You are on page 1of 4

“  [T]he usual opposition of first-person vs.

third-person accounts is misleading. It makes us


less circularity of knowledge emergence
means that we, in the end, cannot reveal
Toma Strle is a philosopher, cognitive scientist, and
assistant professor at the University of Ljubljana.
forget that so-called third-person, objective ac- “invariants of the mind” (see also Strle He holds a bachelor’s degree in philosophy and a
counts are done by a community of concrete peo- 2016b). For instance, “invariant phenom- doctorate in philosophy and cognitive science (he
ple who are embodied in their social and natural enological structures, such as that of the did his PhD on the topic of the role of metacognition

1996: 340)

world as much as first-person accounts. (Varela embodied nature of cognition” (§50) that
Varela (1996) seems to hope for (but see
in decision-making). His main research interests
include decision-making, metacognition,
Petitmengin 2017) in his neurophenom- consciousness and the relation between first- and
« 12 »  What is problematic is that this enological programme. And, would we not, third-person approaches to studying the mind.
double-natured embeddedness (in a scien- by presupposing that such invariants do, in
tific culture and life-world) of inferring has fact, “exist to be discovered,” end up behav- Received: 7 October 2017
remained unreflected and not researched in ing in a similar way to the way third-person Accepted: 12 October 2017
cognitive science. But if we are to radically sciences do?
embody cognitive science, as Martiny ar- « 15 »  What is more, is it not that cogni-
gues (e.g., in §§9, 11, 20, 66), we cannot stop tive science is, in fact, about “variant enti-
at systematic research of experience or at ties of the mind” that, to use the language Varela on the Pragmatic
uncovering correlations with third-person of Ian Hacking (quoted from Brinkmann
accounts of mental phenomena, the “mild” 2005), change according to the classifica-
Dimension of Phenomenology
Andrea Pace Giannotta
Cognitive science Concepts in Enaction

neurophenomenology promises (see Petit- tions, descriptions and actions pertaining


mengin 2017 for the distinction between to them? That is, are not “entities” that cog-
University of Florence, Italy
light or mild and deep or radical neurophe- nitive science tries to understand actually
nomenology). What is required, is (system- much more “fluid” and “unstable” than we andreapacegiannotta/at/gmail.com
atic) reflection upon and research (see, e.g., would want to admit, possibly ever chang-
Kordeš 2016 and Petitmengin 2017) into our ing according to how we approach them? I > Upshot • I examine Varela’s relation-
own theoretical stance(s), presuppositions am not sure whether the author is willing to ship with Husserl’s phenomenology,
and practices (whatever they are: third-, endorse such a radical opening up of cog- highlighting Varela’s acknowledgment
first- or second-person). Namely, theories, nitive science and it would be interesting to of the pragmatic dimension of its phe-
research and findings are structured around hear what he thinks about the possibility of nomenological reduction. I argue that
and constituted by presuppositions, prac- such an endless “looping” of understanding Varela sees, in some developments of
tices and values of the research community the mind that has been, in somewhat differ- phenomenology, a deconstruction of the
and the life-world we are embedded in. ent words, already described by Varela in, subject-object duality and an embodied
« 13 »  If we do not try to understand for instance, his 1984 article “The Creative view of the mind. I also highlight the
and research how our own practices, values Circle: Sketches on the Natural History of existential dimension of Varela’s radical
and viewpoints bear upon the findings and Circularity.” proposal, which contributes to further
conclusions we draw from our research, and « 16 »  Admittedly, even though the in- opening up and embodying cognitive
if we do not try to understand how the world trinsic circularity of trying to understand science.
78 we inhabit bears upon the very practices, the mind, the world and their relation is,
values and viewpoints we passionately de- arguably, unavoidable, and awareness of it « 1 »  Kristian Martiny’s target article
fend, we cannot understand (or claim to be possibly necessitates a kind of existential successfully shows how to “open up” and
endorsing) the full scope of the circularity uncertainty, we should not try to escape “embody” the cognitive sciences. Draw-
that is intrinsic to any research and under- from it by remaining in the “safe” grounds ing on his research on cerebral palsy, Mar-
standing of the mind (and, possibly of the of third-person sciences or, nowadays, in tiny argues that the cognitive scientist must
enactive view of cognitive science). As is suc- “mild” neurophenomenology. For, only by question the objectivist and observational
cinctly put forth by Maurice Merleau-Ponty allowing uncertainties to remain a part of premises that are present in most of the clas-
towards the end of his Phenomenology of our life-world, can we, in fact, claim to be sical cognitive sciences, by working simul-
Perception: opening up cognitive science and, to quote taneously with first-, second- and third-per-
Varela, allow for ethics to be “the very foun- son approaches and by the rethinking of the
“  The world is inseparable from the subject, but
from a subject who is nothing but a project of the
dation of knowledge, and also its final point”
(Varela 1984: 323).
concept of what a laboratory is by, e.g., en-
gaging with subjects in the everyday world
world; and the subject is inseparable from the « 17 »  All said, I strongly sympathise and working with audio-visual media and

