You are on page 1of 13

Home

Back to "articles"

[Originally published as in Building and Dwelling [Bauen und Wohnen],


edited by Eduard Führ. Munich, Germany: Waxmann Verlag GmbH; New
York: Waxmann, 2000, pp. 189-202; to see other articles in this
collection, which originally appeared on the Web, go to:
http://www.theo.tu-
cottbus.de/Wolke/eng/Subjects/982/Seamon/seamon_t.html

Concretizing Heidegger's Notion of


Dwelling:
The Contributions of Thomas Thiis-
Evensen And
Christopher Alexander
David Seamon

In “Building Dwelling Thinking,” phenomenological philosopher Martin


Heidegger discusses the notion of dwelling and contends that “only if we
are capable of dwelling, only then can we build” (Heidegger, 1971, p.
160). A major problem with dwelling as an idea is its lack of specificity,
particularly in terms of design significance. This article argues that the
work of two architects--Thomas Thiis-Evensen and Christopher Alexander
—indicates important but different ways in which Heidegger’s dwelling
can be translated into more grounded architectural meaning. Thiis-
Evensen and Alexander's ideas, placed in a Heideggerian framework,
point toward a way of thinking that might lead to the kind of
dwelling‑building relationship suggested by Heidegger when he writes that
"to build is already to dwell" (ibid., p. 146).

DWELLING AND BUILDING


In “Building Dwelling Thinking,” Heidegger's major means of
investigation is etymological: what is the word history of "to build"
(“bauen”) and its links to dwelling? Bauen, says Heidegger, relates to
nearness and neighborliness and also implies "to cherish and protect, to
preserve and care for" (ibid., p. 147). Bauen also relates to the old High
German word for building, “baun,” which means “to dwell” in the sense
of remaining or staying in place.
In emphasizing this link to place, Heidegger suggests that building relates
to dwelling, which therefore can be said to involve a sense of continuity,
community, and at-homeness (Harries, 1983). The crux of dwelling,
Heidegger argues, is sparing and preserving--the kindly concern for land,
things, creatures, and people as they are and as they can become (ibid., p.
149; Zimmerman, 1983). As human beings, we cannot fail to dwell, for
dwelling, ultimately, is the essential existential core of human being-in-
the-world from which there is no escape.

At the same time, dwelling is just as much a means as an end. There will
always be a certain tension, a kind of imperfection, between what we
wish, do, and make. The significant questions are how do we dwell in our
own particular situations and how can we shape the quality of our
dwelling for better or worse? Heidegger links the quality of our dwelling
to the quality of our building, since an effective building arises from a
genuine sense of sparing and preserving (see Foltz, 1995, pp. 159-63).

Heidegger also argues that, in practical terms, dwelling involves the


gathering of the fourfold--the coming together of earth, sky, people, and a
sense of spiritual reverence, or "the gods," as he signifies higher realities
(ibid.). In this sense, dwelling is no mere extension of existential space or
place; rather, "it becomes itself the fundamental human activity, in the
light of which both place and space find their first clarification" (Jager,
1983, p. 154). As Heidegger interprets dwelling, the built environment is
crucial because it supports and reflects a person and group's way of being-
in-the-world. The built environment is a certain embodied grasp of the
world, a particular way of taking up the body and the world, a specific
orientation disclosing certain aspects of a worldly horizon (ibid.,
pp. 154‑155). The world in which we find ourselves completes us in what
we are, and therefore the specific nature of the built environment becomes
crucial.

In other words, people are immersed in their world, and this immersion is
qualitative, subtle—in many ways, ineffable. Thus a walk through a
well‑tended garden evokes a different state of being than a similar walk
through an uncared‑for garden or an unsightly vacant lot. Similarly,
entering a church evokes a different human stance than entering a
nightclub or a shopping mall or an empty street or a street filled with
human activity. One aim for aim for architects is to become sensitive to
these experiences and to become more aware of how specific qualities of
the built environment enhance or stymie particular human experiences.

Heidegger argues that, in our modern age, human dwelling is reduced and
so, therefore, is building. His explication of why we dwell less fully today
is complicated; he suggests that, in part, it is because we manipulate and
demand from our world rather than meet it an attitude of sparing and
preserving‑‑i.e., allowing it to be and become. In this sense, a key to
dwelling is letting ourselves and the world be, and this letting‑be includes
the ways we build, see, understand, and think.

