – can only be concretized through It is from such a degradation of the transindi-
participation in the transindividual which the vidual into interindividuality that psycho-
psycho-social constitutes and which itself pre- social individuation can regress to a stage
supposes technical objects that, as object- which is neither animal, nor vegetable, nor
images, are the supports of the transindividual. mineral. This regression of psycho-social
The transindividual occurs to the strict individuation constitutes a deficient relation to
extent that “entering the path of psychic indivi- the potential that its preindividual funds
duation requires the individuated being to constitute (at once as crystalline, vital and
surpass itself” (164), and this surpassing of the psycho-social: the psychic individual which
psychic individual is not only a trans-formation disindividuates suffers psychically, and somati-
of the self. The self can only trans-form itself cally, which means that he or she also tends to
psychically to the extent that it trans-forms its disindividuate vitally, that his or her organs
social milieu. In order that its psychic trans- are in contradiction, and even that they may
formation can in fact become its own, it must no longer metabolize, that is, assimilate
transindividually surpass itself as social trans- minerals and so on – this being the preindivi-
formation, that is, as social différance: dual potential for vital individuation).

The psychic results in a transindividual order


of reality […], the psychic is born of the tran-
sindividual […], psychic reality is not closed three types of psychic
in on itself […], the resolution of the intra- disindividuation
individual psychic problematic […] occurs
at the transindividual level. (164) In psycho-social individuation the specific
group gives way to what Freud described as
That the psychic individual may, however, get the horde, then, in constant and functional
bogged down in the transindividual, and there- relation to the prehistoric, then proto-historical
fore function as a quasi-specific individuation, and finally historical evolution of the

169
bêtise and animality

hypomnesic supplement, to what Leroi-Gourhan altering. As such, it is also what conditions


referred to as the socio-ethnic group, which the formation of an I, or of an ego, that is, of
itself gives way to the socio-political group: a narcissistic structure which mirrors (with)
psycho-social individuation is characterized by other similar structures in interindividuality –
the fact that it constantly techno-logically mod- the fantasy of identity being thus constructed
ifies the conditions of its individuation – that as a “narcissism of minor differences” (Freud,
is, of its transindividuation. Civilization and Its Discontents 114), and
But these successive stages are always tending founded on the paralogisms conceived by Kant
to return to vital forms of individuation, which long before Freudian analyses of the psychic
constantly polarizes them – they are always apparatus and psychic functions.
tending to put in place the regime of the specific In the epoch of psycho-power and psycho-
group, and to operate the technical envelope of technologies, and now with neuro-power, market-
this group as an animal society in which the ing exploits these tendencies in order to take
psychic and the social de-compose (and disindi- control of the processes of transindividuation –
viduate) in being superimposed in an interindi- thereby provoking massive disindividuation pro-
viduality of the group, which thus becomes cesses. Given that the projection of a phantas-
more like a herd. This does not mean that tech- matic identity polarizes the interindividual, and
nicity is regressive. It means that it constitutes a that the interindividual always haunts the tran-
polarity at once regressive and progressive. sindividual, the I and the ego are thus moments
Simondon, therefore, says the following of disindividuation. But this does not mean
about the collective formed by psychic and col- that we ought to try and reduce or dissolve
lective individuation: them (that is, raise them into a dialectical syn-
thesis), if only because disindividuation is the
[it is a] transindividual reality obtained
condition of a new individuation, which itself
through the individuation of preindividual
realities associated with a plurality of living consists in the fabrication of “new chains.”
things [becoming through that psychic indi- It is necessary in fact to distinguish three
viduals], distinguished from the purely types of disindividuation:
social and from the purely interindividual; . that which proceeds from this interindivi-
the purely social exists, in fact, in animal
duality where the social group regresses to
societies; it is not necessary for a new indivi-
duation to exist to expand vital individuation; the purely social, through which it again
it expresses how living things exist socially; it takes on specific traits (in the sense that
is vital unity at the first degree which is they characterize that species of vital indivi-
directly social. (L’Individu et sa genèse duation) which infest the I or the ego;
physico-biologique 165; my emphasis) . that which occurs as a divestiture by tech-
nics – what Simondon described as
In its interindividual modality, and when
proletarianization;
this spreads to the totality of the social group
. that which is necessary for individuation as
(through some kind of mimetic contagion), the
the epokhé of an earlier individuation,24 and
transindividual psycho-social tends thus to
through which the psychic individual
rejoin the “purely social” of animal societies in
accomplishes a “quantum leap,” that is,
so far as they are conditioned by a specific indi-
crosses a threshold in their psychic trans-
viduation (that is, herd-like – in the sense that
formation.
Lacan refers to the grégarisation of the locust,
the way it is able to take on its gregarious This third form of disindividuation, as con-
form) rather than a psychic individuation. dition of the pursuit of individuation, itself pre-
Now, stupidity always passes through this supposes emotion as the psychic modality and
tendency, in so far as it seeks to stabilize in différance of affectivity. It is the “capacity of
the form of an identity that which is in reality the individuating being to temporarily disindi-
always a metastability with the potential for viduate” (165).