world, but from a world that it itself projects.
(Merleau-Ponty 2012: 454)
with Martiny’s call for opening up cognitive
science. His take on what it means to be an
theatre. Martiny argues that these strategies
for opening up the cognitive sciences were
embodied cognitive scientist is, in my view, a first introduced by Francisco Varela more
« 14 »  The hard question of course is, welcome illumination and critique of cogni- than 25 years ago, with his radical proposal
whether endorsing such a seemingly end- tive science. of an enactive approach to cognitive science

Constructivist Foundations vol. 13, N°1


Enaction
Varela on the Pragmatic Dimension of Phenomenology Andrea Pace Giannotta

and the subsequent development of neu- “what” he described but “how” he did it theory of the life-world was not reductionistic and
rophenomenology and the second-person
method.
(§18). VTR acknowledge the fact that, espe-
cially in The Crisis of European Sciences and

representationalist. (Thompson 2007: 413f)

« 2 »  I consider Martiny’s development Transcendental Phenomenology (Husserl « 5 »  Thompson details the reasons why
of Varela’s project effective and fruitful. 1970), Husserl acknowledged the practical he and the other authors of EM were mis-
However, I will focus my commentary on and lived aspects of experience by devel- taken, admitting that, when they wrote EM,
an aspect that is only briefly touched upon oping the notion of “life-world,” but he did their knowledge of Husserl was limited and
by Martiny: the relationship between Va- so in a purely theoretical way, developing a that they were misled by Martin Heidegger’s
rela’s proposal and Edmund Husserl’s phe- disembodied reflection on the embodiment “largely uncharitable […] reading of Hus-
nomenology, especially in §§17–19. Here, of the mind. However, if we look at the de- serl” (Thompson 2007: 414) and by Hubert
Martiny takes up Varela’s opinion that Hus- velopment of both Varela’s and Thompson’s Dreyfus’s influential interpretation of Hus-
serl’s phenomenology lacks a pragmatic di- philosophies after EM, we become aware serl as a “representationalist and proto-
mension, without investigating Varela’s later that the criticism that they had in mind cognitivist philosopher” (Thompson 2007:
comments to the contrary. In addition, I concerned not only the “how” but also the 414).1
would like to highlight a further, existential “what” of the phenomenological analysis « 6 »  This reappraisal had already been
dimension of Varela’s radical proposal that is of experience. These authors thought that, made by Varela, whose reference to Husserl’s
not mentioned in Martiny’s article, one that apart from some elements in Husserl’s later phenomenology became more and more
contributes to further opening up and em- works such as the notion of life-world, most central after the publication of EM. Martiny
bodying cognitive science. of the phenomenological analyses present us (§31) acknowledges that the subsequent de-
« 3 »  According to Martiny, a crucial with an abstract and disembodied concep- velopment of neurophenomenology (Varela
aspect of Varela’s radical proposal consists tion of subjectivity. In the words of Thomp- 1996) and the second-person method (Vare-
in embodying cognition, in contrast to the son: la & Shear 1999) are essentially based on the
disembodying aspects of classical cognitive phenomenological analysis of experience. In
science. In §17ff., Martiny parallels these
disembodying aspects with similar ones
“ In The Embodied Mind, we asserted (i) that
Husserl was a methodological solipsist (p. 16);
contrast to the hasty dismissal of Husserl’s
project in EM, considered a “failure” (Varela,
that are present in Husserl’s phenomenol- (ii) that his theory ignored ‘both the consensual Thompson & Rosch 1991: 19), Varela (1996)
ogy and that are criticized by Varela, Evan aspect and the direct embodied aspect of experi- considers the method of neurophenomenol-
Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch (VTR) in ence’ (p. 17); (iii) that his theory of intentionality ogy to be in accordance with the phenom-
The Embodied Mind (EM; Varela, Thompson was a representational theory (p. 68); (iv) that his enological method. I would like to stress the
& Rosch 1991). Notwithstanding the fact theory of the life-world was reductionistic and fact that this reappraisal concerns both the
that Husserl’s phenomenology is an essential representationalist (that he tried to analyze the theoretical and pragmatic dimensions of
source of inspiration for the development of life-world ‘into a more fundamental set of con- phenomenology. Varela takes the concept
the enactive proposal of EM, VTR argue stituents’ (p. 117) consisting of belief understood of phenomenological reduction (PhR, ibid:
that, in the end, it was “entirely theoretical” as mental representations (p. 18)); and (v) that his 336) and places it at the core of his neu-
and that it “completely lacked any pragmatic phenomenology was a purely abstract, theoreti- rophenomenology. We should note that the
dimension” (ibid: 19). Martiny stresses this cal project lacking a pragmatic dimension (p. 19, PhR has been pointed out by Husserl’s crit-
firm judgment, which sees in Husserl’s phe-
nomenology an example of “disembodying