It is this need for letting‑be in designing and understanding that marks the
value of Thiis-Evensen and Alexander's work for a deeper, more
grounded, understanding of dwelling. Both architects seek concrete means
for identifying and describing built qualities that sustain and strengthen
the quality of dwelling. Through evoking one style of sparing and
preserving, Thiis-Evensen and Alexander provide ways to see and think
more clearly, which, in turn, might lead to better designing and building.

A PHENOMENOLOGY OF ARCHITECTURAL FORM


Norwegian architect Thomas Thiis-Evensen's Archetypes in Architecture
goes far in developing a language of architectural elements as they have
relation to dwelling (Thiis-Evensen 1987).1 Thiis-Evensen's aim is to
understand "the universality of architectural expression" (ibid., 8). His
vehicle is what he calls architectural archetypes—“the most basic
elements of architecture," which for Thiis-Evensen can be identified as the
floor, wall, and roof (ibid.). Thiis-Evensen argues that these three
architectural elements are not arbitrary but, rather, are common to all
historical and cultural traditions. The essential existential ground of floor,
wall, and roof, he argues, is the relationship between inside and outside.
Just by being what they are, the floor, wall, and roof automatically create
an inside in the midst of an outside, though in different ways: the floor,
through above and beneath; the wall, through within and around; and the
roof, through over and below.

Using examples from architectural history as evidence, Thiis-Evensen


argues that any building can be interpreted experientially in terms of these
three archetypes. His main purpose is to describe the kinds of
environmental and architectural experience that different variations of
floor, wall, and roof sustain and presuppose. The result, he claims, is "a
common language of [architectural] form which we can immediately
understand, regardless of individual or culture" (ibid., 17).

Thiis-Evensen demonstrates that a building’s relative degree of insideness


or outsideness in regard to floor, wall, and roof can be clarified through
motion, weight, and substance—the three “existential expressions of
architecture” (ibid., p. 21). By motion, he means the architectural
element's sense of dynamism or inertia--that is, whether the element seems
to expand, to contract, or to rest in balance. Weight involves the sense of
heaviness or lightness of the element and how it relates to gravity. Last,
substance relates to the material sense of the element--whether it is soft or
hard, coarse or fine, warm or cold, and so forth.

In broadest terms, the central question Thiis-Evensen asks in Archetypes


is, “How do floor, wall, and roof express insideness and outsideness
through motion, weight, and substance?” The relationship between
insideness and outsideness has, in fact, received considerable attention in
phenomenological research on environmental and architectural experience
(e.g., Chaffin 1989, Dovey 1985, Mugerauer 1991, Mugerauer, 1994,
Seamon 1991, Silverstein 1991), especially in geographer Edward Relph's
phenomenology of place (Relph 1976), which demonstrates that insideness
is the hallmark quality transforming space into place and sustaining the
deepest sense of dwelling. One of Thiis-Evensen's contributions is to
illustrate ways in which architecture contributes to insideness and
outsideness and therefore grounds a sense of dwelling.

Thiis-Evensen emphasizes that different architectural styles and cultural


traditions may interpret the inside-outside dialectic through different
degrees of openness and closure (for example, the medieval fortress's
impenetrable walls versus the Renaissance palace's walls of many
windows). Regardless of the particular stylistic or cultural expression,
however, floors, walls, and roofs provide related results in that they shape
an insideness in the midst of outsideness so that the individual and group
can dwell. In addition, varying physical qualities of floors, walls, and
roofs lead to different experiences of motion, weight, and substance. The
result is an intricate set of tensions between architectural elements and
architectural experience:

What is it that the roof, the floor and the wall do? As a motion,
the roof rises or falls. The walls stand up or sink, the floor spreads
out, climbs or descends. In this way, weight is also implied. That
which rises is light, that which falls is heavy. And if the roof is
bright and soft as a sail, it is open. If it is dark and of stone, it is
closed. If the openings in a wall are tall and narrow, they ascend, if
they are short and wide, they sink. A soft and fine floor is warm
and open, but if it is hard and coarse, it closes and is heavy ( ibid.,
23).

