You are on page 1of 10

AMDG John Brodeur The Problems of Evolution Book Report For Professor Matthew McCann Survey of Physical Science

PHY 105 2 December 2008

The controversy of evolution seems to be over. Most scientists and educators of our day simply overlook the questions it left unanswered. Evolution is taught in schools as if it were a law. Almost every relevant modern theory of science presupposes the evolutionary theory as the origin of species. Very few dare challenge it; it has become as much a reality to most students as the law of gravity. The great debate appears to have ended. The only substantial quarrels still raging are heralded by a select few creationist extremists who refuse to argue with scientific or philosophical ideas. As far as science goes, evolution has been proven or has it? Despite the breadth and development of the theory of evolution over the years, there are still intricate questions which have remained unanswered to this day. It seems common practice these days to leave these questions unaddressed, to learn only the working elements of the theory of evolution. I have always taken a personal interest in these overlooked scientific problems of evolution, and I found it fitting to designate this second book report to this interest. The book I have selected to accomplish this task was written by Mark Ridley and is entitled The Problems of Evolution. As I have read through it, I have marveled at its uniquely objective approach which seeks philosophical logical answers over superficial ones. By the report I have provided below, I hope not only to peak the readers interest, but to encourage an intellectual engagement in the controversy of evolution which is, as Ridley makes clear, far from over. In the preface of his work, Ridley states that his goal in writing this book has been to set forth the problems of evolution which are timeless and investigate the merits which those problems bring forth. Ridley desires not only to address modern controversy but all controversy which is fundamental to a true understanding of the evolutionary theory. The book is modeled after a similar book by Bertrand Russell. However, as Ridley points out, science must be differently approached than a book grounded in Platonic philosophy; it must necessarily seek real tenable answers; it cannot leave open questions unanswered. Many things, Ridley concedes, can be known and asserted as facts in science (such as the science of genetics), and these are the very things which frame what Ridley calls a set of Great Questions in evolutionary biology. These Great Questions are the very controversy which science must continually strive to answer. Some have been addressed and/or answered more effectively than others, and Ridley makes it a point to proceed in sequence from the most concretely answered to the least explored. In this way, Ridley begins his book on the problems of evolution. The first question Ridley asks is whether or not evolution is true. The unanimity of biologists, he remarks, should not be overlooked when answering such a question, nor should it be taken for granted. Both common sense and the

authorities of history and modernity give witness to the immutability of species. The arguments which can be pitted against these two authorities are those which choose between evolution and the fixity of species. In recognizing this, Ridley asserts that there are three possible theories to consider which are defined by two questions: 1) whether species are immutable and 2) how many independent origins of life there have been. In the case of evolution (Figure 1c), all species would have descended from a single common ancestral series, diversifying through a period of time and originating all at once. The diversity of species would have necessarily resulted from a splitting of the species. If it was the case that species do change but that life originated more than once, a second possible theory is born. Akin to the theory of Lamarck is this theory that life has originated as many times as there are modern species and that in each case the species has evolved but never split. This hypothesis is known as transformism (Figure 1b). A last hypothesis is more akin to a creationist approach wherein all species have looked the same in the past and that all of them have separate origins; this is termed separate creation by Ridley (Figure 1a).

Figure 1 The three kinds of evidence Ridley uses to test these theories are 1) observation of evolution on a small scale, 2) the argument from classification, and 3) the fossil record. The best is the first of these. Evolution has indeed been observed in both natural and artificial conditions. The peppered moth example which Ridley elaborates upon demonstrates that a new generation which is different from its ancestor can be produced by selective breeding. In any way experimentation is done in this manner, the outcome will always favor either evolution or transformism. It will not and cannot favor separate creation. It has been proven time and time again that, especially in the fields of agriculture and horticulture, new species come about in both the morphological and reproductive interpretation of origin. Hybridization, then, seemingly destroys the hypothesis of separate creation, and reasserts the common sense that species are not immutable. Gradual changes in a species, particularly as illustrated by the many gradations of the herring gull, could not possibly be accounted for by individual