117). (Thompson 2007: 413) ics as being responsible for the abstract and
disembodied nature of phenomenological
79

philosophical practice” (§21). However, I Thompson devotes appendix A of his Mind investigations. The typical example of this
would like to point out the fact that the rela- in Life (Thompson 2007: 413–416) to ex- kind of criticism can be found in Heidegger
tionship between Varela and Husserl’s phe- plaining in detail his “change of attitude” to- (1992: 109ff.). Varela, on the contrary, sees
nomenology is more complex than what can ward Husserlian phenomenology. Thomp- in the PhR the “how” of the phenomenolog-
be seen in these passages. This is an aspect son claims that “our earlier interpretation ical inquiry, which has significant theoreti-
of Varela’s proposal that is easily overlooked of Husserl was mistaken” (Thompson 2007: cal and pragmatic implications.
but is important in order to understand the 413) and that: « 7 »  Varela likens PhR to mindfulness/
development of Varela’s view and the enac- awareness meditation (Varela 1996: 331,
tive approach as originally formulated in
EM. The issue is: in what way does phe-
“ Husserlian phenomenology has far more re-
sources than we realized for productive cross-
346), which constitutes the “living pragmat-
ics” that lies at the basis of the enactive ap-
nomenology lack a pragmatic dimension fertilization with both the sciences of mind […] proach of EM. Varela considers the PhR to
for VTR? In addition: why do VTR contrast and Buddhist thought […]. In particular, I now be a “capacity for becoming aware” (ibid:
phenomenology with the living pragmatics believe (i) that Husserl was not a methodological 341), through which one can shift from the
of mindfulness/awareness meditation in the solipsist; (ii) that he was greatly concerned with
Buddhist tradition? the intersubjective and embodied aspects of expe- 1 |  These claims are reiterated by Thompson
« 4 »  Martiny claims that the criticisms rience; (iii) that his theory of intentionality was in his introduction to the revised edition of EM
addressed by VTR to Husserl concern not not a representational theory; and (iv) that his (Thompson 2016).

http://constructivist.info/13/1/059.martiny
natural, ordinary attitude of everyday life « 10 »  Varela clearly sees that a certain The pragmatics of mindfulness/aware-
to a new, phenomenological attitude that line of development of Husserl’s phenom- ness meditation embodies these theoreti-
looks at the same ordinary experience in a enology is the foundation of an embodied cal achievements in a lived experience and
reflexive way. The method of PhR allows us view of the mind, which converges with a practice that is cultivated and shared by
to investigate the nature and the structural and complements the enactive approach. a vast community of practitioners. The
invariants of mental processes, by changing In Pace Giannotta (2016) I have argued for pragmatic and existential implications of
the unexamined experiences of the natural this convergence and complementarity be- this practice are stressed by VTR: it allows
attitude into reflexive ones (ibid: 336). The tween Varelian enactivism and Husserlian the meditator to progressively free him-
ensuing phenomenological descriptions phenomenology, especially in its genetic self from the existential suffering (dukkha)
constitute an “‘embodiment’ that incarnates development. In particular, the genetic that characterizes the human condition on
and shapes what we experience” (ibid: 337). analysis of the intentionality of the mind re- many levels. This condition derives from
So conceived, the method of PhR is very veals a primordial process of co-constitution the “grasping” attitude of the mind, which
similar to mindfulness/awareness medita- of subject and object in reciprocal depend- is naturally inclined to conceive of phenom-
tion. This is a method for examining ex- ence. This notion converges with that of co- ena as permanent and substantial. In his
perience by becoming present with one’s dependent arising that is at the heart of the turn, the meditator sees the groundlessness
mind (Varela, Thompson & Rosch 1991: enactive approach of EM (Varela, Thomp- and the emptiness of the notion of a sub-
23). Through mindfulness/awareness the son & Rosch 1991: 110ff, 220ff). stantial reality of all phenomena as a source
meditator can interrupt the ordinary state of « 11 »  This way of understanding Hus- of freedom, joy, and compassion (Varela,
Cognitive science Concepts in Enaction