170
stiegler

I myself argue that, in the final analysis, these 3 See also Habermas: “In the transition from the
three forms of disindividuation can never be sep- literary journalism of private individuals to the
arated, and always constitute three necessary public services of the mass media the public
moments of psychic individuation in so far as it sphere was transformed by the influx of private
leads to the formation of the transindividual, interests, which received special prominence in
the mass media” (53).
that is, of the psycho-social collective individual,
and in so far as they must be thought in terms of 4 See Adorno and Horkheimer 214. The link made
a doubly epokhal redoubling over-determined by in this fragment by Adorno and Horkheimer
technical evolutions.25 Such an epokhality consti- between stupidity and frustrated desire, and
tutes a shock, and for this reason we must under- which they inscribe here into a perspective that I
stand technical life as a life of shocks. These would call organological, must be analysed as a
process of the regression of desire towards the
moments are not dialectical because the poiso-
drives. The fragmentary and incomplete character
nous aspect of this pharmacology is irreducible. of these notes and sketches, however, prevents
For example, if individuation occurs as rational going further here.
knowledge, this knowledge may always some
day or other come to serve stupidity: there is 5 This is what became clear to Freud in 1920.
no absolute knowledge. 6 I have previously commented on this remark by
This is because “the I or the ego,” as a fantasy Zabunyan in Stiegler, Uncontrollable Societies (24).
of identity (as the purely psychic as well as the
7 “Quite generally, the well-known, just because it
purely social) is the point of articulation of is well-known, is not cognitively understood. The
these three dimensions of disindividuation that commonest way in which we deceive either our-
Deleuze calls “indices of the species” (Deleuze, selves or others about understanding is by assuming
Difference and Repetition 151). something as familiar, and accepting it on that
As such, it is necessary to posit that the account” (Hegel, Phenomenology of Spirit §31; trans-
psychic individual is the individual who is lation modified). My citation of Hegel to support a
capable of disindividuating (just as, according proposition by Deleuze no doubt seems surprising.
to Canguilhem, the technique of healthy living This is, however, precisely a question of the well-
lies in “the power and the will to fall sick” known belief, which is also to say, the stupid
[Canguilhem 200; translation modified]) belief, that Deleuze – and Nietzsche – oppose Hegel.
through a disindividuation due not to his will 8 I refer here to the height of what Gilbert Simon-
but to the artefactual (factical) and pharmaco- don called “key-points,” which are culminating
logical situation through which alone it is poss- points, highlights, and to those heights which mean
ible to say and do stupid things, and where there are base thoughts as the truths from which
saying here often means doing they are made:
– stupidity being also and
perhaps especially performative There are imbecile thoughts, imbecile dis-
courses, that are made up entirely of truths;
(and perhaps Gabriel Tarde
but these truths are base, they are those of
should be read from this a base, heavy and leaden soul. The state of
perspective). mind dominated by reactive forces, by right,
expresses stupidity and, more profoundly, that
notes which it is a symptom of: a base way of thinking.
(Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy 105)
1 This was the year of publication, though it was
written in 1944. In relation to the worst, and to the worst stupidity,
see Sophocles, Antigone, and my commentary in
2 The spread of this word, malin, particularly in
Uncontrollable Societies (24ff.).
marketing and advertising, which initially referred
to the Devil and which has come to designate 9 See Derrida, “The Supplement of Copula: Philos-
cunning intelligence and a “wise guy” [petit malin], ophy before Linguistics” in Margins of Philosophy
is a symptom typical of our misery. 175–205.

171
bêtise and animality

10 I have attempted to begin this analysis in Tech- 17 I have tried to show that it is this logic that is at
nics and Time, 1 and Technics and Time, 2. I will work in what Heidegger calls “das Man” (the
return to this question in Technics and Time, 4 they or the one). See Stiegler, “The Theatre of Indi-
(forthcoming). viduation,” and idem, “To Love, To Love Me, To
Love Us: From September 11 to April 21” in
11 If this is so, this is because Derrida plays the
Acting Out.
fool ( fait la bête, which is not necessarily the
same thing as doing stupid things, faire des 18 See Blanchot and my commentary in Veux-tu
bêtises), and not because he is stupid [est bête]. devenir mon ami? (forthcoming).
Anyway, who could one say is stupid? Heidegger,
19 In the sense given to this in Simondon, Imagin-
for example? Surely not. Heidegger, who was not
ation et invention 13.
exactly stupid, who was “not just stupid” [ juste
pas bête] as the younger generations say today, 20 Derrida, Margins of Philosophy 3:
did – that is, said – stupid things. And in this case
he was not content to “play the fool.” However
I will speak, therefore, of the letter a, this
that may be, in relation to stupidity, being and not
initial letter which it apparently has been
being perhaps do not agree, perhaps never agree,
necessary to insinuate, here and there, into
even when these copulas are determined or unde-
the writing of the word difference; and to do
termined by the adverb “exactly.” Between being
so in the course of a writing on writing, and
(stupid), doing (stupid things), and saying (stupid
also of a writing within writing whose differ-
things), the question of stupidity would be at the
ent trajectories thereby find themselves, at
same time older, deeper and lower than the ques-
certain very determined points, intersecting
tion of being and of spirit, including in Of Spirit: Hei-
with a kind of gross spelling mistake.
degger and the Question, where Derrida
approaches the question of the animal “poor in
21 And this is a trait common to both Derrida and
world.” The default of spirit, that is, the feeling of
Deleuze.
not having any: such would be the commencement
of spirit starting from that which is stupid, epi- 22 In his interpretation of the theory of the three
metheia (and this is also la Bête de la Belle). souls outlined by Aristotle in On the Soul – where
vital individuation in the Simondonian sense
12 I will return to this question of the indetermi-
includes both the vegetative and sensitive stages
nate in Deleuze, which must be compared to the
of the soul – Hegel shows that any noetic soul
question of the indeterminate in Heidegger – in
(any psychic individual) can regress to an animal
passing through the relation to death.
state. It means that they are in a deferred and sus-
13 To this must be added the process of technical pended relation to their own possibility, held
individuation, which psycho-social individuation pre- within their “in itself” without passing into the act
supposes, even though Simondon is not very clear of the “for itself.” And this is not without relation
about this. See Stiegler, De la misère symbolique 1. to Deleuze’s statement about stupidity as a form
which does not take. See Hegel, Lectures on the
14 It is this that enables Simondon to think indus-
History of Philosophy.
try. I have tried to analyse this reversal of relations
between being and possibility in Technics and Time, 23 It is true that Simondon’s thesis, from which
3, in Économie de l’hypermatériel et psychopouvoir these lines are extracted, was defended seven
and in What Makes Life Worth Living. years before Leroi-Gourhan published Gesture
and Speech.
15 The crystal is the individuation of an amor-
phous milieu from which emerges individuality, 24 That is, the interruption, suspension and trans-
that is, a physical individual. See L’Individu et sa formation, or the individuation, of an earlier
genèse physico-biologique 83. individuation.
16 I shall return to these questions and to the 25 On the doubly epokhal redoubling, see What
question of animality in Veux-tu devenir mon ami? Makes Life Worth Living, Technics and Time, 1 and
(forthcoming). Technics and Time, 2.