THE WALL AND WINDOW AS EXAMPLES


In the three main sections of Archetypes, Thiis-Evensen examines the
ways through motion, weight, and substance that floors, walls, and roofs
express insideness and outsideness. This work marks the start toward a
descriptive language delineating the invariant elements of the built
environment that have significance for human experience and dwelling.

One example is Thiis-Evensen's explication of the wall, which, of the


three archetypes, he shows to reconcile most potently the relationship
between inside and outside, since it is by way of the wall that one "passes
through" between exterior and interior, either physically or visually
through doors and windows. The wall resolves the existential tension
between inside and outside in two ways: either the wall draws exterior
space inside, or the wall draws interior space outside. In turn, this degree
of penetration from inside to outside or vice versa can vary: on one hand,
there can be complete openness and invitation; on the other hand, there
can be complete closure and rejection.

One way in which the wall expresses this dialectic between openness and
closure is through its windows, which are said by Thiis-Evensen to
contribute to a building's sense of inside and outside in that they announce
the mode of life within the building. Windows are "always an expression
of the interior to the world at large" (ibid., 251):

While the door is determined by its relation to what is outside,


the window is the symbol of what is inside. Just like the eye, it
expresses the interior's outlook over exterior space.... (ibid.).

Thiis-Evensen points out that a window is much more than a wall


opening: a window that is only a gaping hole makes the wall "a lifeless
skin around a dead and empty interior" (ibid., 259). In clarifying how
windows actually give life to a building, he examines the parts of a
window‑-the opening, the face in the opening, and the frame around the
opening. He then considers how each of these components contributes to a
sense of insideness and outsideness.

For example, the frame of a window is important because it makes a


setting for the inside space and brings it toward the viewer on the outside.
If the window has no frame, the outside forces its way in. The frame is
important, therefore, because it leads the inside out. This "leading out"
occurs in varying ways, depending on what parts of the frame‑-sill, lintel,
and jambs‑-are emphasized or deemphasized (figure 1). If all its parts are
emphasized (a in figure 1), then the entire interior space seems to reach
outward. On the other hand, if only the lintel is highlighted, then an
upward movement and roofs take precedence (b); or, if only the sill is
highlighted, a sinking movement and floors take precedence (c). In
addition, the sense of movement for a wall as a whole can be affected by
the arrangement of window frames (figures 2 & 3).
Figures 1, 2 & 3

Another important quality that relates to the window's sense of insideness


and outsideness is the shape of its opening for which Thiis-Evensen
identifies three variations‑-vertical (a in figure 4), horizontal (b), and
central (c). These different forms lead to different inside-outside
relationships, thus both vertical (a in figure 5) and central (b) windows
suggest a movement coming from inside out, while a horizontal window
(c) suggests an inside lateral movement that is separate from the person
outside.

Figures 4 & 5
In his explication of the floor, wall, and roof, Thiis-Evensen assumes that
there are various shared existential qualities‑-insideness-outsideness,
gravity-levity, coldness-warmth, and so forth‑-that mark the foundation of
architecture. Thus, a wall with windows whose lintels are emphasized
suggests a sense of upward movement and levity, just as a wall with
windows whose sills are emphasized will feel heavier and in relationship
to the ground. Or, if one studies the experienced qualities of stairs, one
realizes that narrow stairs typically relate to privacy and a faster ascent,
whereas wide stairs often relate to publicness, ceremony, and a slower
pace. Similarly, steep stairs express struggle and strength, isolation and
survival--experienced qualities that frequently lead to steep stairs' use as a
sacred symbol, as in Mayan temples or Rome's Scala Santa. On the other
hand, shallow stairs encourage a calm, comfortable pace and typically
involve secular use, as, for example, Michelangelo's steps leading up to
the Campidoglio of Rome's Capitoline Hill (ibid., 89-103).

Thiis-Evensen argues that his work has direct design implications. He


claims, that, too often, an architect's aesthetic sense is subjective because
he or she has not thoughtfully considered how architectural forms arise
from and translate themselves back into shared existential qualities like
motion, weight, substance, insideness, outsideness, permeability, closure,
and so forth. Thiis-Evensen believes that understanding the archetypes
“and their expressive potentialities is essential when [a design] vision is to
be turned into a realization" (ibid., 387). The result might be a building
whose formal qualities resonate with its practical needs. The possibility
becomes greater that human beings and their built world are reconciled
and the quality of dwelling strengthened.