creation. The idea of separate creation would ultimately lead to the conclusion that every individual is created separately because each differs from the other in some way, and this is simply not the case as we know the natural reproductive methods by which creatures are born to the world. To check this idea would be to assert that evolution takes place up to a certain point in the Linnaean hierarchy, but because the degrees of difference are continuous, the point at which evolution stops and separate creation begins creates an immediate paradox: if evolution could produce all changes up to that point, why could it not produce the small alteration between these next two levels? The philosophical principle of uniformitarianism, the principle that an observed process over a short time could have operated for longer to produce proportionately longer effects, is necessarily applied here. Just as in all of science, uniformatarianism is the logical assumption which makes this conclusion credible. Now that the theory of separate creation has been ruled out, the theory of transformism needs to be addressed; although Ridley has proven that species are not fixed in form, he has yet to show that they all share a common ancestor. The first proof of a common ancestor comes from the observation of hierarchical classification. Although it is true that any set of objects can be classified hierarchically, the method by which the Linnaean hierarchy is constructed is special because it involves traits known as homologies. Homologies are traits that are similar between species, but do not have to be because of functional necessity. A striking example of this homology is found in the resemblance of a mammals ear-bone to the jaw-bone of reptiles. The fact that species share homologous structures with other species is a strong case for evolution. This same argument was the chief argument of Darwins own example of the Galapagos finches. The genetic code, according to Ridley, is by far the greatest argument of homology: every organism is made up of the hereditary material known as DNA. In each strand is a sequence made up of four bases symbolized by the letters A, C, G, and T. In every amino acid there is a triplet of these bases, and in every protein, there is a sequence of these amino acids. The homological wonder here is that for every organism, the code is the same. Just like a language, the sequence need not represent the same thing in each organism; the combination GGC could mean one thing in one organism and something different in another, but this is not the case it means the same in every organism, namely glycine. This observation severely weakens the theories of separate creation and transformism. The third and last argument for evolution is the fossil record. Ridley admits in this argument that the record of evolutionary change within single lineages is very poor. If evolution were true, one would expect to find more changes in the

fossil record; the rarity of fossils can most definitely be a deterrent to this argument on a local level. If one were to observe the fossil record as a whole, however, he would take notice of the importance of sequence in the fossil record. When one observes the sequence of vertebrates, he will find first fish, then amphibians, then reptiles, and then mammals, a clear sequence of more mammal-like reptiles in the order which evolution would necessarily proceed. Worth noting is the lack of any real breach of sequence throughout the entire fossil record. If there were to be such a breach it would throw much of the theory of evolution into question, but as it is situated thus, evolutionary descent looks at worst probable. It seems much too great a coincidence that these forms would follow this sequence. The idea that environmental conditions caused changes in the groups present over time appears as a very forced argument, although difficult to dispute decisively. This argument, spear-headed by Lyell, is weak not so much by its own logic but in-so-far as the separate creation theory which it supports has already been proven false. At the end of these discussions, Ridley asserts that there is consequently no sensible alternative to evolution, and that, insofar as whether or not evolution is true, the answer is fairly clear. From this extensive analysis of the necessity of evolution, a myriad of other questions emerges, not least of which is the question which seeks the proper relation of the evolutionary theory to the classification system. Ridley points out that the strongest possible relation is one of practical necessity, one in which evolution must precede the classification in order to give it structure. However, as Ridley points out, this is simply not the case. History saw classification long before the theory of evolution. The act of classification, after all, is a simple process which merely requires its groups to be recognized, defined, and named resulting in different traits defining different groups. However, a fundamental flaw in classification is its tendency toward subjectivity; if classification was truly a subjective practice alone, not only would evolution be practically unnecessary, it would be completely unnecessary. The way to check this subjective germ in classification is to classify with the aid of a perfectly unambiguous principle. In this case no group would be chosen unless it is in reference to the principle. With the introduction of this idea, Ridley asserts that evolution could fit into one of three categories in relation to classification: 1) philosophically necessary, 2) philosophically desirable, and 3) completely unnecessary. The hierarchy of classification can be assumed; this means that one group will necessarily be contained completely in more inclusive groups without overlap. According to Ridley, two hierarchical principles exist. They are: 1) a phenetic hierarchy, one which is governed by the similarity of form of the classified group, and 2) a phylogenic hierarchy, one which is governed by the pattern of evolutionary

descent. Both principles may agree or disagree as is illustrated in Figure 2. In (a) both agree in classification because the rate of evolution is approximately constant in direction and divergent. This agreement is not present in the case of convergence (b) or significant differential divergence (c).

Figure 2 Before beginning his discussion on both principles individually, Ridley reminds the reader that if both principles are valid, evolution would merely be philosophically desirable; if however, only the phylogenic principle is valid, then evolution would be philosophically necessary. If however, both principles are invalid, evolution would be completely unnecessary and classification would be a completely and utterly subjective practice which bore no relation to evolution at all.