172
stiegler

bibliography Lacan, Jacques. Écrits. Trans. Bruce Fink. New York


and London: Norton, 2006. Print.
Adorno, Theodor, and Max Horkheimer. Dialectic of
the Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels. The Communist
Edmund Jephcott. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2002. Print. Manifesto. Trans. Samuel Moore. London:
Penguin, 1967. Print.
Bataille, Georges. Lascaux, or The Birth of Art. Trans.
Austryn Wainhouse. Lausanne: Skira, 1955. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Trans.
Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage, 1974. Print.
Blanchot, Maurice. Friendship. Trans. Elizabeth
Rottenberg. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1997. Print. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Human, All Too Human. Trans.
R.J. Hollingdale. Cambridge and New York:
Camus, Albert. The Myth of Sisyphus. Trans. Justin Cambridge UP, 1986. Print.
O’Brien. London: Penguin, 1975. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. On the Genealogy of Morality.
Canguilhem, Georges. The Normal and the Trans. Carol Diethe. Cambridge and New York:
Pathological. Trans. Carolyn R. Fawcett. Cambridge UP, 1994. Print.
New York: Zone, 1991. Print.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition. Trans. Trans. R.J. Hollingdale. London: Penguin, 1961.
Paul Patton. New York: Columbia UP, 1994. Print. Print.
Deleuze, Gilles. Nietzsche and Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Simondon, Gilbert. Du mode d’existence des objets
Tomlinson. New York: Columbia UP, 1983. Print. techniques. Paris: Aubier, 2001. Print.
Derrida, Jacques. The Beast and the Sovereign, Simondon, Gilbert. Imagination et invention. Chatou:
Volume 1. Trans. Geoffrey Bennington. Chicago Transparence, 2008. Print.
and London: U of Chicago P, 2009. Print.
Simondon, Gilbert. L’Individu et sa genèse physico-
Derrida, Jacques. Margins of Philosophy. Trans. Alan biologique. Grenoble: Millon, 1995. Print.
Bass. Chicago and London: U of Chicago P, 1982.
Print. Simondon, Gilbert. L’Individuation à la lumière des
notions de forme et d’information. Grenoble: Millon,
Freud, Sigmund. Civilization and Its Discontents. 2005. Print.
Trans. James Strachey. The Standard Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Simondon, Gilbert. L’Individuation psychique et col-
Vol. 21. London: Hogarth, 1964. Print. lective. Paris: Aubier, 2007. Print.

Habermas, Jürgen. “The Public Sphere: An Stiegler, Bernard. Acting Out. Trans. David Barison,
Encyclopedia Article (1964).” New German Daniel Ross, and Patrick Crogan. Stanford:
Critique 3 (1974): 49–55. Print. Stanford UP, 2009. Print.

Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Lectures on the Stiegler, Bernard. De la misère symbolique
History of Philosophy, 1825–6. Vol. II. Greek 1. L’Epoque hyperindustrielle. Paris: Galilée, 2004.
Philosophy. Trans. Robert F. Brown. Oxford: Print.
Oxford UP, 2006. Print. Stiegler, Bernard. Économie de l’hypermatériel
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. Phenomenology of et psychopouvoir. Paris: Mille et une nuits, 2008.
Spirit. Trans. A.V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1977. Print.
Print. Stiegler, Bernard. Taking Care of Youth and the
Generations. Trans. Stephen Barker. Stanford:
Heidegger, Martin. “The Self-Assertion of the
Stanford UP, 2010. Print.
German University.” Martin Heidegger and
National Socialism: Questions and Answers. Ed. Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 1: The Fault of
Günther Neske and Emil Kettering. Trans. Lisa Epimetheus. Trans. Richard Beardsworth and
Harries. New York: Paragon, 1990. 5–13. Print. George Collins. Stanford: Stanford UP, 1998. Print.
Kant, Immanuel. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 2:
Morals. Trans. H.J. Paton. New York: Harper, Disorientation. Trans. Stephen Barker. Stanford:
1964. Print. Stanford UP, 2009. Print.

173
bêtise and animality

Stiegler, Bernard. Technics and Time, 3: Cinematic


Time and the Question of Malaise. Trans. Stephen
Barker. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2011. Print.
Stiegler, Bernard. “The Theatre of Individuation:
Phase-Shift and Resolution in Simondon and
Heidegger.” Parrhesia 7 (2009): 46–57. Print.
Stiegler, Bernard. Uncontrollable Societies of
Disaffected Individuals: Disbelief and Discredit.
Vol. 2. Trans. Daniel Ross. Cambridge: Polity,
2013. Print.
Stiegler, Bernard. What Makes Life Worth Living: On
Pharmacology. Trans. Daniel Ross. Cambridge:
Polity, 2013. Print.
Zabunyan, Dork. “L’Apprentissage de la bêtise.”
Paper delivered at the “Deleuze” conference,
ENS Ulm, 2004. Unpublished.

Bernard Stiegler
UTC – Université, de Technologie de
Compiègne
Rue du Dr Schweitzer
Compiègne 60200
France

Daniel Ross
E-mail: djrossmail@gmail.com
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

steve baker

FIVE HERALDIC
ANIMALS (FOR
EDUARDO KAC)

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010175-6 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783437

175
five heraldic animals

176
baker

177
five heraldic animals

178
baker

179
five heraldic animals

Steve Baker
School of Education and Social Science
University of Central Lancashire
Preston PR1 2HE
UK
E-mail: sbaker1@uclan.ac.uk
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

Ron Broglio: In Philosophy and Animal Life


you along with Cora Diamond open up a
shared difference with other animals. We
along with other animals are exposed. We
house within us a vulnerability co-substantial
with corporality and liveness. Biopolitics and
dispositif leverage corporality toward a way
of managing lives. But Foucault also sketches
a line of thought by which biopower is that
which cannot be assimilated. For example
homo oeconomicus in which “Economic ration-
ality is not only surrounded by, but founded on
the unknowability of, the totality of the
process.” Moving from a restricted to a ron broglio
general economy, can animal and human
bodies, vulnerable bodies, produce an unknow-
ability over and against the frames and appar- AFTER ANIMALITY,
atus of biopolitics? Which is to say, how can
that which is vulnerable also take us BEFORE THE LAW
elsewhere?
interview with cary wolfe 1
Cary Wolfe: Yes, that’s something I’m very
attracted to in Foucault’s work. This is some-
thing that Maurizio Lazzarato’s reading of Fou- that’s exactly what generates the new forms of
cault emphasizes, and something that Jeff surveillance, and control, and micromanage-
Nealon emphasizes in his book on Foucault as ment, and the new forms of power/knowledge
well: that biopolitics is always a somewhat fanta- that attempt to deploy this new political
sized reduction of a more complex relation to resource and not get burned by the resistance
biopower, fantasized because it wants to always and alterity that’s always a part of the
control something that’s inherently risky. So, transaction.
when Foucault talks about power and resistance
RB: So, the friction of the bodies? A vulner-
being in this permanently unstable relationship,
ability, flesh, and exposure.
the way I think about this is that with the shift
to biopolitics the body in the most general sense CW: That’s right. And so one way to think
becomes a new political resource. But to have about it is that the relationship between the bio-
the goodies that go with this new political political proper and biopower is always a
resource, certain risks are entailed, right? dynamic and risky – and, above all, a strategic
Certain relations of alterity are entailed and – relation in ways that biopolitics cannot
levels of unexpectedness are entailed, and always completely foresee. And so, what

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010181-9 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.783438