CHRISTOPHER ALEXANDER AND PATTERN LANGUAGE


This reconciliation between people and their built world is also a major
aim in the research and design of American architect Christopher
Alexander, though he works at a different experiential scale than Thiis-
Evensen, who largely emphasizes lived qualities of individual buildings.
Alexander is more concerned with architecture in its larger environmental
context. In other words, how can activities, buildings, spaces, and
landscapes be designed in an integrated, coherent way to create places that
are coherent, beautiful, and alive for their residents and users? In short,
the aim is place making that sustains dwelling.

Like Thiis-Evensen, Alexander believes that architecture today often fails


both practically and aesthetically. He also believes that many built
environments of the past--for example, a city like Venice or Oxford, or a
building like Chartres Cathedral or a Japanese farmhouse--generally had a
sense of togetherness and harmony (Alexander, 1979). An important focus
of Alexander's work is how architectural parts belong together in a larger
environmental whole (Alexander, 1993). Alexander argues that, if an
environmental whole is made rightly, it has a powerful sense of place,
which may help people who live in and use that place to have more
satisfactory, vibrant lives.

In his work, Alexander seeks a way to return a sense of wholeness to the


buildings and environments of modern Western society. He emphasizes
that the crucial process is healing. Every new construction, whether
building or square or street furniture or window detail, must be made in
such a way as to heal the environment, where “heal” especially means
“make whole.” The obligation is that the thing built must work “to create
a continuous structure of wholes around itself” (Alexander 1987, p. 22).

The practical tool that Alexander develops to foster environmental wholes


and healing is "pattern language"--a conceptual method whereby the
layperson or designer can identify and visualize the underlying elements
and relationships in a built environment that foster a sense of place
(Alexander et al. 1977). In his master volume, Pattern Language (ibid.),
Alexander and colleagues identify 253 of these elements, or patterns, as
the are called. A pattern is both interpretive and prescriptive: first, it is a
description of a particular element of the built environment that
contributes to a sense of place (for example, "identifiable neighborhood"
[no. 14], "degrees of publicness " [36], "main gateways" [53], "high
places" [62], and "window place" [180]); second, it is a practical
instruction that suggests how to design the particular element effectively
(for example, in regard to "main gateways," "Mark every boundary in the
city which has important human meaning‑-the boundary of a building
cluster, a neighborhood, a precinct‑-by great gateways where the major
entering paths cross the boundary" [Alexander et al. 1977, p. 278]).

Alexander emphasizes, however, that successful places are always


composed of many interrelated patterns that work synergistically to create
a whole greater than the individual parts. To incorporate this wholeness in
pattern language, Alexander organizes the 253 patterns from larger to
smaller in three groups:

1. Patterns that describe larger-scale environments that cannot be


designed or built all at once (e.g., "community of 7,000," [12],
"shopping street" [32], "housing cluster" [37]);
2. Patterns that describe buildings and groups of buildings (e.g., "main
building" [99], "family of entrances" [102], "positive outdoor space"
[106]);
3. Patterns that describe individual building details (e.g., "structure
follows social spaces” [205], “columns at the corners” [212], “front
door bench” [242]).

Alexander argues that, for any new design problem, it is important to


write a pattern language that begins with larger patterns and then
incorporates smaller patterns. In this way, the larger qualities of
environmental wholeness are held in sight as smaller qualities are fitted
around them. He also emphasizes that the 253 patterns in Pattern
Language are illustrative and far from complete. New design problems
and environments may require revised patterns or even entirely new
patterns that the architect will need to create from scratch (e.g., Coates
and Seamon, 1993). In the end, pattern language is not a finished product
but an on-going process of dialogue among architect, client, user, builder,
and site. Pattern language is not a master list of unchangeable design
principles that must be incorporated in all buildings and places. Instead, it
is a way of looking at and thinking about buildings and environments so
that one can better understand how their parts might work together to
create a whole. As Alexander (1987, p. 16) explains,