unmindfulness, cutting the chain of habitual serl’s phenomenological project allows us Thompson & Rosch 1991: 122f, 248). VTR
thought patterns and preconceptions (ibid: to disclose its embodied aspect. As argued point out the profound implications that
27), in order to become acquainted with her by Rudolf Bernet (2013), the investigation the pragmatics of mindfulness/awareness
experience and to examine the nature of of the living and lived body as flesh, which meditation has on the life of practitioners
both cognition and the objects of cognition. is developed by phenomenologists such as and of the transformative potential that it
« 8 »  Varela considers the PhR a skill Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Emmanuel Levi- can have on Western societies and culture at
and a discipline that requires sustained nas and Michel Henry, is first introduced large. I would like to highlight this aspect of
training and that must be cultivated (Varela by Husserl himself in his analysis of bodily the enactive approach of EM and of Varela’s
1996: 346). He also complains about the lack consciousness (especially in Husserl 1989). proposal, because it is often overlooked in
of pragmatic elaboration of the phenomeno- Claire Petitmengin also highlights the con- subsequent discussions of “enactivism.” It
logical method, whose potentialities for the tinuity between Varela’s neurophenomenol- is an “existential” dimension that addresses
investigation of the mind are yet to be fully ogy and Husserl’s genetic phenomenology the fundamental issue of the meaning of the
utilized. Martiny (§31ff) shows well the sub- (Petitmengin 2017: 146), arguing that both human condition.2
sequent successful applications of Varela’s investigate the “process of co-constitution” « 13 »  Concerning this existential ques-
proposal made by him and his followers (ibid:142) of the “objective and subjec- tion, Husserl’s phenomenology does not
to open up and embody cognitive science. tive poles […] within lived experience” appear on the surface to have much to say.
However, I would like to stress the fact that (ibid:141). Notwithstanding this, its deconstruction of
these developments and applications are « 12 »  However, having stressed the the subject-object duality is consistent with
80 based on a pragmatic dimension that Varela continuity between the theoretical and the notions of selflessness and co-depend-
sees as already present in the phenomeno- pragmatic aspects of both Varela’s proposal ent arising. This applies also to some impli-
logical method. and phenomenology, we can detect an im- cations of the cognitive sciences that point
« 9 »  Furthermore, Varela points out portant difference between Husserl’s phe- toward the fragmentation or disunity of
some aspects of Husserl’s phenomenol- nomenology, including its most “embodied” the self (Varela, Thompson & Rosch 1991:
ogy that call into question the idea that it developments, and the pragmatics of mind- 48ff) and of some strands of Western phi-
amounts to an abstract and disembodied fulness/awareness meditation that plays losophy, such as Hume’s deconstruction of
view of subjectivity. Such a view would be such an important role in Varela’s view. I the notion of a substantial self (ibid: 59ff).
based on a hypostatization of the duality would like to refer to it as the existential di- However, according to VTR, in these views
between the cognizing subject and the cog- mension of Varela’s radical proposal. A large there is also at play a refusal to confront the
nized object. On the contrary, according to part of EM is devoted to describing how the existential implications of the discovery of
Varela, practice of mindfulness/awareness leads the selflessness. On the contrary, the pragmat-
meditator to acknowledge the emptiness of ics of mindfulness/awareness meditation
“  [PhR] does not sustain the basic subject-ob-
ject duality but opens into a field of phenomena
the notion of a substantial, permanent and
independent reality of both the self and the 2 |  The central role of this existential aspect
where it becomes less and less obvious how to dis- world. In its stead, the meditator becomes in Varela’s work is highlighted by Bitbol and Elena
tinguish between subject and object (this is what acquainted with the impermanent nature of Antonova (2016: 356), Bitbol (2017: 151), Petit-
Husserl called the ‘fundamental correlation’).
(Varela 1996: 339).
” all phenomena, both subjective and objec-
tive, and their co-dependent origination.
mengin (2017: 146), and Sebastjan Vörös (2017:
150).