181
after animality

Esposito’s language would call a more “affirma- biopolitical. I talk about this some in the
tive” way of understanding biopolitics empha- book: that biopolitics actually operates more
sizes this space of resistance that is part of the precisely at the level of flesh than the level of
gambit of biopolitics itself. So even in “the body.” Flesh is a shared kind of organicity
the most oppressive and dominating forms of and a shared kind of embodiedness for which
the biopolitical use of biopower, there is “the body” then becomes a kind of foreshorten-
always a potentially aleatory and creative ing and, already, a kind of closure. Having said
element that can erupt in very unexpected that – and this is something I insist on in the
ways at very unexpected times. To me, this is book – I don’t want to evacuate questions of
a much more robust understanding of the biopo- the phenomenological with regard to specific
litical than you would get from Agamben or the forms of life and specific ways of being in the
Schmittian line, with its emphasis on sover- world. This is one reason I return to and try
eignty and the abjection of the body as to retheorize the concept of Dasein and try to
“animal,” which in turn becomes a kind of radicalize, actually, what Heidegger was right
abstract philosophical topos. What we’re about: that Dasein has this radically inhuman,
talking about here instead is a kind of biopoli- ahuman, character, or as he puts it, that the
tics that is very, very specifically articulated in being of beings is not a being. I try to rearticu-
relation to different, particular kinds of bodies. late the radically ahuman character of Dasein as
consisting of a constitutively prosthetic relation-
RB: Right, so their resistance or how they play
ship between the biological wetware of specific
out is a matter of risk?
types of life forms and the exteriority of techni-
CW: That’s right – it’s risky. Biopolitics can’t city that rewires that wetware. That technicity
have the goodies of the new political resource doesn’t need to be tools; it can simply be the
without running the attendant risk. And that’s semiotic in the most bare, fundamental sense.
how Foucault’s rendering of biopolitics And so some creatures (but not all) have this
enables us to rearticulate questions of political constitutively prosthetic relationship to techni-
effectivity in the relationship of biopower to city and exteriority in a way that others don’t.
biopolitics. For example, that can’t happen for a cockroach
in the same way because a cockroach has an
RB: Is this discussion of vulnerability, flesh,
exoskeleton that limits its ability to have a suffi-
and exposure inscribed within phenomenology
cient concentration of neural tissue, which in
and so still within the purview of the human?
turn limits the kind of plasticity that can be
One could trace these concepts to Merleau-
reconfigured in relationship to this exteriority
Ponty’s flesh of the world and to his work on
of technicity in a way that’s different from a
chiasm. Or is it possible that vulnerability,
dolphin or an elephant. That doesn’t mean
flesh, and exposure are a leap from phenomenol-
that we can really be certain about drawing “a
ogy to something else – a posthuman phenomen-
line,” and on one side of that line we would
ology? Here I am thinking of Merleau-Ponty’s
find Dasein and on the other side of that line
unfinished work The Visible and the Invisible
we wouldn’t. In fact, the history of science
in which opacity or invisibility is not a conse-
clearly shows that that line is constantly
quence of our failed sense organs but rather
moving and constantly shifting – under
the nature of things in a world of perception.
erasure, you might say. I mean, look at what
Withdrawal or invisibility is an essential part
we’ve learned about certain kinds of animals
of the being of beings. Here, then, Heidegger’s
over the past fifty years. So it’s not an issue of
figure of the human as shepherd of being lags
drawing a line; it’s an issue of articulating the
the very beings he intends to shepherd.
specificity of how different forms of life exist
CW: Yes, I think that’s really well put. And this in the world, and the ethical and political conse-
is what Esposito is attempting to do with this quences for norms that one would want to
figure of flesh in his own work on the derive from that. And insisting on that

182
broglio

phenomenological dimension is precisely what you to give a robust, naturalistic account of


Heidegger is right about critiquing biological how phenomenological domains arise that
or zoological continuism; he’s right that these cannot be reduced to the biological or the zool-
kinds of issues can’t be simply reduced to a ogical. At this point, then, you could also veer
kind of zoological or biological description. off, if you wanted, into Stiegler’s entire reread-
What he’s wrong about is that the radically ing of Heidegger, which would be an important
ahuman character of Dasein coincides in any part of that conversation. But that’s the articula-
way with the distinction between human and tion it seems to me that it has to be made in
animal. And so I think it’s crucial to hold onto relation to reframing the specific character of
the phenomenological dimension even as you the phenomenological.
can give a robust naturalistic, rather than trans-
cendental, account of how the phenomenologi- RB: That’s interesting because then once you
cal arises in the first place. play that out you begin to talk about cultures,
You could point to what I call in the book the right?
scandal of the cephalopods, for example. The CW: Very quickly you do. And even there I
scandal of the cephalopods is that cephalopods think it’s useful to more finely parse the vocabu-
demonstrate everything that I mean by nonhu- lary. I’m thinking, for example, of Maturana
man, animal Dasein. And yet, they don’t have and Varela’s discussion of the difference
the physiological and biological architecture between linguistic domains and language
that is shared with mammals – they’re not ver- proper. Those are actually two different
tebrates or even chordates, number one. And things, and language proper is actually a
number two, the kinds of behaviors that they second order phenomenon that arises on the
demonstrate have always been presumed to basis of the capacity for linguistic domains
exist only in animals that have a sufficiently that is broadly shared by lots of different nonhu-
long lifespan and live in social groups. But man animals. But that actually only leads to
neither is true for the cephalopods. Giant language proper in only very rare instances.
squids live about three years … It’s a much more finely tuned theoretical appar-
RB: Wow, I didn’t realize so short. atus, I think, for describing what we would
otherwise call phenomenology.
CW: Yes, and almost all of the cephalopods are
solitary. RB: That’s right. So phenomenology itself is
too much of a blanket term?
RB: Yes.
CW: Far too much of a blanket term. It’s too
CW: So, where does this Dasein come from?
blunt of an instrument. Even as the insistence
Nobody knows.
on disarticulating the properly phenomenologi-
RB: We were talking about Bateson earlier, cal from the biological and the zoological is
and his “ecology of mind” stuff seems useful absolutely right. That’s why Derrida himself
here. agrees with Heidegger’s resistance to “biological
continuism,” and says it would be “asinine.”
CW: Yes. To fully evacuate the humanism of
the description, you have to look back into a RB: So, this is slightly along the lines of
kind of systems theoretical description of auto- Derrida in The Animal That Therefore I Am
poiesis, emergent behaviors, structural coup- where he develops contours by which to differ-
lings, embodied enaction, and the like to have entiate a community of beings “not in affect-
a vocabulary that enables you to talk about the ing the limit, but in multiplying its figures
specificity of these things in a robust way and complicating, thickening …” The multiply
across species lines. And it enables you to give folded, re-fractured abyss relates to what you
– and this is, to me, the theoretical challenge are doing in the middle of your book where
that has to be met and is difficult – it enables you address the problem of welcoming all