Design must be premised on a process that has the creation of


wholeness as its overriding purpose, and in which every increment
of construction, no matter how small, is devoted to this purpose.
ASPECTS OF AN ARCHITECTURE OF DWELLING
Like Heidegger, both Thiis-Evensen and Alexander believe that the built
world can help illuminate and sustain essential qualities of human
understanding, life, and experience, though the two architects’ thinking is
somewhat different as to what these essential qualities are. Alexander
would no doubt appreciate Thiis-Evensen's effort to understand
architectural elements existentially, but he might ask that Thiis-Evensen
give more attention to how individual archetypes join together into a
larger sense of human meaning, environment, and place. For example,
Alexander would probably accept Thiis-Evensen's interpretation of the
way that architectural qualities support a sense of insideness and
outsideness, but he would also emphasize that these architectural qualities
are of little use if they do not contribute to the building's wider sense of
place.

To understand more clearly this difference between Alexander and Thiis-


Evensen, we can consider one example‑-windows, to which both writers
devote considerable attention but in different ways. In Pattern Language,
Alexander includes several patterns dealing with windows and, in each,
they work in such as way as to involve people more directly with their
place. For example, the pattern "windows overlooking life" (no. 192)
insists that the building, through its windows, have direct visual or
physical relationship with the surroundings so that there will be a
connection between inside and outside. Similarly, the pattern "window
place" (no. 180) says that:

Everyone loves window seats, bay windows, and big windows with
low sills and comfortable chairs drawn up to them....Therefore, in
every room where you spend any length of time during the day,
make at least one window into a "window place" (Alexander 1977,
p. 834, p. 837).

This pattern particularly well illustrates Alexander's emphasis on how


buildings work as networks of behaviors and experiences. When people
enter a room with a window, Alexander argues, they typically experience
two forces: first, they are drawn toward the light; second, they want to
rest and be comfortable. A window seat automatically resolves these two
forces, and a space is transformed into a place where one can both sit
comfortably and enjoy the light.

In pattern language, Alexander uses the term density to describe the


multivalent meaning of the built environment. He explains that "many
patterns overlap in the same physical space: the building is very dense; it
has many meanings captured in a small space; and through this density it
becomes profound" (ibid., p. xli). A simple example of density is the
"window place" pattern, which, in terms of Thiis-Evensen’s motion,
weight, and substance, could be said to gather and reconcile darkness-
light and movement-rest. By incorporating a "lighted place to be
comfortable," a room becomes more meaningful and dense than if it
included either a "lighted place" or "place to rest" alone.

Unlike Alexander, Thiis-Evensen does not consider how windows work


as a significant locus of activity. Instead, he speaks of the window largely
in terms of its formal existential expression. In other words, how, by its
specific size, shape, and physical arrangement, does a window allow the
interior and exterior of a building to speak or not to speak to the world
beyond?

Thiis-Evensen’s emphasis on how formal architectural qualities are


experienced does not mean that Alexander is more complete in his
existential understanding of architecture than Thiis-Evensen. Rather, these
differences in approach and scale point toward the considerable variety of
ways in which the built environment can contribute order and pattern to
human life. One can imagine a continuum of architectural and
environmental meaning that runs, on one end, from the pure architectural
element to, on the other end, complex aggregations of buildings, spaces
and environments that evoke a powerful sense of place. A thorough
architectural and environmental phenomenology would delineates this full
range of architectural and environmental experience and considers how
qualities of the natural, built, and human worlds contribute to a sense of
place and environmental wholeness.

In this sense, both Thiis-Evensen and Alexander’s theories of architecture


and place are a major contribution to clarifying Heidegger’s cryptic
statement cited at the start of this article—“Only if we are capable of
dwelling, only then can we build.” The work of both architects helps us
better to dwell because they help us better to see one part of our world—
the way that architecture can contribute to human being-in-the-world. In
different ways, both architects seek a virtuous circle in which people and
world, thinking and designing, designing and building are all mutually
supportive. In this sense, Heidegger would no doubt cheer these works,
seeing them as a pragmatic complement to the larger philosophical
questions that he reopens in his own writings.

NOTE
1. Thiis-Evensen's book is a rewritten version of his 1982 doctoral
dissertation done under the direction of Norwegian architect and
architectural theorist Christian Norberg-Schulz, one of the major figures in
developing a phenomenology of architecture and environment. Though
not discussed here, Norberg-Schulz's work also draws centrally on
Heidegger’s thinking and is another major contribution to grounding
Heidegger’s notion of dwelling practically. See Norberg-Schulz, 1971,
1980, 1985, 1988.