Ridley begins his discussion of the phenetic principle by recalling the difficulty of classification by an arbitrarily chosen trait. The phenetic principle, as he points out, is much indebted to numerical taxonomy in order to compensate for this arbitration. It classifies not by single traits, but as many traits as possible. This is most handsomely illustrated by a certain statistic known as the multivariate cluster statistic in which groups are defined by their overall morphological similarity. The more traits used, the less arbitrary the arbitration. The statistical clusters are formed by what has been termed as the distance between the units being classified. This distance is the difference between the values of a trait in two given groups. Because numerical taxonomy uses more than one trait, the distance which forms the clusters is often a mean trait distance; it takes the sum of all trait distances and divides the result by the number of traits. As such, the classification of the phenetic principle is the hierarchical output of the statistical data. The advantages which such a hierarchical output claims are objectivity and repeatability, but, as Ridley explains, this claim is tainted. Drawing on the insight of L. A. S. Johnson, Ridley explains how there can actually be more than one cluster statistic for any set of traits because there is a plurality of ways in recognizing the distance between groups. In other words, there is no principle guiding which cluster statistics should be used. The principle of numerical taxonomy provides no additional guidelines for the use of certain cluster statistics; there is no way to differentiate a better cluster from a worse one. The decision becomes one contingent on personal preference and therefore fails to live up to its objective claim. The phenetic principle is in fact still a subjective approach to classification. In the failure of the phenetic principle, Ridley turns to phylogeny. What makes the principle of phylogeny so refreshing is the observation that its hierarchy exists independently of our techniques to measure it. The hierarchy is unique and not pluralistic as with the phonetic principle. The criteria are more certain: there either is either a common ancestor between two species or there is not; there is no room for subjective choice. The immediate problem here is that it is impossible for phylogenetic relations to be discovered by direct observation because evolution is an historical phenomenon. Rather than discovered, they must be inferred. The means of inference as proposed by Hennig is to seek traits which are evolutionary innovations. This involves determining whether a given trait is an earlier or a later evolutionary stage, a primitive or derived trait. Any given trait can be both primitive and derived at once; with respect to later stage traits, it is primitive and with respect to earlier traits, it is considered derived. One can also use a method known as outgroup comparison which examines the state of some related species known as the outgroup. In this method, the outgroup is a species no more closely

related to either of the two species being compared. Any trait found in the outgroup would be considered primitive. It is not a foolproof method, as some shared traits are due to convergence, but in most cases, shared traits are most often due to common ancestry. In each of the methods presented lies the fundamental problem that we need to know the classification before applying the techniques, while it is the very technique we must use to discover the classification. While this seems like a paradox, Ridley suggests that it is simply the common practice of testing a theory. An example of this hypothesis testing is exhibited in Figure 3 wherein the outgroup comparison is used by successive approximation. In (a), five species are classified together, and it is hypothesized that (6) is less related to them than they are to each other. When trait A is compared in all six species, it is found that 2, 3, and 4 have it in the form of a while species 1 and 5 have it in the form of a. Using the method of outgroup comparison, we can reason that a is a derived state. Figure 3b has been adjusted to accommodate for this discovery. Now, species 1 and 5 are classified together because of their shared derived a trait, and the relation s between the other four species remain unknown until the procedure can be repeated with new evidence of shared traits.

Figure 3 The method illustrated above employs what Ridley describes as successive approximation. As the analysis develops, errors found in the original assumptions are proven or disproven so as to minimize error along the way. With the consequences of false assumptions removed, the classification moves closer and closer to its most perfect form. In this way, classification is a classic case of scientific theory-building. Rigorous adherence and alteration as a result of the

interpretation of facts constantly and consistently aids the accuracy of classification. Despite the apparent perfection of the phylogeny principle, Ridley makes is not satisfied with it as such. He insists its imperfections are manifold. The first problem he points out is how to resolve conflicting information from different traits. Despite this, Ridley illustrates that its imperfection does not render it impractical. As he himself says, few biologists would deny the cladistic evidence that humans share a more recent common ancestor with chimps than butterflies. The other difficulties of phylogeny arise from the fact that traits continually change in time and in place. This change is impossible to accurately classify because classification itself strictly applies only to one place and not to members from more than one geological period. Again, Ridley clarifies that this problem is not one in practice but one in philosophy; it does not completely void phylogenys usefulness in classification. Lastly, Ridley addresses the temptation one might feel to account phylogeny as a form of phonetic classification. While there is some element of truth in that, Ridley asserts that the represented hierarchy, not the techniques employed, are what properly describe a classification system. While both phonetic and phylogeny principles use shared traits as a technique, phylogenys objective principle is significantly better than the subjective quality of phonetic classification. In the end, phylogeny has been aptly proven philosophically preferable to its counterpart. Ridley answers his question as to the relation between evolution and classification by asserting they are actually quite close, so close indeed that it must be one of philosophical necessity. Herein lays a great underlying irony: evolution is not practically necessary to classification, but it is philosophically necessary. Ridley then proceeds to finish his work with a last discussion on macro-evolution, what he considers the most open-ended question of all the evolutionary theory. It is clear by the end of the work that despite the necessity of evolution which he asserts in Chapter 1, we lack evidence to support an opinionated conclusion (vi). Ridley was a joy to read and a very stimulating writer. He has quite a skill in the clarity of his words and in the communication of his ideas. Most of the questions he asks are enough to make the reader reconsider his own position in both extremes. Because of this, I find his book to be something of a hidden treasure. I would recommend it to anyone seriously considering the controversy of evolution, but I would also refrain from recommending it to anyone looking for concrete answers as to the reality of evolution. Although it was scientifically static, it was philosophically thrilling, and I am very glad to have read it.

Bibliography Ridley, Mark. The Problems of Evolution. New York: Oxford University Press, 1985.

You might also like