183
after animality

animals and the problem of infinite hospital- biologically, or physiologically (or even, you
ity. I think you’re responding to Esposito’s might say more broadly, socially or culturally).
call for recognition of “life singular and imper- In other words, whatever that process of extend-
sonal.” Hospitality, to such a wide swathe of ing hospitality is, it radically has (to use psycho-
life, and forms of life, and living beings, analytic language) an unconscious, one that’s
seems impossible or an ideal limit – an absol- not just psychoanalytic but is actually biologi-
ute hospitality. cal, physiological, and involves communities of
different kinds of life forms that inhabit differ-
CW: Right. That’s the passage I was invoking.
ent creatures (and vice versa) in radically differ-
RB: So it’s not a matter of division between ent ways in terms of their own autopoiesis. And
man and animal, but rather humans among so the point of unconditional hospitality is not
other animals differentiated by a number of that it’s actually possible, but that it should
figures and folds. So in all of this, then, how always be a kind of horizon to strive for to
is one to think about the limits of hospitality prevent the immunitary foreclosure of self-refer-
between humans and other animals? ence. This horizon, or this desire, or whatever
you want to call it, of unconditional hospitality,
CW: I think the sense of this that’s underneath
is precisely to remind you that in that decision
your question is spot on, and this is related to
and in that moment you will be shown, at
something I was talking about earlier. What
some point later, to have been wrong. And the
Esposito is up to at the end of Bios seems to
reason that this is crucial to biopolitical
me, actually for this very reason, a radically de-
thought is that it keeps that zone of immunologi-
differentiating move in declaring in effect the
cal protection from automatically turning into,
radical equality in all forms of life. Now,
as Derrida puts it, an autoimmune disorder.
that’s problematic for a number of reasons,
The idea is that once you start drawing lines
some of them philosophical and some of them
between humans and animals, Aryans and
pragmatic – I mean since we are, after all, to
Jews, Muslims and Christians, that is always
take him at his word that we are talking about
going to lead to the runaway train process of
norms in relation to ethics and politics. A prag-
an autoimmune disorder. So eventually, you
matic problem that I underscore in the book is
know, how Aryan is Aryan enough? How Chris-
that his position takes us right back to the
tian is Christian enough? How human is human
debates that took place in North America, but
enough? How “proper,” to go back to Heideg-
beyond as well, back in the 70s and 80s
ger, is proper enough? The horizon of uncondi-
around biocentrism and around deep ecology.
tional hospitality as something to strive for is
So, if he’s right, are we then supposed to allow
precisely calculated to remind you that whatever
anthrax, and Ebola virus, and Hanta virus,
those liens are that you are drawing have to
and S.A.R.S., and so on, to achieve their crea-
always be taken under erasure, even as, pragma-
tive flourishing even if it means, you know, a
tically, those lines have to be drawn and are
70 percent die off of the human population?
drawn all the time. As Derrida puts it, in offer-
You’re very quickly led to these kinds of prag-
ing any kind of hospitality you are always perfor-
matic dilemmas. And that’s a debate that I
matively offering something specific,
don’t think Esposito or people working in
determinate, and conditional. If you weren’t,
Italian political philosophy around biopolitics
things like politics would have no binding force.
really have any reason to know much about –
the debates about deep ecology and biocentrism. RB: For Heidegger, animals are benumb to the
A theoretical and philosophical problem – and possibility of seeing objects themselves? The
this is the part that’s related to what I was animals do see and interact with the world
talking about earlier – is that it’s not as if the around them. So, if not a Heideggerian clearing
organism is ever in a position to unilaterally that’s reserved, say, for humans, then is it poss-
exercise an unconditional hospitality, either ible that animals have some other sort of

184
broglio

clearing and revealing available to them and and least proper. It’s a polluted, contaminated,
not to humans? So even Heidegger, in addres- hybrid relationship between the human and
sing the poverty of animals, admits this. That the nonhuman, the biological and the technical,
is, the living flesh of animals is not “something that makes possible any apprehension of the
inferior, or that is a lower level when in compari- world whatsoever. So the funny thing is that at
son to the human Dasein. On the contrary, life is the end of the day, to make a very long story
a demanding which possesses a wealth of being short, Heidegger’s description of animals in
opened, of which the human world may know relation to the world as “having a world in the
nothing at all.” So is it possible to think of mode of not having” is actually the best descrip-
such a wealth of being open? And how would tion of Dasein that we have.
one approach such a mode of thinking?
RB: You know what’s interesting is very early
on you were saying we really need a different
CW: It is attractive to think that, but I think it
language because almost formed within the
requires an articulation that’s radically non-Hei-
Heideggerian construct he’s already prefigured
deggerian. And the reason I think it has to be
his own sense of a humanity as a very sort of
radically non-Heideggerian is that the distinc-
particular way of being.
tion between the open and its other is like the
distinction between the “proper” and the impro- CW: Yes, and Derrida’s emphasis on this ques-
per in Heidegger. It is a firm distinction, and a tion of the “proper” in Heidegger is a key
distinction that is not under erasure, as moment in drawing that out.
Derrida would put it. And actually, what I
RB: So what sorts of language do you think
argue – quite the contrary – in the book is
will become available for talking about this?
that Heidegger’s description of animals having
a world in the mode of not having is maybe CW: Well, I think there are different languages
the best description of Dasein that we’re going that can be useful here. One that I’ve already
to get. Humans don’t have a relationship to mentioned in my own work is my attempt to
the world, in Heidegger’s words, “as such and cross articulate the kind of work that Derrida
in its being.” That’s a fantasy of the “proper” does with work in second order systems theory
of the human in relation to the open that’s and, beyond that, in people like Bateson. But
made possible by the fact that humans, for Hei- another example – just to sort of shift gears for
degger, possess language and animals don’t, a moment – that I know you’re really interested
which in turn grounds the phenomenological in is the kind of work that artists do. Artists
possibility to have a relation to the world “as have a lot to teach us about the relationship
such and in its being.” What I argue (and this between specific sensory modes that are different
is really just following Derrida’s reading of Hei- for different creatures in relation to the media
degger) is that human beings don’t have a that make possible specific forms of meaning.
relationship to the world as such and in its They’re sensitive to it because they work with
being because language doesn’t work that way those media so closely, in a way that people
and meaning doesn’t work that way. So our who just work with words and texts aren’t. So I
relationship to the world through language or think there are different kinds of languages and
through other forms of meaning, or other sorts different kinds of practices that can address
of knowledge-making schemata, is made poss- these questions. Something that needs to be
ible by the technicity of a semiosis that is radi- added here (and this is maybe just a segue into
cally not ours and radically not us – and, in talking about the Posthumanities series) is that
fact, radically nonorganic. It is machinic, or this doesn’t mean that the traditional languages
une “grille,” as Derrida puts it in Signature, of humanism aren’t useful and important. This
Event, Context. And so what is most ours, goes back to what I was saying earlier about not
what is most “proper,” to our relationship to wanting to jettison what Heidegger’s right
the open is precisely that which is least ours about, I think, in the question of the