REFERENCES
Alexander, C., 1987. A New Theory of Urban Design. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Alexander, C., 1993. A Foreshadowing of 21st Century Art: The Color
and Geometry of Very Early Turkish Carpets. NY: Oxford
University Press.
Alexander, C., Ishikawa, S., & Silverstein, M. 1977. A Pattern
Language. New York: Oxford University Press.
Chaffin, V. F. 1989. Dwelling and Rhythm: The Isle Brevelle as a
Landscape of Home. Landscape Journal, 7: 96-106.
Coates, G. J., and Seamon, D., 1993. Promoting a Foundational Ecology
Practically Through Christopher Alexander’s Pattern Language: The
Example of Meadowcreek. In D. Seamon, ed., Dwelling, Seeing,
and Designing. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 331-54.
Dovey, K. l985. Home and homelessness. In I. Altman & C. M. Werner
eds., Home Environments. New York: Plenum, pp. 33-64.
Foltz, B. V., 1995. Inhabiting the Earth: Heidegger, Environmental
Ethics, and the Metaphysics of Nature. Atlantic Highlands, NJ:
Humanities Press.
Harries, K. 1983. Thoughts on a Non‑Arbitrary Architecture. Perspecta,
20, 9‑20; reprinted in Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing, D. Seamon,
ed. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 41-59.
Heidegger, Martin, 1971. Poetry, Language, Thought. New York: Harper
and
Row.
Jager, Bernd, 1983. Theorizing and the Elaboration of Place: Inquiry into
Galileo and Freud, in A. Giorgi, A. Barton, and C. Maes, eds.,
Duquesne Studies in Phenomenological Psychology, vol. 4.
Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, pp. 153‑180.
Mugerauer, R. 1993. Toward an Architectural Vocabulary: The Porch as
a Between. In D. Seamon, ed., Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing.
Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 103-28.
Mugerauer, R., 1994. Interpretations on Behalf of Place. Albany, NY:
SUNY Press.
Norberg-Schulz, C. 1971. Existence, Space, and Architecture. New York:
Praeger.
Norberg‑Schulz, C. 1980. Genius Loci: Toward a Phenomenology of
Architecture. New York: Rizzoli.
Norberg‑Schulz, C. 1985. The Concept of Dwelling: On the Way to a
Figurative Architecture. New York: Rizzoli.
Norberg-Schulz, C. 1988. Architecture: Meaning and Place. New
York: Rizzoli.
Relph, E., 1976. Place and Placelessness. London: Pion.
Seamon, D., 1979. A Geography of the Lifeworld. New York:
St. Martin's.
Seamon, D., 1982. The Phenomenological Contribution to Environmental
Psychology. Journal of Environmental Psychology, 2, 119‑140.
Seamon, D., l987. Phenomenology and Environment‑behavior Research.
In G. T. Moore and E. Zube (Eds.), Advances in Environment,
Behavior and Design, vol. l. New York: Plenum, pp. 3-27.
Seamon, D., 1989. Humanistic and Phenomenological Advances in
Environmental Design. The Humanistic Psychologist 17 (Autumn),
280-293.
Seamon, D., 1991. Awareness and Reunion: A Phenomenology of the
Person-Environment Relationship as Portrayed in the New York
Photographs of André Kertész, in Place Images in the Media, L.
Zonn (ed.). Totowa, New Jersey: Roman and Littlefield, pp. 87-
107.
Seamon, D., ed., 1993. Dwelling, Seeing and Building: Toward a
Phenomenological Ecology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.
Seamon, D. & Mugerauer, R., eds., 1985. Dwelling, Place and
Environment: Towards a Phenomenology of Person and World.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Silverstein, M., 1993. The First Roof: Interpreting a Spatial Pattern. In D.
Seamon, ed., Dwelling, Seeing, and Designing: Toward a
Phenomenological Ecology. Albany, NY: SUNY Press, pp. 77-101.
Thiis-Evensen, T., 1987. Archetypes in Architecture. Oslo: Norwegian
University Press.
Zimmerman, M. 1983. Toward a Heideggerian Ethos for Rational
Environmentalism. Environmental Ethics, 5, 99‑131.

Back to top

You might also like