Constructivist Foundations vol. 13, N°1


Enaction
On the Second-Person Method Susanne Ravn

consists in facing this discovery in order to On the Second-Person nomena. I will argue that if the purpose of
find within it the source of existential trans- a second-person method is to contribute
formation.
Method: Considering to the promotion of new and sustainable
« 14 »  At the same time, these existen- the Diversity and Modes forms of collaboration (as claimed in §1),
tial implications have repercussions on a the fundamental circularity of the scientist
theoretical level, loosening the “grasping at-
of Subjects’s Descriptions and the investigation of lived experience
titude” that is at the basis of the search for an Susanne Ravn need to be considered in an extended form
absolute metaphysical ground beyond the that:
University of Southern Denmark,
all-pervasive impermanence and emptiness ƒƒ involves methodological considerations
of phenomena. Michel Bitbol (2008, 2012) Denmark on how the samples of the “cases” (the
refers to this crucial aspect of Varela’s view sravn/at/health.sdu.dk subject’s experiences of a phenomenon/
as the “Varelian” or “neurophenomenologi- class of phenomenon) are selected and
cal” stance.3 This stance leads us to dissolve > Upshot • Varela’s description of how how relational conditions of the inter-
the so-called “hard problem” of conscious- first-, second- and third-person posi- view situation are handled;
ness (Chalmers 1995), by dismantling the tions are inserted in a network of so- ƒƒ clarifies the different communicative
foundationalist attitude that gives rise to it cial exchange forms a central ground modes that can be at play when opening
(see Bitbol & Antonova 2016: 355, Vörös for using a second-person position as up the lab to involve the lived experi-
2014: 104) and by experiencing the dis- a mediator in a phenomenological ex- ences of subjects in a direct and/or per-
solution of the subject-object duality (Pe- ploration of lived experiences. Based on formative way.
titmengin 2017: 145). In my opinion, this Martiny’s arguments that we should « 2 »  Firstly, Martiny presents an infor-
existential stance is a crucial component of expand the notion of the lab, I suggest mative account of how Francisco Varela,
Varela’s radical proposal and constitutes a that the fundamental circularity of the Evan Thompson and Elanor Rosch (VTR)
further dimension of its way of embodying scientist and the first-person experienc- (1991) find it necessary to go back to the
and opening up cognitive science. es investigated needs to be considered particularity of experiences as embodied
in an extended form when involving a and lived by the subject. Subsequently, he
Andrea Pace Giannotta obtained his PhD in Philosophy second-person method taking place in argues for the necessity of expanding the
from the University of Florence in 2016. His main topics the conditions of the world of everyday notion of the lab and involving explorations
of investigation encompass phenomenology, philosophy life. of phenomena as they unfold in and as part
of mind and philosophy of perception. His research of the world of everyday life. In that sense,
focuses on genetic phenomenology, 4E cognition, « 1 »  Kristian Martiny’s target article Varela’s insistence on including thorough
neurophenomenology and phenomenal intentionality. about ways to conduct cognitive science exploration of first-person methodolo-
does not only present a very welcome over- gies in cognitive sciences is aimed at being
Received: 21 October 2017 view of Francisco Varela’s proposals on how radically extended by involving the second-
Accepted: 25 October 2017 to open up and develop the way in which person method of interviewing. Pursuing
cognitive science is performed. He also, in this aim, Martiny, however briefly, makes a
the second part of the article, argues for reference to Bent Flyvbjerg’s work. Without
how to use interviews – or “second-per- embarking on a further description of Flyv- 81
son methods” to generate descriptions of berg’s methodological discussions, it seems
experiences as lived. As my own research fair to ask for considerations of the strate-
is based in the interdisciplinary field(s) gies of the enquiry when dealing with “the
of combining short-term ethnographical detailed examination of a single example
fieldwork/qualitative research methodolo- (or case) of a class of phenomena” (Flyvb-
gies with phenomenological analysis, in the jerg 2011: 301). Flyvbjerg very explicitly
following, I will primarily focus on outlin- connects the characteristics of the design of
ing interdisciplinary considerations related such a study to how the different types of
to the latter part of Martiny’s article. Draw- design influence the way results of analysis
ing on the manner in which first-, second- can be interpreted and contribute to general
and third-person positions are described theoretical knowledge. Absolutely central to
3 |  The Varelian stance also leads us to high- as inserted in a network of social exchange his work, and of specific relevance for the
light the anti-foundationalist and anti-metaphys- – and change – in Varela and Jonathan ambition of combining the second-person
ical orientation of the original enactive approach Shear’s article (1999), I will specifically fo- method with phenomenological analysis, is
of EM, in contrast to some contemporary forms cus on how the use of the second-person that Flyvbjerg presents four different strat-
of “domesticated enactivism” (Vörös, Froese & position constructively mediates explora- egies related to the information-oriented
Riegler 2016: 198) that are characterized by a tions of the circulation that unfold between selection of cases (all quotes are from Fly-
“shift towards realism” (ibid: 194). first- and third-person descriptions of phe- vbjerg 2011: 307):

http://constructivist.info/13/1/059.martiny

You might also like