185
after animality

phenomenological. It would be a humanist RB: I’ve heard about this, yes.


fantasy, in fact, to think that one could just “post-
humanistically” institute a radical rupture and CW: Monty Roberts was the first famous “horse
not be informed by those languages. It’s more whisperer” on the scene, but this guy, Buck, has
about saying, well, you know, the commitments a remarkable technique when working with
and the desires and the interests of a lot of horses. If you’ve read Vicki Hearne’s work,
work in humanism are important. But the philo- for example, you get a picture of the super
sophical and theoretical tools used to articulate specific way that horses are in the world –
those commitments are actually self-defeating their bodily sensitivity, how they’re not like
and actually undercut and foreclose those inter- dogs, and so on. Anyway, the interesting thing
ests and commitments. An example of this that about this documentary is that this guy does a
I discuss in What is Posthumanism? is the use kind of traveling road show, and he goes into
of rights discourse in relation to the ethical stand- these highly skeptical communities where the
ing of nonhuman animals. I think we would all only way people know how to train horses is
agree that an admirable desire of humanism by “breaking” horses. Well, he goes into these
would be to respect the standing of at least communities and in about ten or fifteen
some nonhuman animals and to protect them minutes the traditional horse breaking people
from exploitation, cruelty, and so on. But the on the scene watch what he’s doing with the
attempt to articulate that desire, which is an horses and they just can’t believe it. As he’s
admirable one, in terms of the rights framework interacting with the horses, he’s taking advan-
ends up foreclosing and undercutting that desire tage of his understanding of their visual field
by reinstating a normative picture of the subject and how they see the world, how they respond
of rights that ends up being humanist and anthro- to different kinds of touch, both light and
pocentric through and through, that ends up heavy, all sorts of things. Like Monty Roberts,
with a being that looks a lot like us, so that, in he has an extraordinary sensitivity to what you
the end, nonhuman animals matter because might call the bodily gestural nature and reper-
they are just a diminished version of us. It toire of horses and how it is constantly commu-
seems to me self-evident that trying to think nicating in ways that he’s sensitive to but other
about the value of dolphins in terms of their people can’t see. Anyway, as the story unfolds,
being diminished versions of Homo sapiens we learn that when he was a child he and his
makes no sense. And at that point, people like brother would go on television and perform all
Judith Butler and Cora Diamond, on these these roping and lassoing tricks. They were
issues of vulnerability and precarious life, come little cowboy celebrities. But what Buck also
back into the picture as an alternative to the reveals, as the movie unfolds, is that he and
entire rights framework. his brother were severely beaten by their
father when they were kids – beaten and
RB: You know, I think the ability to think the almost “broken,” really. So what becomes
vulnerable … I mean reason is such a tool of clear in the film is that there is a very deep con-
mastery and so many of our projects have been nection between his own experience of his own
projects of mastery; so, to think the vulnerable bodily vulnerability as child, his own bodily
and to write it in a way that itself is not necess- exposure to violence, to what his dad did to
arily masterful. That is, you’re not mastering vul- him, and his refusal to impose that sort of vio-
nerability either. It is sort of a current challenge. lence on animals, which then led him to
CW: Did you see this film Buck? develop great sensitivity to the embodiment of
other creatures in ways that enabled him to
RB: No.
work with horses in a way that almost no one
CW: This is something you should see. It’s a else can. And I would say in that situation that
documentary about this real Montana cowboy you have in play both the embodied, the biologi-
who is sort of the original “horse whisperer.” cal or zoological, and the phenomenological, in

186
broglio

the sense of shared meaning taking place across “green” pole – our relations to nonhuman
species lines. They’re both in play in that animals and more broadly the environment.
relationship. And this brings us back to these But then we have other works in the series
“aleatory” and creative elements of biopower that gravitate more toward the “gray” end of
that we were talking about earlier. the spectrum. Thierry Bardini’s book Junkware
would be a good example. But a lot of books in
RB: Let’s turn the conversation a bit. I’d like to
the series actually work at the crossing of these
talk some about your book series Posthuman-
two as well. Dominic Pettman’s book Human
ism with the University of Minnesota Press.
Error: Species Being and Media Machines is
By now the series has had enough books in it
a good example. And, you know, thinking
that you’re beginning to get a sense of the
back to what you might call the prehistory of
mosaic regarding what is this question of post-
the series, Donna Haraway’s work has always
humanism and how it’s developing. Maybe we
been in a way situated at that crossing point.
can talk a little bit about that as well as the
So those are the poles that define the nexus
types of books in the series.
within which the series operates, and when
CW: The original rubric in the series as I pre- you think about it, it is a pretty generous
sented it to the press has to do with posthuman- space. What I wanted to do in the series is
ism as a fundamental decentering of the human that I precisely did not want to do an “animal
as a constitutive category, one that can’t, any studies” series. As I argue in What is Posthu-
more, do any heavy lifting in an explanatory manism?, I don’t even like this term “the
way in relation to the situation in which we animal,” much less the term “animal studies,”
find ourselves. You can describe that as a his- and even if I did, both of those for me are
torical phenomenon if you want, having to do subsets and sub-questions of this broader ques-
with a whole range of developments in technol- tion of posthumanism. “The animal” is one
ogy, information, medicine, economics, and so terrain on which those questions of posthuman-
on – all sorts of factors that have made the ism play themselves out and can be explored
human no longer “master in his own house.” with particular stakes that are different, of
The series rubric was originally framed as course, from other areas that you might investi-
exploring that question between two poles. gate. So my hope is that these two poles open up
One was the decentering of the human vis-à- a space in which these constitutive terms can
vis a “green” dimension, in relation to questions constantly destabilize each other and trouble
of ecology, so-called animal rights, environ- each other and interrogate each other to
mentalism, global warming, the extinction of deepen our sense of the ways in which posthu-
other creatures, etc. The imbrication of the manism plays out in different areas. A major
human within these larger biological, ecological, challenge of the series that we were talking
zoological networks of relations. The other pole, about earlier is, you know, that a book series
the so-called “gray” pole, would be the decenter- is something that unfolds in real time, so you
ing of the human in relation to informatic and don’t want to do four or five of the same kind
communication technologies, economic struc- of book at the same time. It’s not just about
tures and systems, and different forms of the abstract, synchronic, conceptual nature of
media in an increasingly prosthetic and over- the series; you’re also always dealing with ques-
determined relation of the human and its ways tions of a kind of choreography of the list for the
of knowing and acting in the world to things fall and the spring, the mix of books that are
like cell phones or the Internet. When projects going to be on that list. We get projects that
come to the series, they tend to break off in are right for the series, but I’ll have to tell
one of those two directions. For example, Mick authors that we just did a book like that, or
Smith’s book on ecological sovereignty is an we’re about to. So that’s a second level on
obvious example; your book would be another which the mosaic is constantly reconfigured.
example that’s clearly associated with the My feeling is really we’re just getting started.

187
after animality

The series began, technically, in 2007, and we that come across my desk, which in turn reshape
were doing four books a year – now we’re how I think about these questions. So the biopo-
doing six books a year. My challenge as an litical dimension of the issue is central for me
editor is to keep the series unexpected and now in a way that it wasn’t five or six years
fresh for people, and not let it turn into some- ago, in no small part because of the work I’ve
thing – and this a danger for any book series been doing as an editor.
or a journal – that becomes a mechanism for
RB: So, do you think in Foucault’s sort of
codification of a particular position or theoreti-
understanding of the biopolitical, that there
cal approach. So, for example, we’re doing a
is already something of the posthuman
clutch of books right now around Speculative
within it?
Realism and Object Oriented Ontology – Ian
Bogost’s book Alien Phenomenology, among CW: Absolutely, yes. This goes back to what we
others. This is not because I myself am were talking about earlier. The posthumanist
especially enamored of Object Oriented Ontol- dimension – or one of the posthumanist dimen-
ogy or Speculative Realism – I’m not. It’s that sions, I actually think there are many – of Fou-
I think there are a lot of obviously very smart cault’s work on this question is precisely to
people who are interested in this work right demonstrate that whatever we’re talking about
now, so perhaps if that work is a part of the here is not a question of “the subject.” That is
series, there can be some interesting crosstalk not an adequate vocabulary to describe the
between it and other, very different, work in highly complex articulations of bodies – human
the series; it’ll make possible a conversation and nonhuman – with technologies in relation
that maybe I myself am not that interested in to political and economic formations. Foucault
getting that deeply into in my own work, but allows us to rearticulate these questions so that,
that many readers will be interested in. So as I argue in the book, you can understand some-
that’s the editorial challenge: how to use your thing like factory farming – and the fallout of
own expertise, but not let it turn into a matter factory farming, economically, ecologically, also
of simply reproducing your own thinking, with regard to things like antibiotics and public
your own approach to these questions. health – as what Foucault calls “a new schema
of politicization.” It’s not just an ethical issue.
RB: Yes. Do you think that having seen the
It’s a robustly political issue. But you’ve got to
series play out and also work that’s in the pipe-
have a political vocabulary that allows you to
line that your understanding of posthumanism
talk about the articulation of technologies and
has changed as a result of that?
bodies in the service of the commodification of
CW: Yes, I think it has changed because just in life in a way that makes it legible as a political
the five years that the series has been up and issue. So that requires a posthumanist vocabulary
running, a lot of the conversations have that sees politics as no longer being about ques-
changed. Take, for example, my own work and tions of agency, autonomy, inten-
the new book that we’ve just been talking tionality, the subject, reciprocity,
about. Five, six, seven years ago, questions of and so on, but something far
biopolitics were really not that central to my more complicated and distribu-
approach to these questions around nonhuman ted going on.
life. That’s different now, and it’s different
partly because of work that we’ve done in the
series, projects that I’ve read in consideration
of the series, and conversations that editing
the series made me aware of in a deeper way note
than I would have been otherwise. So, for me, 1 The following interview was conducted while at
part of the payoff of editing the series is that the Modern Language Association conference in
I’m constantly being reeducated by the projects Seattle. The conversation took place on 14

188
broglio

January 2012 at the Edgewater Hotel. Wolfe’s


book Before the Law: Humans and Animals in a Biopo-
litical Frame was still forthcoming and discussion of
the book was from a completed draft.

Ron Broglio
Department of English
PO Box 870302
Arizona State University
Tempe, AZ 85287-0302
USA
E-mail: ron.broglio@asu.edu
notes on the contributors
steve baker seung-hoon jeong
is an independent writer, researcher and artist, is Assistant Professor of Cinema Studies at
affiliated to the University of Central Lancashire New York University Abu Dhabi. He received
as Emeritus Professor of Art History. His most Korea’s Cine21 Film Criticism Award in 2003
recent book is Artist|Animal, in the “Posthu- and the Society for Cinema & Media Studies
manities” series from the University of Minne- Dissertation Award in 2012. He has published
sota Press. He is also the author of The on diverse filmmakers such as Werner Herzog,
Postmodern Animal; Picturing the Beast; Peter Greenaway, and Apichatpong Weerasetha-
and, with the Animal Studies Group, Killing kul, on major theorists such as André Bazin,
Animals. His recent roadkill imagery has been Gilles Deleuze, and Jacques Rancière, and
reproduced and discussed in the journals on critical issues such as the animal, multicultur-
Antennae, Art & Research, and Tierstudien, alism, and catastrophe in cinema. His book
and shown in group exhibitions in London, Cinematic Interfaces: Film Theory after New
New Orleans and Melbourne. Media is forthcoming with Routledge in 2013.

ron broglio stephen loo


is an associate professor in the Department of is an architect, artist and philosopher, and
English at Arizona State University and Senior Professor of Architecture at the University of
Scholar at the university’s Global Institute of Tasmania, Australia. He has published widely
Sustainability. His research focuses on how phil- on language, affect and the biophilosophy of
osophy and aesthetics can help us rethink the the contemporary subject, posthumanist ethics
relationship between humans and the environ- and experimental digital thinking. His forth-
ment. He is author of Surface Encounters: coming edited book with Hélène Frichot is
Thinking with Animals and Art (U of Minne- Deleuze and Architecture (Edinburgh UP).
sota P, 2011) and Technologies of the Pictur-
esque (Bucknell, 2008).
john mullarkey
is Professor of Film and Television Studies at
allison hunter
Kingston University, London. He has also
is Artist-in-Residence at Rice University. More taught philosophy and film theory at the Univer-
information can be found at <www.allisonhun- sity of Sunderland, England (1994–2004) and
ter.com>. the University of Dundee, Scotland (2004–10).
He has published Bergson and Philosophy
(Edinburgh UP, 1999), Post-Continental Phil-
osophy: An Outline (Continuum, 2006), Philos-
ophy and the Moving Image: Refractions of
Reality (Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), and
edited, with Anthony Paul Smith, Laruelle
and Non-philosophy (Edinburgh UP, 2012).
He is currently working on a book entitled
Reverse Mutations: Laruelle and Nonhuman
Philosophy.

191
marcel o’gorman daniel ross
is an associate professor in the Department of is the author of the book Violent Democracy
English at the University of Waterloo and Direc- (Cambridge UP, 2004) and director of the film
tor of the Critical Media Lab. His published The Ister (Black Box Sound and Image, 2004).
research, including E-Crit: Digital Media, He has written numerous articles on Bernard
Critical Theory and the Humanities (U of Stiegler and translated many of his works,
Toronto P, 2006), is concerned primarily with including the books Acting Out (Stanford UP,
the fate of the humanities in a digital culture. 2009), For a New Critique of Political
O’Gorman’s most recent work investigates the Economy (Polity, 2010), The Decadence of
“collusion of death and technology,” a concept Industrial Democracies (Polity, 2011) and
that he calls “necromedia.” O’Gorman is also a Uncontrollable Societies of Disaffected Indi-
practising artist, working primarily with phys- viduals (Polity, 2012).
ical computing inventions and architectural
installations. Visit the Critical Media Lab at
undine sellbach
<http://criticalmedia.uwaterloo.ca>.
is a philosopher, writer and performer, based in
the School of Philosophy, University of Tasma-
jussi parikka
nia, Australia. Her publications explore the
is Reader in Media & Design at Winchester imagination in relation to notions of life,
School of Art (University of Southampton) gender, instinct, ethics and the unconscious.
and Adjunct Professor in Digital Culture Undine and Stephen Loo are currently working
Theory (University of Turku). He is the on a monograph on psychoanalysis, ethics and
author of Digital Contagions (Lang, 2007), the entomological imagination of childhood.
Insect Media (U of Minnesota P, 2010) and Their performance-based work includes Whirl-
What is Media Archaeology? (Polity, 2012). wind of Insects in the Body of a Girl for the
Recently he edited the online book Media- Sexuate Subjects international conference at Uni-
natures (http://livingbooksaboutlife.org/). versity College London (2010), The Grasshopper
Cabaret for the Architecture-Writing sym-
posium at KTH Stockholm (2012) and Mistress
dominic pettman
O & the Bees for the Kelly’s Garden Curated Pro-
is Chair of Culture and Media, Eugene Lang jects and the Sydney Biennale (2012).
College, as well as Associate Professor of
Liberal Studies, New School for Social Research.
bernard stiegler
He is the author of After the Orgy: Toward a
Politics of Exhaustion (State U of New York is a French philosopher, Director of the Institut
P, 2002), Avoiding the Subject: Media, de recherche et d’innovation, and founder of the
Culture and the Object (Amsterdam UP, 2004 School of Philosophy at Epineuil-le-Fleuriel.
– with Justin Clemens), Love and Other Technol- Since 1994 he has published some thirty
ogies: Retrofitting Eros for the Information Age books, including Technics and Time, 1 (Stan-
(Fordham UP, 2006), Human Error: Species- ford UP, 1998), The Decadence of Industrial
Being and Media Machines (U of Minnesota Democracies (Polity, 2011), and Uncontrollable
P, 2011) and Look at the Bunny: Totem, Societies of Disaffected Individuals (Polity,
Taboo, Technology (Zero, 2013). 2012). His most recent major works are Ce qui
fait que la vie vaut la peine d’être vécue. De
la pharmacologie (Flammarion, 2010), Etats
de choc. Bêtise et savoir au XXIe siècle (Mille
et une nuits, 2012) and Pharmacologie du
Front national (Flammarion, 2013).

192
eugene thacker frederick young
is the author of a number of books, including In is faculty in the Merritt Writing Program at the
the Dust of this Planet – Horror of Philosophy, University of California, Merced. Before com-
vol. 1 (Zero, 2011), and After Life (U of Chicago pleting a post-doctorate in New Media at
P, 2010). Thacker teaches at The New School in Georgia Tech, he received a Ph.D. in High
New York. Theory, Media and Culture Studies at the Uni-
versity of Florida. He was a Senior Lecturer in
English and New Media in Sweden and also lec-
tom tyler
tured in Nepal. Many of his publications are
is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy and Culture at concerned with animality, post-structuralist
Oxford Brookes University, UK. His research theory as well as moving towards art practice.
concerns the use of animals, and the persistent He has collaborated with several conceptual
expression of anthropocentric assumptions, artists. Currently he is working on a lengthy
within philosophy, critical theory, and popular theoretical treatise on the question of revolu-
culture. He is the editor of Animal Beings (Paral- tion, animality and technics. With Linus Lan-
lax, 2006), the co-editor of Animal Encounters caster, he is collaborating on the same topic
(Brill, 2009), and the author of CIFERAE: A Bes- using art practice as an interdiction for a new
tiary in Five Fingers (U of Minnesota P, 2012). “politics of art.”

cary wolfe
Cary Wolfe’s books and edited collections
include Animal Rites: American Culture, the
Discourse of Species, and Posthumanist
Theory (U of Chicago P, 2003), the edited col-
lections Zoontologies: The Question of the
Animal (U of Minnesota P, 2003) and, most
recently, What is Posthumanism? (U of Minne-
sota P, 2010) and Before the Law: Humans and
other Animals in a Biopolitical Frame (U of
Chicago P, 2012). He has also participated in
two multi-authored collections: Philosophy
and Animal Life (Columbia UP, 2008), with
philosophers Cora Diamond, Ian Hacking,
Stanley Cavell, and John McDowell, and The
Death of the Animal: A Dialogue (Columbia
UP, 2009), with philosophers Paola Cavalieri,
Peter Singer, Harlan Miller, Matthew Calarco,
and novelist J.M. Coetzee. He is founding
editor of the Posthumanities series at the Uni-
versity of Minnesota Press, which publishes
six books per year by noted authors such as
Donna Haraway, Roberto Esposito, Isabelle
Stengers, Michel Serres, Vilem Flusser, and
many others. He is founding director of 3CT:
Center for Critical and Cultural Theory, at
Rice University.
ANGELAKI
journal of the theoretical humanities
volume 18 number 1 march 2013

In the Notes on Contributors for issue 17


volume 4 the first entry for Amir Ahmadi
should read:

amir ahmadi
is a Ph.D. candidate at the School of Languages,
Cultures and Linguistics, Monash University, in
the field of ancient Iranian languages and myths.

CORRIGENDUM

ISSN 0969-725X print/ISSN 1469-2899 online/13/010195-1 © 2013 Taylor & Francis


http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0969725X.2013.780793

195

You might also like